2024/02/12

Advaita Vedanta An Introduction Arvind Sharma

Advaita Vedanta An Introduction Arvind Sharma MLBD | PDF



====
Arvind Sharma, Advaita Vedänta. An Introduction, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 2004, pp. vii+125. ISBN 81-208-2027-4, Rs 295.00
Reviewed by Kazimieras Seibutis
Sri Aurobindo Cultural Center, Vilnius

Any book about such a challenging matter as Advaita Vedänta is fascinating, therefore it is no wonder that reading a short introduction on the subject by Arvind Sharrna is an exciting experience indeed, not only because the author manages to avoid getting involved in conflicting aspects of different schools of classical intellectual trend of India that is not yet widely known in the West, but also because the subject matter is presented in a condensed and very succinct manner.

Sharma, Birks Professor of Comparative Religion at McGill University, attempts to overcome this challenge by consistently relying on three approaches: scriptural, rational and experiential.

Sharma says that he "tries to accord an independent status to each of these approaches without losing sight of their interconnectedness".

In a short preface prior to the analysis, Sharma calls the readers' attention to a fundamental fact that in the West philosophy represents an intellectual movement which has achieved an independent status by shaking off constrains of theology. 
Meanwhile, within the framework of Indian culture such a divergence between philosophy and religion did not occur, and according to Sharma "the two, even when they become dual, remain undivided." Sharma also draws attention to the concept of jivanmukti and the pivotal idea, which supports the concept of jivanmukti, that the results of one's faith can be attained while still living in this world. 
Sharma goes on saying that according to this notion faith is understood as "faith pending realization — it denotes the trust one must have in order to undertake an experiment, but the outcome of the experiment is independent of such a faith".
In view of this, while toting to define ultimate reality or Brahman, Advaita Vedänta is relying not only on revelation and reason, but also on the teachings of those who achieved the state ofjivanmukti and became jivanmuktas or living embodiments of Brahman.

In the first chapter devoted to a scriptural approach, the author mainly discusses the scriptural authority of Upanisads and the hermeneutical attempts of Advaita Vedänta in a unified way to interpret and harmonize four key statements called mahäväkyas. These are accepted as the authority by other schools of Vedanta as well, but they interpret them using a rather different exegetical clue. Each of the four mahäväkyas has been given a detailed analysis in separate subsections.
Sharma stresses that acceptance of Vedic authority is not as binding for philosophical purposes as it is for social cohesion.

The second chapter explains the subtleties of the rational approach. Using classical examples of a bracelet of silver and silver (rüpyakundalanyäya) and of a rope and a snake (rajjusarpanyäya), the author compares doctrines of Asatkäryaväda and Satkäryaväda. He emphasizes that for a rational presentation of Advaitic ontology we must rely upon the paradoxical logic of contradiction between the non-contradictable and contradictable.

Chapter Three, the last one, contains analysis of experiential approach to the study of Advaita Vedänta. Here Sharma says that our experience of life compels us to take into account all the three states of consciousness as postulated in the revealed scripture. These are waking, dreaming and deep sleep. Invoking the assumption of the triad points out that rationality is only one aspect of manifold mental activities and that it cannot be regarded as encompassing the whole of life. Also, this implies the existence of unchanging consciousness which undergirds the consciousness of change of the three states of consciousness and constitutes the unchanging core of our being — self or ätman, which in turn is identical with Brahman. Trying to underscore this "experientially most resonant dimension of Advaitic nondualism", the author produces some accounts of mystical experience from the hagiographies of the twentieth century yogis Swämi Vivekänanda, Ramana Maharsi and Krishnamurti.

The author expresses hope that his attempt to present Advaita Vedänta with pedagogical variation will be a refreshing one, and surely it will be a useful addition to the literature available on this particular school of Vedänta, especially for students of comparative philosophy of religion.

====
Full text of "Advaita Vedanta An Introduction"
See other formats

The novelty of this book consists of the 
fact that it introduces the reader to 
the basic tenets of Advaita Vedanta in 
three independent but com¬ 
plementary ways: scripturally, 
rationally and experientially. All the 
three elements are usually found 
intertwined in accounts of Advaita 
Vedanta. They are presented 
distinctly here in the hope that each 
perspective will enrich one’s 
understanding of Advaita Vedanta as 
a whole and also allow the reader to 
form his or her own opinion about the 
relative merits of each approach. 



ADVAITA VEDANTA 




ADVAITA VEDANTA 

An Introduction 


Arvind Sharma 


MOTILAL BANARSIDASS PUBLISHERS 
PRIVATE LIMITED • DELHI 



First Edition: Delhi, 2004 

====



Contents 

Preface vii 

Introduction 1 

Religion, Philogophy and Advaita Vedanta 3 

Parti 15-49 

Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 17 

Part II 51-76 

Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach 53 

PartHI 77-110 

Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 79 

Conclusion 111 

Note 113 

Bibliography 121 

Index 125 


======

Preface 


The Biblical recognition of the fact that to the writing of 
books there is no end must surely not be used as an excuse 
for writing books indiscriminately. The readers therefore 
have a right to ask : why another book on Advaita Vedanta? 

Most of the existing books on Advaita Vedanta rely on the 
scriptural approach in presenting it. Some books mix it with 
the rational and experiential approaches as well, without always 
distinguishing clearly between them. This book tries to 
accord an independent status to each of these approaches 
without losing sight of their interconnectedness in the hope 
that the readers will find such a presentation refreshing. 

I hope that this pedagogical variation in the way Advaita 
Vedanta is thematically presented will be welcomed by the 
readers. 


—Arvind Sharma 




INTRODUCTION 




Religion, Philosophy and Advaita Vedanta 


I. Religion and Philosophy in India and the West 

It might be helpful to say a few words about the nature of 
philosophy as it is pursued in India, prior to providing an 
introduction to the school of Indian philosophy known as 
Advaita Vedanta. 

Both Western and Indian philosophers admit that the 
nature of the relationship between philosophy and religion 
follows a different pattern in Western and Indian civilization 
but they tend to differ in their assessment of the significance 
of this divergence. Both accept that philosophy essentially 
consists of a rational investigation into the nature of Reality. 
The nature of the Reality, however, also constitutes, in its own 
way, the subject matter of religion, so the nature of the 
relationship between the two needs to be considered. 

A relationship between religion and philosophy is 
considered peripheral in Western culture for historical and 
philosophical reasons. In the West, philosophy represents an 
intellectual movement which first distinguished itself from 
theology and then proceeded to achieve an independent 
status. This meant that the attitude of Western philosophy 
towards religion came to be marked by indifference, aversion 
and perhaps even rejection. Such a development did not occur 
within Indian culture. Thus, although the distinction between 
philosophy and religion can also be drawn in the Indian 
context, such a distinction therein tends to be analytical 
without being antagonistic. It can even be claimed that the 





Advaila Vedanta 


two, even when they become dual, remain undivided. 
Moreover, the distinction between philosophy and religion 
in the West additionally rests on the distinction between reason 
and faith, with reason constituting the cornerstone of 
philosophy and faith that of religion. This distinction is 
strengthened by the fact that the results of faith are typically 
accessible only posthumously, while the results of rational 
investigation are typically available here and now. 

A separation of philosophy and religion is intellectually 
approved of in the West, as this allows for the pursuit of 
philosophical truths untrammelled by religious scruples. Many 
Indian thinkers, however, take a different view of the matter. 
According to them this divorce of philosophy from religion 
runs the risk of reducing philosophy to a merely intellectual 
pastime, far removed from the kind of ultimate concern which 
should ideally characterise philosophy. In this context they 
make a further point: that although the claims made by Indian 
philosophy may sometimes seem to possess a religious nature, 
they are attainable within this life, and are therefore, in 
principle, verifiable. 

The successful attainment of such results is characterised 
by the term jivanmukti. Not all schools of either Indian 
philosophy, or of Hindu philosophy, make such a claim but 
Advaita Vedanta does'—along with the Hindu systems of 
Sarikhya and Yoga. The claim also characterises much of 
Buddhist and Jaina thought. The term jivanmukti is often 
translated as living liberation, as the word mukti means liberation 
and jivan means while living. The idea underlying jivanmukti 
thus seems to be that one can attain the results of one’s faith 
while still living in this world. There is no reason in principle 
why faith in reason could not also represent such faith. 

These ideas contrast, perhaps even sharply, with those 
found in the thought of other religious systems such as those 
of Christianity and Islam. In Christianity and Islam, specifically 
in their more traditional versions of Catholicism and Sunni 
Islam, the benefits of faith are to be enjoyed in a post-mortem 



Religion, Philosophy and Advaita Vedanta 




existence. That is to say, one does not experience the results 
of one’s faith until after death, or perhaps not even until 
the Day of Judgement, which takes place not at the time of 
one’s death but at the end of the world or of Time itself. 
This leads to the curious situation that one of the questions 
critically debated in those traditions which accept jivanmukti 
is What happens to the liberated one after his or her death” 
rather than “What happens after death”! The grand question 
is not what happens after death as in Christianity and Islam, 
but what happens to the liberated person after his or her 
death. 

It is clear that the concept of faith itself also carries very 
different connotations in the schools which accept jivanmukti, 
compared with those of the West. In schools which accept 
jivanmukti, faith is understood as faith pending realization - it 
denotes the trust one must have in order to undertake an 
experiment, but the outcome of the experiment is 
independent of such faith. It is even possible that the revealed 
results might contribute towards strengthening faith, just as 
one’s faith in science is strengthened when one experimentally 
discovers that water is made of two gases. 

It is in the light of these considerations that Indian thinkers 
take a more positive view of the fact that philosophy and religion 
have not been sundered in India, as in the West. This atdtude 
is also reflected in their treatment of Advaita Vedanta. 

To recapitulate: Philosophy in the Western world consists 
of rational investigation into the nature of reality. For Indian 
philosophers, however, philosophy in the Western world is 
only half of what it should be. They like to say that Western 
philosophy is a purely intellectual activity, and that in the West 
religion and philosophy have been broken apart. In the West, 
then, reason is opposed to faith. This split, they argue, has 
not occurred in the Indian tradition. Thus many schools of 
thought in the Indian religious traditions feel no awkwardness, 
embarrassment or self-consciousness in discussing the ultimate 
nature of reality both from a philosophical and a religious 
perspective. Advaita Vedanta is one such school. 





Advaita Vedanta 


II. Advaita Vedanta and other Schools of Indian Thought 

Since religion cannot be completely overlooked when 
dealing with philosophy in the Indian context, it is useful to 
draw a distinction between Indian religions and Indie 
religions. The term Indian religions refers to all the religions 
found in India such as Hinduism, Buddhism, Jainism, 
Sikhism, Judaism, Zoroastrianism, Christianity, Islam and so 
on. The term Indie religions, by contrast, is used to refer 
only to the religions of Indian origin collectively, namely 
Hinduism, Ruddhism, Jainism and Sikhism. Indian 
philosophy, again by contrast, is classically taken to refer to 
the philosophical systems which characterise the Indie 
religions. 

In one classification, which has gained wide acceptance 
since 1900 when it was adopted by Max Mueller, Indian 
philosophy includes nine schools of Indian thought. 2 A school 
of philosophy in India known as darsana, a word which may 
be translated in several ways. It is derived from the verbal 
root which means to see, thereby yielding such meanings as 
insights into reality or worldviews. These nine systems are further 
classified into the non-orthodox and orthodox systems of 
Indian thought as follows: 


Indian Philosophy ( Darsana ) 

Non-Orthodox schools 
of Hindu thought 

Nastika (3) 

Indian Materialism 
Buddhism 

Jainism 

Orthodox Schools of 
Hindu thought 

Astika (6) 

Nyaya 

Vaisesika 

Sankhya 

Yoga 

Mimarhsa 

Vedanta 


Asti in the word astika above means yes and na in the word 
nastika changes the meaning into no. The three non¬ 
orthodox schools of Indie thought do not accept Vedic 







Religion, Philosophy and Advaita Vedanta 




authority; to be nastika is to say no to the Vedas. Astika, then, 
means saying yes to the Vedas. Among the six schools which 
accept Vedic authority, the first four, that is Nyaya, Vaisesika, 
Sankhya and Yoga, indeed accept the authority of the Vedas 
but they do so basically a posteriori rather than a priori. The 
last two schools of Mlmarhsa and Vedanta, however, actually 
base themselves on the Vedas. 

It is obvious that orthodoxy here has been defined from a 
Hindu perspective, and the acceptance of the authority of 
the Vedas, the foundational scriptures of Hinduism, has been 
identified as its hallmark. It should now be added that the 
Mlmarhsa and Vedanta schools are to be further 
distinguished from the above-mentioned astika schools in 
that they not only acknowledge the authority of, but also 
base their teachings on the Vedas. Therefore, in order to 
understand these schools, it is important to understand the 
traditional view of the Vedas. 

The term Veda comes from the root vid, which means to 
know, as in video (to know visually). The Vedas are said to 
have been revealed to or seen by the sages. It is traditionally 
understood that the Vedas are not works of human authors. 
This idea also exists in the Islamic tradition, where the Qur’an 
is understood to have been received by the Prophet Muhammad 
frpm God. In Hindu Vedantic thought, however, even God is 
eliminated as the author. The Vedas are woven into the fabric 
and texture of the universe, which is eternal. This in turn 
means that the Vedas are eternal, and are periodically 
discovered, and not created or invented. 

The Vedas have never been formalised into a closed canon, 
although a certain degree of informal consensus does exist. 
This uncertainty has the subtle effect of making the person 
who speaks with authority more influential than the text. 
Because the Vedas are numerous and the canon loosely 
defined, it stands to reason that one would turn to a person 
Who has experienced jivanmukti for authoritative opinion, 
4'ather than sift through a mass of confusing, indeterminate, 
tecl sometimes contradictory information. 





Advaila Vedanta 


The Vedas are four in number. Each of the four Vedas 
(Rg, Sama, Yajur, Atharva) can be divided into four different 
layers, just as the Christian Bible ran be divided into two 
layers, the Old Testament and the New. Judaism and 
Christianity differ in that they do not accept the same layer 
as authoritative. In a somewhat similar fashion, Mlmarhsa 
thought regards the earlier parts of the Vedas as of primary 
importance, whereas Vedanta accords greater authority to 
the last layer, consisting of the Upanisads. The Upanisads, 
according to Vedanta, mark the consummation of all the 
previous layers, and thereby reveal the final truth contained 
in the Vedas. 

The basis of the classification of the darsanas, or schools of 
thought, provided above was textual, the text involved being 
the Veda. The point however should not be overstated. As 
already noted, the word astika comes from the verbal root 
which literally means to be or yes it is\ which means that these 
schools have responded with a yes to the question: “do you 
accept the authority of the Vedas?” The six astika schools: 
Nyaya, Vaisesika, Sarikhya, Yoga, Mlmarhsa and Vedanta were 
mentioned earlier. It was also mentioned that the first four 
of these, although they accept Vedic authority, do not base 
.their teaching on the Vedas. These schools simply 
acknowledge the authority of the Vedas, and then proceed to 
go on and do what they like. Because the corpus of Vedic 
scripture is vast, one could justify almost any view, and 
therefore nominally acknowledge the authority of these texts. 
Thus acceptance of Vedic authority is not as binding for 
philosophical purposes as it is for social cohesion. Hence the 
four schools are listed before the two schools of Mlmarhsa and 
Vedanta because they accept Vedic authority only nominally 
and after the three non-orthodox schools because 
nevertheless they do accept it, instead of rejecting the Vedas 
like the three non-orthodox schools. 

III. A Philosophical Explanation of the Classification 

It is also possible to provide a more philosophical justification 




Religion, Philosophy and Advaita Vedanta 




for the nature and order of this system of classification- 
specially from the perspective of Advaita Vedanta, the subject 
of our study. This has to do with the concept of the self or 
atman, which plays such a key role in Advaita Vedanta that 
the system itself has been referred to as atmadvaita. 

One can detect a pattern in the progression of thought 
through these nine schools, if one examines their concept 
of the atman, the self or soul. The materialists believe that 
natural elements suffice to give rise to consciousness in 
human beings. As materialism does not acknowledge an 
atman, the materialists encourage people to live for the 
moment, for death is final. They believe in happiness 
through materialism, in keeping with the maxim: “eat, drink 
and be merry.” Buddhism also does not acknowledge an 
atman but it accepts allied concepts such as a belief in the 
cycle of rebirth. Jainism accepts an atman, but it is considered 
coextensive with the physical body. Nyaya and Vaisesika also 
believe in an atman. However, in these systems although the 
atman does exist, it cannot exhibit consciousness 
independently of accessories, that is, by itself. Sankhya and 
Yoga also believe in an independent atman. But they also 
posit a strict dualism between matter and spirit, although 
the two are not on par. Matter is subservient to spirit and all 
matter is integrated into one category. (In other schools 
matter, is sometimes split into different ultimate parts.) 
However, in these systems, all atmans retain their individuality 
to the very end. They do not merge into one. The concept 
of atman in Advaita Vedanta, however, unites all entities in 
the realm of the spirit into Brahman, just as Sankhya and 
Yoga unite all entities in the realm of matter into prakrti. 
The school of Advaita Vedanta thus arguably represents a 
Culmination of the underlying philosophical thrust around 
the concept of the atman or self as found in Indian philosophy. 

TV. Another Philosophical Explanation of the Classification 

Another philosophical justification of classification can be 
found in the attitudes of the various schools towards the 



10 


Advaita Vedanta 


relationship between the realms of matter and spirit. Both 
matter and consciousness are equally given in human 
experience: we see material objects all around us, and it is 
immaterial consciousness which enables us to be aware of 
them. 

Since both matter and spirit in this sense are empirically 
given, three fundamental philosophical positions can be 
postulated on this point: (1) that it is matter alone which is 
the ultimate reality, consciousness being its epi-phenomenon, 
a position which may be characterised as materialism, (2) that 
both matter and spirit constitute ultimate reality in their own 
right, a position which may be described as that of 
fundamental dualism (3) or that spirit alone is ultimately real, 
matter being its byproduct, a position which may be 
characterised as idealism. 

In terms of this schema, the classification of the nine schools 
starts with materialism, then moves through the fundamentally 
dualistic schools which accept the reality of both matter and 
spirit, to end with Vedanta which is idealistic in its orientation, 
Advaita Vedanta being specially so. 


V. Advaita Vedanta: What Does it Mean? 

Let us begin with the word Advaita itself, which perhaps 
appears formidably foreign when first encountered. It can 
however be de-exoticised quite easily with the help of a 
brief foray into philology. It can be broken up as a-dvaita. 
The initial a here has the same meaning as the letter a in 
ahistorical, that is, of negating what follows. Thus just as 
ahistorical means not-historical, a-dvaita means rcot-dvaita. 

But what does dvaita mean? This word is etymologically 
connected with the English word dual - a connection which 
can be phonetically heard if one says the two words dvaita 
and dual out aloud. The word dvaita, moreover, not only 
sounds like dual, but shares its meaning as well. Thus dvaita 
means dualism or twoness. 

The word advaita ( a-dvaita ) thus means not-two or non¬ 
dual. 



Religion, Philosophy and Advaita Veddnla 1 1 

The word is however an adjective — so the question arises: 
what is it being applied to? In other words, what is it about 
which this claim is being made that it is not two ? 

So let us put the word advaita on hold for a moment and 
tty to find out what the word which it qualifies means; namely, 
Vedanta. The two can then be brought together again to 
reveal their meaning in its fullness. 

The word Vedanta might also, like the word advaita , 
appear forbiddingly alien at first sight. But once again it yields 
its meaning easily with the help of a mercifully brief excursion 
into philology. 

The word Vedanta is made of two words - veda + anta. 
The word Veda is derived from a root which means to knoio — 
the same root which appears in three English words: wit, 
wisdom and video, that is, to know intelligently (wit); to know 
sagely (wisdom) and to know visually (video). The word Veda, 
derived from the same root vid (to know) as noticed earlier, 
denotes wisdom, that is to say, spiritual wisdom, and by 
implication the texts which embody such wisdom. Thus it is 
that the sacred scriptures of the Hindus are called the Vedas, 
just as the sacred scripture of the Christians is known as the 
Bible, and of the Muslims as the Qur’an. Note that unlike the 
Bible and the Qur’an, the word Veda often takes a plural 
ending. This is so because traditionally one speaks of the 
four Vedas, a fact also noticed earlier. Sometimes, however, 
the word Veda is also used in the singular to refer to the 
Vedas collectively. The fact that, even to begin with, 
Hinduism possesses four sacred books and not just one tells 
us something about the inherently plural ethos of the 
tradition. 

Not only are the Vedas four in number, four layers can be 
identified in each of them. The following chart may help 
clarify the picture in this respect. 



12 


Advaita Vedanta 


Vedas 

Rg Yajur Sama Atharva 

Mantra or 

Sarhhitd — — — — 

Brahmana — — — — 

Aranyaka — — — — 

Upanisad — — — — 

Each of the Vedas contains (1) hymns (many shared by 
them in common) in praise of the gods; (2) prose explanations 
of the ritual use of these hymns; (3) reflections on the 
significance of ritual and (4) secret texts meant to 
communicate the highest mysteries which go beyond ritual 
into the realm of spiritual knowledge. These layers are 
respectively called (1) mantra or samhitd (i.e. hymns, or 
collections of hymns); (2) brahmana (i.e. authoritative 
utterances of priests); (3) aranyakas (i.e. forest-books) and 
(4) upanisads (or mystic texts revealed to disciples as they 
sat up close to the masters). 

The rest of our presentation will focus on the upanisads. 
Because they come at the end of the Vedas, or constitute the 
last of the four layers, they are also called Vedanta, that is, 
Veda’s end. The word anta in Sanskrit has the same meaning 
as the English word end. 

The texts which constitute the Upanisads, or Vedanta, deal 
with the central issues of philosophy: what is the ultimate 
reality about the universe around us and about us who are 
asking this question? And what is the ultimate nature of this 
ultimate reality? 

The Upanisads, (more than two hundred of which have 
been identified, among which close to a dozen or more are 
considered major ones) do not offer, at least on the face of it, 
a single answer to these questions. They are closer to being 
works of religious inspiration than systematic treatises on 



Religion, Philosophy and Advaila Vedanta 


13 


theology, and the inspired statements found therein lend 
themselves to many interpretations. Thus different schools 
of philosophy arose in India out of an attempt to present 
their teachings in a systematic way. These various schools of 
philosophy are known as schools of Vedanta, and they differ 
in their interpretation regarding the final teaching of the 
Upanisads. Thus questions such as: is the ultimate reality 
ultimately personal or impersonal in nature? are answered 
differently by these schools. Similarly, the schools differ in 
the answer they come up with to such questions as: what is 
the relationship of the ultimate reality ( Brahman) to the 
world, or what does Realization consist of. 

Advaita Vedanta is one such school of Vedanta. It is 
labeled Advaita because it does not ultimately regard either 
us or the universe as different from the ultimately reality - 
they are not-two. It prefers to call them not-two rather than 
one. because not-two implies a lack of fundamental division 
to begin with, whereas one may imply the coming together 
of two items that are in fact apart. Hence it prefers to speak 
in terms of an “undivided” ( a-dvaita ) Reality, in preference 
to one Reality, because according to it the positing of such a 
fundamental division is itself a product of error. 

Are all living beings ultimately identical with Brahman ? Is 
the universe also identical with it? Is there any difference 
between the way the living beings are identical with Brahman 
compared to the way the universe is? If the ultimate reality 
is a single undivided Reality, what reality do the different 
things and different people around us possess? Are they 
defilements or embellishments, and how can they exist 
without involving duality on the part of an undivided reality? 
The school of Advaita Vedanta tries its best to answer these 
questions by relying (1) on revelation, (2) on reason and 
(8) on the teachings of those who are said to be living 
embodiments of the Realization of Brahman or the ultimate 
Reality. 

====

PART I  Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


The scriptural approach relies on scriptural authority as the 
basis for the claims it makes regarding the nature of the 
ultimate reality. This reality is regularly referred to in the 
Upanisads as Brahman. 

The Upanisads, however, make several pronouncements 
regarding the nature of the objective world, the nature of 
the individual subject and the nature of the ultimate reality 
{Brahman), with the result that “there are great, almost 
insurmountable difficulties in deciding what exactly is the 
teaching of the Upanisads in certain important respects. This 
accounts for the emergence in later times of diverse schools 
of Vedanta, all of which claim to propound the Upanisadic 
teaching”. 3 It is also worth adding that: 

The vagueness of Upanishadic teaching is 
particularly in reference to the relation of 
Brahman to the individual soul on the one hand, 
and to the physical universe on the other. 
Though... statements about their identity are many 
and prominent, those distinguishing them are not 
altogether wanting. The first problem to solve for 
any one attempting to systematize the teaching of 
the Upanishads is accordingly to harmonize these 
two sets of statements. 4 

Each system of Vedanta has evolved its own method of 
harmonizing these statements on the underlying assumption 
(contained in Brahmasiitra 1.1.4) that these Upanisadic 
teachings have to be understood in a unified way. Advaita 



18 


Advaita Vedanta 


Vedanta, as a system of Vedanta, has devised its own 
understanding of the Upanisads in keeping with this 
assumption. 

it was noted above that the Upanisads seem to contain 
two streams of thought: one which recognizes the diversity 
of the objective universe, the subjective individual and the 
ultimate reality ( Brahman) and another which emphasizes 
their unity. The great exponent of Advaita Vedanta : 
Sarhkara recognizes, that there arc two streams of 
thought in the Upanishads; but he thinks that one 
of them, viz. that which affirms the reality of 
diversity, is only a concession to empirical modes 
of thought. All diversity being thus only 
conditionally true, the only teaching of the 
Upanishads, according to him, is that of unity. 
Since, however, there can be no unity apart from 
variety, he does not describe his teaching as 
monism but only as “non-dualism” ( advaita ). 5 

How, it might now be asked, does Sankara achieve such a 
result? 

He achieves this outcome through an exegetical 
manoeuvre according to which the Upanisads are said to 
contain certain key statements called mahavakyas, and 
through the subsequent claim that their teachings as a whole 
are to be understood through the lens of these seminal 
utterances. It is like claiming that if one wants to understand 
the New Testament, this is best done in the light of the 
overarching statement that ‘Jesus is the Messiah”. All other 
parts of the New Testament which do not directly confirm 
this—as when Jesus asks Peter: who do you think I am?—or 
when Jesus wonders on the cross whether God has forsaken 
him—are all to be understood subject to the mahavakya : 
“Jesus is the Messiah”. 

These mahavakyas , in the light of which the Upanisads 
should be understood according to the hermeneutical 
tradition of Advaita Vedanta, are the following: 



Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


19 


I. All this is verily Brahman. 

II. I am Brahman. 

III. This Atman is Brahman. 

IV. That thou art. 

To this a fifth is sometimes added: 

V. Brahman is spirit (or consciousness). 

These statements, however, need to be understood with 
extreme exegetical care, for they can be easily 
misunderstood. Indeed these rnahavakyas are accepted as 
authoritative by other schools of Vedanta as well, so it is not 
so much the fact of singling out these statements as 
rnahavakyas as their understanding within Advaita Vedanta, 
which sets this system apart from other schools of Vedanta. 6 

All This is Verily Brahman 

The reader will, for instance, note that this first statement 
identifies the objective universe with Brahman. The reader 
will also note that the second statement (I am Brahman) 
identifies the individual with Brahman. However, the exact 
manner in which the objective universe is held to be identical 
with the Brahman ; and the individual subject (or jiva is held 
to be identical with Brahman, are not identical. 

Before explaining this difference, it is necessary 
to draw attention to an important distinction 
between two types of illusion in common 
experience. A person may fancy that he sees a 
serpent at a distance, while closer scrutiny reveals 
to him that it is only a rope. The latter or 
correcting knowledge, like practically all 
knowledge of the kind, affirms the existence of 
something; but it contradicts that object as which 
(i.e., serpent) that something appeared before. 

He says to himself or feels when he discovers his 
error: “It is a rope, not a serpent.” Again a person 
looking at a white conch through a sheet of yellow 
glass, of whose existence he is not aware, takes it 



20 


Advaila Vedanta 


to be yellow. But a suitable change in his 
standpoint will disclose to him that the yellowness 
belongs to the glass and not to the conch. Here 
also, as in the previous case, the later knowledge 
affirms the existence of some reality; unlike it, 
however, it does not deny the object as which it 
appeared, viz. the conch, but only an aspect of it - 
its yellowness. He still sees it as a conch, but only 
adds that it is white and not yellow. The illusion in 
the first case consists in mistaking a given object 
for another that is not given; in the second, it 
consists merely in attributing to an object which is 
given, a feature that does not really belong to it, 
though it also is presented at the time. But for the 
interposition of the sheet of glass (upadhi) to which 
the yellow actually belongs, there would be no 
illusion at all in the latter case. Now these types of 
illusions serve to illustrate the difference in the 
manner in which, according to Sankara, one and 
the same Brahman comes to appear both as the 
world and as the individual self (jiva). It gives rise 
to the illusion of the world, as the rope does to 
that of a serpent in the first example. 7 

The relationship of the jiva to Brahman, however, must 
be explained with the help of the other example, for the 
‘Jiva is not false or illusory as the world is.” 8 Rather it is “its 
limitations which are false,” 9 and “these limitations, which 
are really its empirical adjuncts, appeared transferred to it, 
as in our second example of illusions, the yellowness of the 
glass appeared transferred to the conch.” 10 As a result: 

The ultimate truth, as realised by a jivanmukta, 
denies the world while affirming the underlying 
reality of Brahman which is given in all 
presentations as positive being (sat) and with which 
we may therefore be said to be constantly, though 
not consciously, in touch. The individual self, on 



Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


21 


the other hand, is not illusory in this sense. It is 
Brahman itself appearing through media or 
limiting adjuncts ( upadhi) like the internal organ 
( antahkarana ) which, we may state by the way, are 
all elements pertaining to the physical world and, 
as such, are illusory. Or, to state the same 
otherwise, the individual self when seen sub specie 
aeternitatis, is Brahman itself. When this fact is 
realized in one’s own experience, what is denied 
is not the jivci as a spiritual entity, but only certain 
aspects of it, such as its fmitude and its separateness 
from other selves. Its conception may thereby 
become profoundly transformed, but the 
important point is that it is not negated ( badhita ) 
in the same way in which the physical world is. It 
is, on the other hand, reaffirmed, though only as 
Brahman. We cannot thereby say that the 
individual self is false ( mithya ), as we may that the 
world is false. We can only say that it is not truly 
the agent, the enjoyer, etc." 

The overall picture which emerges on the basis of this 
discussion may be presented succinctly as follows: 

We now know the advaitic world-view in general. 
Brahman is the sole reality, and it appears both as 
the objective universe and as the individual subject. 

The former is an illusory manifestation of 
Brahman, while the latter is Brahman itself 
appearing under the limitations which form part 
of that illusory universe. 12 

I am Brahman 

The second statement, “I am Brahman” must now be 
examined in more detail. The subjective individual - the I - 
is regularly referred to in Advaita as the jivdtman, or jiva for 
short. The importance of this compound form will become 
clear at the end of this exposition, although the term 



22 


Advaila Vedanta 


jivatman will be referred to as jiva, during the exposition for 
the sake of brevity. 

In the case of the distinction between the first two 
mahavakyas —one which identified the Brahman with the 
universe and the other which identified it with the jiva —it 
turned out to be the case that although both were said to be 
identical with Brahman, the exact nature of this identity was 
not identical. The clue to the understanding of the second 
mundvakya and the kind of identity it involves is provided by 
the fact that although the jiva is referred to as anddi, or 
beginningless, from both an empirical and a transcendental 
point of view, this “beginninglessness” in the two cases is not 
identical in nature. 

It was noted earlier that the notion of the jiva is “that of a 
complex ( visista ), and points not only to an element which 
is identical with Brahman, but also to limiting adjuncts like 
the internal organs.” 1 ’ It is important to keep this in mind as 
we proceed. The empirical reality about the jiva consists of 
the fact that it is caught up in the process of samsara, bound 
by its karma, or actions. 


Here no doubt, a question will be asked as to when 
the responsibility for what one does first occurred. 

But such a question is really inadmissible, for it 
takes for granted that there was a time when the 
self was without any disposition whatsoever. Such 
a view of the self is an abstraction as meaningless 
as that of mere disposition which characterises no 
one. The self, as ordinarily known to us, always 
means a self with a certain stock of dispositions; 
and this fact is indicated in Indian expositions by 
describing karma as beginningless (anddi). It 
means that no matter how far back we trace the 
history of an individual, we shall never arrive at a 
stage when he was devoid of all character. 14 

This is one sense in which the jiva is anddi, or beginning¬ 
less. The other sense in which it is anddi, or beginningless, 



Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


23 


may be identified by asking the question: does the jlva, in its 
true, nature, undergo any change in the process of being 
involved in the universe? In this context: 

It is desirable to distinguish further between actual 
and apparent change. Actual change ( parinama) 
signifies that when a particular thing is destroyed, 
it does not disappear entirely. A rope when pulled 
to pieces remains as fibres. A pot, when broken, 
exists as potsherds. In apparent transformation 
( vivarta ), on the other hand, the disappearance 
is complete. When the illusion of “serpent” is 
overcome, there will be nothing of zHeft. It remains 
only to add that the jiva is not an effect in either 
of these senses. It is not a real transformation, nor 
even an illusory appearance of Brahman, so that 
no principle of causation is at all involved there. If 
we yet speak of the individual self as born, we only 
mean that its adjuncts like the physical body come 
into being and not the spiritual element in it. 
Hence the jiva is described as beginningless 
( anadi ). It is, as already indicated. Brahman 
appearing in an empirical dress. 15 

The distinction between the nature of this example with 
the one cited earlier should be noted. In the first example 
the difference between the two illusions—of the rope-snake 
and tinted-conch—consisted of the fact that while in the 
case of the rope-snake, what is not given at all (snake) was 
taken as given, in the case of the tinted-conch, only a feature 
of the conch, the yellow-tint was taken as given when not 
given. The conch as such is given forever, and because it is 
'given for ever, no concept of change, whether apparent or 
actual, applies to it. It is not the argument that the white 
conch was transformed into a yellow conch and when the 
error was discovered, was transformed back into a white 
conch, when the yellow colour was removed. The yellow colour 
was never part of the conch. 



24 


Advaita Vedanta 


Anything which is beginninglessness is assumed under 
normal philosophical assumpdons to be endless, i.e. eternal. 
So we discover that the jiva is eternal in two senses: (1) It is 
eternal in the sense that it is part of sarhsara which, as a 
process is eternal, (2) it is etemalin the sense that it is identical 
with Brahman , which is eternal. It is perhaps because it is 
eternal in both the senses that it can be referred to as ji.va.tman. 
As the permanently still witness to its eternally fluctuating 
fortunes the jivdlman is known as the sdksi or witness; the 
permanent as the witness of the constant. 

But this leads to the view that there can be two kinds of 
eternalities. Such indeed is the case. 

In Indian philosophy two kinds of eternity are 
distinguished, a) kutastha nityata and b) 
pravaharupa nityata. A thing is kutastha nitya if it is 
unchanged forever, while a thing is pravaharupa 
nitya if though incessantly changing it does not 
alter its pattern ( niyati ). Roughly speaking, a rock, 
for example, has the former kind of reality, and a 
river the latter kind. The nature of a river is to 
flow incessantly, and so long as it does not swerve 
from this nature of its, it may be said to be mutably 
real ; though not enduringly real as a rock. 16 

The jiva part of jivatman partakes of pravaharupa-nityata, 
and the atman element in it partakes of kutastha-nityata. 

Thus when it is said that “I am Brahman”, it is not the jiva 
but the atman element of the complex which is referred to. 
Be it also noted that the statement “aham brahma asmi,” (I 
am Brahman) while it may lead to the conviction that all 
spirit is one, “leaves out of account the entire physical 
universe” 17 , thereby indicating the importance of the first 
mahavdkya. 

Atman is Brahman 

We turn now to the third mahavdkya : that atman is Brahman. 



Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


25 


One may begin by recognizing the importance of this 
identification in the light of Vedic and Upanisadic literature. 
M. Hiriyanna writes: 

Thus Brahman means the eternal principle as 
realized in the world as a whole; and atman, the 
inmost essence of one’s own self. These two 
conceptions—Brahman and atman—are of great 
importance and occur not only independently in 
the literature of this period, but are sometimes 
corelated with each other; and their parallelism is 
pointed out by representing the self of the world 
as related to the physical universe in the same 
manner in which the individual self is related to 
the body. Thus in Atharva Veda, the universal self 
or world-soul is stated to have “the earth for its 
feet, the atmospheric region for its belly, the sky 
for its head, the sun and moon for its eyes and the 
wind for its breath.” 18 

He then goes on to say: 

The two conceptions are also sometimes identified; 
and it is this happy identification of them that 
constitutes the essential teaching of the 
Upanishads. They mean that the principle 
underlying the world as a whole, and that which 
forms the essence of man, are ultimately the same. 
Here ended the long Indian quest for the 
pervasive cause of all things—the search, as the 
Upanishads express it, for “that by knowing which 
all will be known.” Passages descriptive of Brahman 
alone or of atman alone occur frequently in the 
Upanishads; but they are not peculiar to them, 
being also found in the earlier literature. Their 
explicit identification, on the other hand, is 
specifically Upanishadic. 19 

What, however, is the philosophical importance of this 
identification apart from its textual significance? 



26 


Advaita Vedanta 


The answer to this question is best provided by the 
perspective that the search for the ultimate reality in the 
Upanisads followed two routes: an external route and an 
internal route. The external approach was represented by 
the search for the ultimate ground of the external universe. 
The following passage from the Upanisads provides a glimpse 
of such an approach in operation: 

The regressus to Brahma, the ultimate world-ground. 

Then Gargi Vacaknavl questioned him. Yajhavalkya, said 
she, since all this world is woven, warp and woof, on water, on 
what, pray, is the water woven, warp and woof? 

‘On wind, O Gargi.’ 

‘On what then, pray, is the wind woven, warp and woof?’ 
‘On the atmosphere-worlds, O Gargi.’ 

‘On what then, pray, are the atmosphere-worlds woven, 
warp and woof?’ 

‘On the worlds of the Gandharvas, O Gargi.’ 

‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of the Gandharvas 
woven, warp and woof?’ 

‘On the worlds of the sun, O Gargi.’ 

‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of the sun woven, 
warp and woof?’ 

‘On the worlds of the moon, O Gargi.’ 

‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of the moon woven, 
warp and woof?’ 

‘On the worlds of the stars, O Gargi.’ 

‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of the stars woven, 
warp and woof?’ 

‘On the worlds of the Gods, O Gargi.’ 

‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of the Gods woven, 
warp and woof?’ 

‘On the worlds of Indra, O Gargi.’ 

‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of Indra woven, warp 
and woof ?’ 

‘On the worlds of Prajapati, O Gargi.’ 

‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of Prajapati woven, 
warp and woof?’ 



Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


27 . 


'On the worlds of Brahma, O GargT.’ 

‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of Brahma woven, 
warp and woof?’ 

Yajnavalkya said: ‘GargT, do not question too much, lest 
your head fall off. In truth, you are questioning too much 
about a divinity about which further questions cannot be 
asked. GargT, do not over-question.’ 

Thereupon GargT VacaknavT held her peace. 20 

The internal route took the form of the search for the 
ultimate ground of one’s being or personality. 

But what was the essential self of man? The term 
introduced into Vedic inquiry was the common 
word for “self,” atman, used generally as a reflexive 
pronoun. From this general usage, atman was given 
a more specific meaning as the essential part of 
man, his basic reality. At times this was taken to be 
the body or the trunk of the body as distinguished 
from the limbs. Gradually, however, the atman was 
distinguished from the gross physical body; it was 
the inner self, the principle or entity that gave man 
his essential nature. 21 

The following Upanisadic passage (Brhadaranyaka 
Upanisad IV. 1-6) also provides a useful scriptural if simple 
illustration of this kind of an internal approach. 

The light of man is the soul 

1. Yajnavalkya came to Janaka, [king] of Videha. He 
thought to himself: I will not talk. 

But [once] when Janaka, [king] of Videha, and 
Yajnavalkya were discussing together at an Agnihotra, 
Yajnavalkya granted the former a boon. He chose 
asking whatever question he wished. He granted it to 
him. So [now] the king, [speaking] first, asked him” 

2. Yajnavalkya, what light does a person here have? 

He has the light of the sun, 0 king, he said, ‘for with the 



28 


Advaita Vedanta 


3. 


sun, indeed, as in his light one sits, moves around, 
does his work, and returns.’ 

‘Quite so, Yajnavalkya. 

‘But when the sun has set, Yajnavalkya, what light does 
a person here have?’ 

‘The moon, indeed, is his light,’ said he, ‘for the 


1 i 1 ww 11 


in his 




4. 


does his work, and returns.’ 

‘Quite so, Yajnavalkya. 

‘But when the sun has set, and the moon has set, what 
light does a person here have?’ 

‘Fire, indeed, is his light,’ said he, ‘for with fire, 
indeed, as in his light one sits, moves around, does his 
work, and returns.’ 

‘Quite so, Yajnavalkya. 

But when the sun has set, Yajnavalkya, and the moon 
has set, and the fire has gone out, what light does a 
person here have?’ 

‘Speech, indeed, is his light,’ said he, ‘for with speech, 
indeed, as in his light one sits, moves around, does his 
work, and returns. Therefore, verily O king, where 
one does not discern even his own hands, when a voice 
is raised, then one goes straight towards it.’ 

‘Quite so, Yajnavalkya. 

But when the sun has set, Yajnavalkya, and the moon 
has set, and the fire has gone out, and speech is 
hushed, what light does a person here have?’ 


‘The soul ( atman ), indeed, is his light,’ said he, ‘for with 
the soul, indeed, as in his light one sits, moves around, 
does his work, and returns. 22 


Elsewhere in the Upanisads a more detailed analysis of 
the human personality is carried out in an attempt to identify 
the atman. One such analysis is characterised by its division 
of the human person into five sheaths, while another focuses 
on the states of consciousness experienced by the human 
being. 



Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


29 


The Taittinya Upanisad (2. 1-6) speaks of the five sheaths 
or kosas, which the human personality may be said to consist 
of. “In this passage an attempt is made to analyze man at five 
levels—proceeding from the grosser forms to the subtler, 
and, therefore, more real forms. The real man transcends 
the physical, vital, mental, and intellectual aspects and even 
the beatific aspect. It is in the end suggested that the real 
self of man is identical with Brahman, the ultimate principle, 
the absolute, which is its raison d’etre’.”" 

Similarly, in another account ( Chandogya Upanisad 8: 7- 
12) “the real essential self is successively identified with the 
bodily self, the dream self, and the self in deep sleep, and it 
is suggested that all these three teachings are quite 
inadequate, for none of the three conditions, namely, of 
wakefulness, of dream and of deep sleep, can the nature of 
the self be said to conform.” 24 The point is pressed that “the 
real self is neither body, mind nor complete negation of 
consciousness. The self is certainly conscious but of nothing 
else but itself. It is pure self consciousness as such and it is in 
this condition that it is identical with the highest reality.” 25 
This picture is fully elaborated in the Mandukya Upanisad} 6 


State of Consciousness 

State of Self 

Waking 

Vaisvanara 

Dreaming 

Taijasa 

Deep Sleep 

Prajna 

The Fourth 

Atman 


In the foregoing passages one notices how, as a result of 
going inward within the human personality, the Upanisadic 
seers identified the Atman, as the real self, whether such an 
exercise focused on the constituents of the self (as in the 
case of the five sheaths) or on the states of consciousness 
experienced by the self (namely waking, dreaming and deep 
sleep). One needs to remind oneself now that as a result of 
going outward into the universe, the Upanisadic seers 
identified its real basis as Brahman, while looking inward the 






30 


Advaita Vedanta 


Upanisadic thinker realised the inner self to be Atman}' 
Now the great discovery the Upanisads made was of the 
identity of the ground of the universe with the ground of 
our own being. Ainslie Embree elaborates this point with 
the help of three passages cited below. In the first he 
describes the quest of the ultimate ground of the objective 
universe, in the second of the individual subject. The two 
are brought together in the final passage. 

1) In their quest for some ultimate ground for the 
world of natural phenomena, of time and space, 
and of human existence, the Upanishadic sages 
came to the conception of brahman, an 
undeniable, impersonal, unknowable power. 28 

2) Over against the questions concerning the 
ground of the external world are to be set those 
that probe inward, asking what is meant by the 
concept of the Self. The Self could be identified 
with the physical body, or “food,” as some of the 
Upanishadic thinkers were inclined to say. But 
consciousness, breath, will, all had claims to be 
regarded as the Self, and all were unsatisfactory as 
final definitions. What was needed was something 
that could be identified as being beyond change, 
something that was in fact immortal. This was 
found in the conception of the atman . 29 

3) In the macrocosm of the universe, the sages saw 
brahman-, in the microcosm of their own being they 
saw the atman. The realization that there is no 
distinction between the two, that the ground of 
one’s own being is identical with the ground of 
the universe, is the great discovery of the 
Upanishadic thinkers. “Whoever thus knows, 1 am 
brahman," declares the sage, “becomes this all. 

Even the gods have not the power to prevent him 
from becoming thus, for he thus becomes the self.” 

It should be carefully noted that this is not 



Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


31 


described as merging with the divine or union 
between God and man or reaching a state of unity. 

It is rather a recognition that there is no “divine” 
as distinct from the individual, no being over 
against the self, no process of becoming what once 
was not, but only the knowledge of the truth that 
always existed. ,0 

This identification of atman and brahman may be said to 
strengthen both, as it were. M. Hiriyanna points out, for 
instance, that the approach to the ultimate reality via 
Brahman runs into some difficulties: 

Such a principle need not be spiritual in its nature, 
and may well be a material or physical entity. 
Further, an objective conception like the above is 
little more than a hypothesis to account for the 
origin of the universe; and as there is nothing 
compelling us to regard it as actually existing, there 
being no logical absurdity in denying it. Some 
thinkers already seem to have done so in the 
Upanishadic period and maintained that ‘in the 
beginning this world was just non-being.” 1 

Similarly, the approach to the ultimate reality via atman is 
also not free from difficulties: 

If we start from the idea of the self, instead of that 
of Brahman, we meet with a similar difficulty, for, 
while the self points to what is spiritual and is an 
incontrovertible certainty, it is, as known to us, 
necessarily limited in its nature. Whatever view we 
may take of its nature, it is determined on one 
side by the world of nature, and on the other by 
the other selves. 12 

But when the two are identified they seem to have the 
effect of helping overcome each others’ shortcomings. It 
was pointed out that Brahman as such might appear too 
hypothetical to be real. But by “its identification with atman 
the establishment of the spiritual character of this principle 



32 


Advaita Vedanta 


and the removal of the uncertainty about its existence are 
both accomplished.” 13 Similarly, it was hinted that the atman 
may appear too personal, to the point of being limited, and 
finite, if very real; “it is this deficiency of fmiteness that is 
made good by its identification with Brahman or the all- 
comprehensive first cause of the universe.” 14 

This identification of atman and brahman is capable of 
being interpreted in several ways. Troy Wilson Organ notes 
some of these in the following passage: 

The question to be asked first is about the meaning 
of the connective “is.” The word “is” has at least 
five logically discernible meanings: 1) predication, 
e.g., “This apple is green”; 2) class inclusion, e.g., 

“Fido is a dog”; 3) class membership, e.g., “Brown 
pelicans are vanishing”; 4) equality, e.g., ‘Two and 
two is four”; 5) identity, e.g., ‘TV is [equivalent to] 

4.” Atman is Brahman seems to be a form of idendty 
or equivalence. There are many classes of identity: 

1) absolute physical identity, e.g., “A is identical 
with A”; 2) relative physical identity, e.g., identical 
twins; 3) same entity at various stages of 
development, e.g., Joe Doakes as boy andJ.D. as 
man; 4) same species, e.g., Harry Truman as man 
and Herbert Hoover as man; 5) same being in 
different contexts, e.g., Jane as mother and Jane 
as wife; 6) whole and part, e.g., a cup of water 
dipped from the Atlantic Ocean and the Atlantic 
Ocean; 7) appearance and reality, e.g., a 
photograph and the person of whom it is a 
photograph; 8) the same object considered from 
different perspectives, e.g., the duck-rabbit 
example of perception. Probably the last subclass 
of identity is the identity of Atman and Brahman: 
Atman is Totality viewed internally; Brahman is 
Totality viewed externally. 35 

The main point to note here is that the identity must be 



Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


33 


understood ontologically. The passage cited above helps 
explain what is meant by identity. It is equally important to 
realize what is wot meant by identity. First, when it is claimed 
in Advaita Vedanta that Atman is Brahman, it is not claimed 
that Atman becomes Brahman, as, for example, in a moment 
of realization. If anything, the realization consists of the fact 
that Atman is Brahman, was Brahman, and will ever be 
Brahman. The point may be explained with the help of the 
parable “Like the King’s Son,” in which “a prince, brought 
up as a hunter from infancy, discover[s] afterward that he is 
of royal blood. It involves no becoming, for he has always 
been a prince and that all he has to do is to feel or realize 
that he is one.” 56 The metaphysical moral of the whole story 
is that there was never a time when the mountaineer was 
not the Prince. He did not become a Prince when told he 
was one. He already was. He only recognized as a fact 
something that was already true. 

Second, when it is claimed in Advaita Vedanta that Atman 
is Brahman it is not meant that Atman merges into Brahman. 
An example from astronomy will be helpful here. For a long 
time astronomers identified two distant stars—a “morning 
star” and an “evening star,” till it was discovered that both 
were Venus. Did it then mean that the morning star merged 
into the evening star, or the evening star merged into the 
morning star? As both were already and always Venus, 
nothing of this sort can be said to have happened. 

Third, it is sometimes suggested that “ Atman is Brahman 
is not a metaphysical statement but a soteriological 
statement.” 37 Consider the following interpretation offered 
by Rudolph Otto: ‘The word is in the mystical formula of 
identification [Atman is Brahman] has a significance which 
it does not contain in logic. It is no copula as in the sentence: 
s is P; it is no sign of equality in a reversible equation. It is not 
the is of a normal assertion of identity.” In order to suggest 
what the statement is attempting to express, Otto adds, “For 
instance one might say instead of lam Brahman, lam “existed" 



34 


Advaita Vedanta 


by Brahman or essenced by Brahman, or Brahman exists me." 
“The suggestion is intriguing but not acceptable as such 
within Advaita Vedanta. 

Fourth, Atman is Brahman does not mean that Atman is a 
portion of Brahman. The jiva as the embodied Atman may, 
in an extended sense, be said to be comprised in Brahman 
as parts of the universe of which it is the substratum but that 
is as much as one can say, for the truth of the matter is that 
‘just as a pure transparent white crystal is wrongly imagined 
to be red on account of a red flower placed near it, or just as 
the colorless sky is wrongly imagined to be sullied W'ith dirt 
by the ignorant, or just as the rope is wrongly taken to the 
be a snake in the twilight, or just as the shell is mistaken for 
silver, similarly the non-dual Atman and Brahman is wrongly 
imagined to be the empirical self.” 39 Sankara’s comment 
on Brahmasutra 2.3.50 must be employed here to point out 
that “the individual soul is not directly the highest Atman... 
nor is it different from Atman.” It is not the former because 
it is subject to the limiting adjuncts, but it is not different 
for it is also bereft of the limiting adjuncts. All the empirical 
selves are also comprised in Brahman, but the exact nature 
of their relationship is a matter of debate. 40 

That Thou Art 

The fourth mahavakya is: That Thou Art. An analysis of how 
this great utterance is to be understood provides a useful entry 
into the hermeneutics of Vedic statements. 

It was pointed out earlier that, as distinguished from the 
other four orthodox schools of Hindu philosophy, those of 
MImamsa and Vedanta actually base their philosophy on the 
text of the Vedas rather than merely accepting Vedic 
authority as such in common with these other schools. It is 
therefore in these two schools that the issue of Vedic exegesis 
is squarely addressed. The key exegetical question as always 
is: how is the purport of a textual passage to be determined? 




Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


35 


The Mlmamsa school of thought reached the conclusion 
that the purport of a textual passage should be determined 
by keeping six factors in mind. This six-fold criteria is 
technically called the sadlinga and is said to consist of the 
following six elements: 


1) unity of the initial and concluding passages 
(upakramopasarhkdraikya ); 2) the recurrence of 
theme ( abhyasa ); 3) the new conclusion sought 
to be brought out ( apiirva ); 4) the fruitfulness of 
such a conclusion ( phala ); 5) the commendation 
or criticism of it throughout ( arthavada ); 6) the 
argument throughout {upapatti). The Advaita 
Vedanta also accepts these criteria as the pramanas 
for finding purport." 


However, although both Mlmamsa and Advaita Vedanta 
accept these criteria, they assign interpretive priority to 
different parts of the Vedas—namely, the earlier sections and 
the latter sections respectively, and this accounts for the fact 
that they arrive at different conclusions regarding the 
purport of the Vedas while applying the same criteria. It 
should not be forgotten, however, that other systems of 
Vedanta besides Advaita also accept these criteria yet reach 
different conclusions regarding even the purport of the 
meaning of the “latter portion” of the Vedas. These 
differences, nevertheless, are the result of differences in 
interpretation of the same Vedic texts, whereas the 
difference between Mimarhsa and Vedanta, and particularly 
Advaita Vedanta, arise from the application of the same 
exegetical criteria to different sets of Vedic texts. 

One may now proceed to examine how Advaitic exegesis 
works by applying it to a particular scriptural passage. The 
passage selected here is a famous one, which occurs in the 
Chnndogya Upanisad. It is in the form of a dialogue between 
a father (Uddalaka) and his son (Svetaketu). The following 
extract provides the setting: 



36 


Advaita Vedanta 


1. Om! Now, there was Svetaketu Aruneya. To him 
his father said: ‘Live the life of a student of sacred 
knowledge. Verily, my dear, from our family there 
is no one unlearned lin the Vedas] ( an-ucya ), a 
Brahman by connection (brahma-bandhu ), as it 
were.’ 

2. He then, having become a pupil at the age of 
twelve, having studied all the Vedas, returned at 
the age of twenty-four, conceited, thinking himself 
learned, proud. 

3. Then his father said to him: ‘Svetaketu, my dear, 
since now you are conceited, think yourself 
learned, and are proud, did you also ask for that 
teaching whereby what has not been heard of 
becomes heard of, what has not been thought of 
becomes thought of, what has not been 
understood becomes understood?’ 

4. ‘How, pray, sir, is that teaching?’ 

5. ‘Just as, my dear, by one piece of clay everything 
made of clay may be known—the modification is 
merely a verbal distinction, a name; the reality is 
just “clay”. 

6. Just as, my dear, by one copper ornament 
everything made of copper may be known—the 
modification is merely a verbal distinction, a name; 
the reality is just “copper”. 

7. Just as, my dear, by one nail scissors everything 
made of iron may be known—the modification is 
merely a verbal distinction, a name; the reality is 
just “iron” so, my dear, is that teaching’. 

8. ‘Verily, those honored men did not know this; 
for, if they had known it, why would they not have 
told me? But do you, sir, tell me it.’ 

So be it, my dear,’ said he. 42 



Advaila Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


37 


We plug into the ongoing discussion at a point when the 
father is explaining the spiritual import of death to his son: 

9. On this point, my dear, understand that this 
(body) is a sprout which has sprung up. It will not 
be without a root. 

10. Where else could its root be than in water? 

With water, my dear, as a sprout, look for heat as 
the root. With heat, my dear, as a sprout, look for 
Being as the root. All creatures here, my dear, have 
Being as their root, have Being as their abode, have 
Being as their support. 

But how, verily my dear, each of these three 
divinities, upon reaching man, becomes threefold, 
as has previously been said. 

When a person here is deceasing, my dear, his 
voice goes into his mind; his mind, into his breath; 
his breath, into heat; the heat, into the highest 
divinity. 

11. That which is the finest essence— (7) the 
whole world has that is its soul. That is Realty ( satya). 

That is Atman (Soul). That art thou, Svetaketu. 

‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’ 

‘So be it, my dear,’ said he. 

The reader will notice that the mahavakya under 
discussion: That art thou has made its appearance in this piece 
of dialogue between the father and the son. It will recur 
eight more times and the passages in which it forms the 
concluding statement are reproduced below. In these 
passages, however, the same mahavakya appears in different 
contexts. I shall therefore introduce each occurrence with 
a brief note, indicating the point to look for. In the next 
occurrence, for instance, the metaphor of honey is used. It could 
be argued that, among other things, the passage highlights 
the bliss that flows from the realization of the identity of 



Advaita Vedanta 


88 

Atman and Brahman , symbolised by honey."" 

1. ‘As the bees, my dear, prepare honey by collecting 
the essences of different trees and reducing the 
essence to a unity, 

2. as they are not able to discriminate “1 am the essence 
of this tree,” “I am the essence of that tree”—even so, 
indeed, my dear, all creatures here, though they reach 
Being, know not “We have reached Being.” 

3. Whatever they are in this world, whether tiger, or lion, 
or wolf, or boar, or worm, or fly, or gnat, or mosquito, 
that they become. 

4. That which is the finest essence - this whole world 
has that as its soul. That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul). 
That art thou, Svetaketu. 

‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’ 

‘So be it, my dear,’ said he. 

In the following passage the metaphor of the ocean is used. It 
has been proposed that the passage hints at the immensity 
of the experience of the ultimate reality. The loss of 
individuality, yet its persistence as universality is hinted at. 44 
The river ceases to be the river, but does not thereby cease 
to be. 

1. ‘These rivers, my dear, flow, the eastern toward the 
east, the western toward the west. They go just from 
the ocean to the ocean. They become the ocean itself. 
As there they know not “I am this one,” “I am that 
one” 

2. Even so, indeed, my dear, all creatures here, though 
they have come forth from Being, know not “We have 
come forth from Being.” Whatever they are in this 
world, whether tiger, or lion, or wolf, or boar, or worm, 
or fly, or gnat, or mosquito, that they become. 

3. That which is the finest essence—this whole world has 
that as its soul. That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul). 
That art thou, Svetaketu. 



Advaita Vedanta; A Scriptural Approach 


39 


‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’ 

‘So be it, my dear,’ said he. 

In tile following passage the metaphor of the tree has been 
employed. It highlights the intrinsic immanence and 
interpenetration involved in the identification of atman and 
brahman. 

This passage is best understood perhaps in the light of 
the following comment by Heinrich Zimmer: “According to 
this Brahmanical formula, the dialectic of the universe is a 
manifestation of a transcendent, non-dual, trans-dual, yet 
immanent principle, which both gives forth the world of 
names and forms ( namarupa ) and inhabits it as its animating 
principle. The dualism of natura naturans (prakrti) and the 
transcendent immaterial monad ( purusa) is thus itself 
transcended’’. 45 

1. ‘Of this great tree, my dear, if some one should strike 
at the root, it would bleed but still live. If some one 
should strike at its middle, it would bleed, but still 
live. If some one should strike at its top, it would 
bleed, but still live. Being pervaded By Atman (Soul), 
it continues to stand, eagerly drinking in moisture 
and rejoicing. 

2. If the life leaves one branch of it, then it dries up. It 
leaves a second; then that dries up. It leaves a third; 
then that dries up. It leaves the whole; the whole 
dries up. Even so, indeed, my dear, understand,’ said 
he. 

3. ‘Verily, indeed, when life has left it, this body dies. 
The life does not die. 

That which is the finest essence—this whole world has 
that as its soul. That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul). That 
art thou, Svetaketu. 

‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’ 

‘So be it, my dear,’ said he. 

In the following passage the ‘metaphor of the seed’ is 



40 


Advaila Vedanta 


used. It highlights the subtlety of the identity of Brahman 
and atman\ among other things. J. Brereton summarizes its 
significance as follows: 

First, the passage establishes that the tree grows 
and lives because of an invisible essence. Then, in 
the refrain, it says that everything, the whole world, 
exists by means of such an essence. This essence is 
the truth, for it is lasting and real. It is the self, for 
everything exists with reference to it. Then and 
finally, Uddalaka personalizes the teaching. 
Svetaketu should look upon himself in the same way. 

He, like the tree and the whole world, is pervaded 
by this essence, which is his final reality and his 
true self. 4 " 

There may also be the implication here that “the world 
which has name and form arises from pure being which is 
subtle and does not possess name and form.” 47 The passage 
runs as follows: 

1. ‘Bring hither a fig from there.’ 

‘Here it is, sir.’ 

‘Divide it.’ 

‘It is divided, sir.’ 

‘What do you see there?’ 

‘These rather ( iva) fine seeds, sir.’ 

‘Of these, please ( ahga ), divide one.’ 

‘It is divided, sir.’ 

‘What do you see there?’ 

‘Nothing at all, sir.’ 

2. Then he said to him: ‘Verily, my dear, that finest 
essence which you do not perceive—verily, my dear, 
from that finest essence this great Nyagrodha (sacred 
fig) tree thus arises. 

3. Believe me, my dear,’ said he, ‘that soul which is the 
finest essence - this whole world has that as its soul. 
That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul). That art thou, 
Svetaketu. 



Advaila Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


41 


Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’ 
'So be it, my dear,’ said he. 


The following passage may be read as an answer to the 
question: if Pure Being is the essence of all that exists, why 
is it not perceived?” The answer proposed is through the 
parable of the salt. Just as “we are able to perceive salt in the 

.i rd,_ U .1,-^ ..4- U,, A 

Wdici LLiiiOLigii Ldatcj Liiuugu n^t uy iiitans ui tuucii aitu 


sight even so we will be able to perceive Pure Being by other 
means though it is not obvious to our senses”. 4 " The passage 
hints at the transcendental yet experienceable nature of 
the identity of atman and Brahman. 


1. ‘Place this salt in water. In the morning come unto 
me.’ 

Then he did so. 

Then he said to him: ‘That salt you placed in the water 
last evening—please bring it hither.’ 

Then he grasped for it, but did not find it, as it was 
completely dissolved. 

2. ‘Please take a sip of it from this end,’ said he. ‘How is 
it?’ 

‘Salt.’ 

‘Take a sip from the middle,’ said he. ‘How is it?’ 
‘Salt.’ 

‘Take a sip from that end,’ said he. ‘How is it?’ 

‘Salt.’ 

‘Set it aside. Then come unto me.’ 

He did so, saying, ‘It is always the same.’ 

Then he said to him: ‘Verily, indeed, my dear, you do 
not perceive Being here. Verily, indeed, it is here. 

3. That which is the finest essence—this whole world has 
that as its soul. That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul). 
That art thou, Svetaketu. 

‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’ 

‘So be it, my dear,’ said he. 

The next passage contains the parable of the blindfolded 




42 


Advaita Vedanta 


person. Since at the moment we are blind to the reality, how 
might we reach it? This passage emphasizes the advisability 
of having a suitable guide or teacher. As Franklin Edgerton 
noted long ago: 

This section contains the beautiful simile of the man 
brought to a strange land and left blindfolded to wander 
about aimlessly, until some one removes his eye-bandage 
and tells him in which direction to go: then he finds his 
way home. Just so a man in this world who has not received 
the true instruction in Upanisadic philosophy wanders 
about aimlessly, his mental eyesight dimmed by the eye- 
bandages of ignorance, until a teacher removes the 
bandage of ignorance and tells him in what direction to 
shape his life’s course; then he will arrive at his true goal. 49 

1. ‘Just as, my dear, one might lead away from the 
Gandharas a person with his eyes bandaged, and then 
abandon him in an uninhabited place; as there he 
might be blown forth either to the east, to the north, 
or to the south, since he has been led off with his eyes 
bandaged and deserted with his eyes bandaged; 

2. as, if one released his bandages and told him, “In that 
direction would be the Gandharas; go in that 
direction!” he would, if he were a sensible man, by 
asking [his way] from village to village, and being 
informed, arrive home at the Gandharas—even so 
here on earth one who has a teacher knows: “I shall 
remain here only so long as I shall not be released [from 
the bonds of ignorance.] Then I shall arrive home.” 

3. That which is the finest essence—this whole world has 

that as its soul. That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul). 
That art thou, Svetaketu. 

‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’ 

‘So be it, my dear,’ said he. 

In the following passage the significance of this insight in 
the context of the experience of death is explained. The 
implication seems to be that in dying a person, who has 



Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


43 


realized the identity of Atman and Brahman, transcends all 
forms of phenomenal existence in a post-mortem state. 


1 . 


‘Also, my dear, around a [deathly] sick person his 
kinsmen gather, and ask, “Do you know me?” So long 
as his voice does not go into his mind, his mind into 


flic Krpiffi 


highest divinity—so long he knows. 

2. Then when his voice goes into his mind, his mind into 
his breath, his breath into heat, the heat into the 
highest divinity—then he knows not. 

3. That which is the finest essence—this whole world has 
that as its soul. That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul). 
That art thou, Svetaketu. 

‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’ 

‘So be it, my dear,’ said he. 


In the following passage ‘the metaphor of the heated axe 
of the ordeal’ is proposed. It highlights the invulnerability 
conferred by the realization of the identity, through what to 
some might seem a measure of overconfidence in the ability 
of metaphysical reality to affect empirical reality. 50 


1. ‘And also, my dear, they lead up a man seized by the 
hand, and call: “He has stolen! He has committed a 
theft! Heat the axe for him!” If he is the doer thereof, 
thereupon he makes himself ( atmanam ) untrue. 
Speaking untruth, covering himself with untruth, he 
seizes hold of the heated axe and is burned. Then he 
is slain. 

2. But if he is not the doer thereof, thereupon he makes 
himself true. Speaking truth, covering himself with 
truth, he seizes hold of the heated axe and is not 
burned. Then he is released. 

3. As in this case he would not be burned [because of 
i the truth]. So this whole world has that [truth] as its 
i soul. That is Reality. That is atman (Soul). That art 
r thou, Svetaketu. 



44 


Advaita Vedanta 


Then he understood it from him—yea, he understood. ’ 1 

Let us now apply the six-fold criteria to determine the 
import of the culled passages. The first criterion pertains to 
the unity of the initial and concluding passages. The initial 
passage states: “That Art Thou”, and so does the concluding 
passage. The second criterion consists of thematic repetition. 
The statement “That Art Thou” is repeated “nine times” 52 
in the selection. The third criterion consists of novelty. The 
claim “That Art Thou” is novel to the point of being 
sensational. The fourth criterion pertains to the result. The 
acquisition of knowledge, even saving knowledge, is the 
result. The fifth criterion is commendation. Quite obviously 
this insight is commended throughout, and the fact of it 
being dealt with throughout also fulfils the sixth and final 
criterion. Note that the purport is that of the non-duality 
between “That” and “This.” 

Now that the purport has been established, how is it to be 
understood - literally or figuratively? 53 

Sankara takes it primarily in a literal sense, 54 and the point 
is made strongly in Advaita Vedanta that the “sentence 
expresses apposition ( samanadhikarana ) between the two, 
Brahman and the individual soul.” 55 

From the point of view of Advaita Vedanta the fact that 
the two are in apposition is important, because it enables 
one to point out that how the statement may not be (mis-) 
understood. (1) It is not to be understood as a tautology 
because “the Upanisadic sentence removes the delusion of 
difference between Brahman and the individual soul, even 
though their identity is known as soon as the true nature of 
both is known. For, Brahman is the self of all, and the ‘Self 
is not really the body or the ego, but Being.” 56 2) It is not to 
be understood as an identity between two different things as 
cause and effect (“The pot is earthen”) or substance and 
attribute (“The lotus is blue”) because here the identity.of a 
thing with itself is asserted. 3) It is not to be understood as 
an injunction to treat them as such, as for instance in 




Advaiia Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


45 


meditation, because the sentence has no reference to action. 
It is a statement of fact, not an exhortation. 57 4) It is not to 
be understood as implication. This view “is based on the 
presupposition that words refer directly to substantives and 
not to attributes of substantives, and that when words have 
to refer to attributes they do so by implication.” 58 

A. critic msy ask, ‘If it is said tHat Here tHe identity 
of the substantives only—Brahman and jlva—is 
asserted, how have been they distinguished from 
their attributes?’ An Advaitin may answer that 
other Hindu schools (e.g. that of Ramanuja) also 
accept omniscience etc., as attributes of Brahman 
and ignorance etc., as attributes of jlva. Further, 
as will be shown later, prior to the hearing of That 
Thou art the meanings of Thou and That should 
be clarified (tattvam-padartha-sodhana). When a 
man, who has clarified for himself the meanings of 
these words, hears the sentence That Thou art, he 
will obviously understand that the asserted identity 
is only between the substantives and not between 
the attributes; just as when somebody tells him bring 
the jar, he understands by jar not jarhood, but a 
particular thing. If, then, the question occurs to 
him, what happens to the attributes? scriptural texts, 
supplemented by reasoning, will demonstrate to 
him that they are products of maya. Thus an 
Advaitin can try to rebut this criticism. 59 

Brahman is Spirit 

(Dne “may now examine the fifth mahavakya, that Brahman 
is spirit, i.e., that it is spiritual rather than material in nature. 

In order to fully appreciate this mahavakya, three 
realizations need to be made available to our consciousness. 
The first is that both material objects and immaterial 
conspicuousness are equally the components of everyday 



46 


Advaita Vedanta 


existence. This fact is so obvious that it runs the risk of being 
overlooked. Each individual is fully aware of material objects, 
as well as of the immaterial consciousness which characterizes 
the person as an individual subject. In fact every 7 individual 
himself or herself possesses a body and a mind—one material, 
the other immaterial in nature. 

The second point to recognize is that, as pointed out 
earlier, this pervasive fact gives rise to three fundamental 
philosophical positions. Although both matter and immaterial 
consciousness are equally given in human existence, one 
could argue that each could be an epiphenomenon of the 
other. In other words, although both are experienced as 
empirical reality, only one of the two—matter or spirit may 
constitute the ultimate reality. Thus one could argue for 
materialism on the ground that, in the last analysis, 
consciousness is a byproduct of material forces and processes. 
Just as wetness is a quality possessed by none of the two gases 
which compose water, consciousness could emerge as a 
property out of material bases. It could also be argued, from 
the other end of the spectrum, that consciousness is the 
only ultimate reality, and that matter is its product. 
Consciousness could produce matter just as the living body 
produces lifeless nails or hair. A third position, which refuses 
to reduce each to either is also possible —and may be 
described as that of fundamental dualism. It was noted 
earlier that the various schools of Indian Philosophy can be 
arranged on an axis of: 

Materialism. Dualism. Idealism. 

In the usual order of enumeration of these systems one 
starts with the Carvaka school, regularly characterized as 
materialists, and one concludes with the discussion of schools 
of Vedanta which are prevailingly idealistic. This also holds 
true of Advaita Vedanta even more so. 

A third point now requires to be considered: that it is 
difficult to refute the claims of materialism or idealism on 






Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 


47 


purely logical grounds.™ In other words, we seem to run here 
into the limits of reason, so that the significance to be 
attached to scriptural authority in general, and Advaita 
Vedanta in particular, takes on a new charge. 

With this in mind one may now approach the Advaitic 
position which aligns itself clearly with the ultimate reality 
of the spirit. The following passage provides a remarkably 
clear statement of the Advaitic position on this point: 

The Advaita definitely denies that there can be 
any relation at all between two such disparate 
entities as spirit and matter. But at the same time, 
it cannot be forgotten that our investigation of 
experience leads us to the conclusion that they 
are not only together but are often identified with 
each other as implied, for example, when a person 
says “I am walking.” Here the act of walking is 
obviously a feature characterizing the physical 
body; and yet it is predicated of the person’s self 
which is spiritual. The only explanation conceivable 
is that their association must be a mere appearance 
or, in other words, that the relation between them 
is ultimately false. Sarhkara treats of this point in 
his celebrated preamble to the commentary on 
the Vedanta Sutra, which is very brief and is written 
in what may be described as his “shorthand style.” 

“The self or the I-element," he says there, “is so 
opposed to the not-self or the Thou-element that 
they can never be predicated of each other.” A 
necessary corollary to this conclusion is that one of 
the relata is unreal. Both, of course, cannot be 
regarded as unreal, for in that case, since all the 
three elements—the two relata and the relation— 
become false, and since the idea of falsehood 
necessarily points to a standard of truth, we shall 
have to postulate another reality from the 
viewpoint of which we declare them to be false. 



48 


Advaila Vedanta 


The advaitin therefore takes for granted that it is 
matter which is false. The other alternative would 
Jesuit in materialism, whose untcnability we have 
already seen . 61 

Advaita as pointed out in the passage, also argues against 
materialism. As M. Hiriyanna notes: 

But even at its best the materialistic theory carries 
no conviction with it, since it tries to account for 
the higher principle of mind by the lower one of 
matter. Starting with the existence of matter, it 
explains mind as only a function of it. But in thus 
starting, the theory has already taken for granted 
that there is no mind, although it is as much an 
implication of experience as matter. In fact, we 
have no conception at all of matter, except as it 
appears to an observing mind. Believing in the 
existence of the one thus amounts to believing in 
the existence of the other. The truth that may 
underlie the theory is that all the things of the 
world can finally be brought under a single head, 
but it is wrong to conclude from this that that 
unitary source is necessarily physical. 62 

The statement is not just negative. It can also be argued 
that the spiritual premise about the ultimate reality as 
Brahman is implied in its description as saccidananda. Thus, 
M. Hiriyanna writes: 

The spiritual and unitary character of this absolute 
reality is very well expressed by the classical phrase 
saccidananda. As a single term defining its nature, 
it is met with only in the later Upanishads; but its 
three elements— sat, cit and ananda —are used of 
Brahman, singly and in pairs, even in the earliest 
of them. Sat, which means “being,” points to the 
positive character of Brahman distinguishing it 
from all non-being. But positive entities, to judge 
from our experience, may be spiritual or not. The 



Advailu Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 49 

next epithet tit, which means “sentience,” show's 
that it is spiritual. The last epithet ananda, which 
stands for “peace,” indicates its unitary and all- 
embracing character, inasmuch as variety is the 
source of all trouble and restlessness. “Fear arises 
from the other,” as a famous Upanishadic saying 
has it. Thus the three epithets together signify that 
Brahman is the sole spiritual reality of the 
Absolute, which comprehends not only all being 
(sat) but also all thought (tit) so that whatever 
partakes of the character of either must eventually 
be traced to it. In other words, it is the source of 
the whole universe, while it is self-existent and self- 
revealing, there being no other entity from which 
it could be derived or by which it might be made 
known. (i:! 




PART II 




Advaita Vedanta: 

A Rational Approach 


We may begin our rational analysis with any object found in 
the universe, even something as simple, as say, bracelet of 
silver, in order to illustrate the rational approach to Advaita 
Vedanta. 

The examination of the bracelet might begin with the 
recognition of the fact that the bracelet is made of silver. It 
has its origin in silver, and as without silver the “bracelet of 
silver” would not exist, silver is the material cause of the 
bracelet. The “bracelet of silver”, in this way of looking at it, is 
thus an effect, with silver as its material cause. 

The next step would now consist of examining the 
relationship of this bracelet, as effect, to silver which is its 
material cause. When the relationship between the two is 
closely examined, some points seem to emerge in clearer view 
as a result of this inquiry. It turns out that the effect is nothing 
more than the cause—that is to say, the bracelet is made of 
nothing other than silver. Note that one is not claiming that 
the bracelet is nothing more than the silver, in the sense that 
it is silver cast in a particular form and can be worn on the 
wrist, in a way plain silver cannot be worn. In this sense the 
bracelet of silver could be taken to mean to be “more” than 
silver. However, one can make bracelets of different shapes 
and sizes out of the same piece of silver but even in the new 
forms the material of which the form is made is nothing other 
than silver. In this sense the effect does not exceed the cause; 
“the effect is nothing more than the cause.” 



54 


Advaita Vedanta 


Moreover, although we might draw a distinction, when 
we speak, between a “bracelet of silver” and silver, as it were, 
the two are really inseparable. Or to put it another way, just 
as an effect is nothing more than the material cause, it is 
also nothing less than it, in the sense that it cannot be 
removed or divorced from it. That is to say, the effect cannot 
exist without the cause; we can separate the idea of the 
bracelet from the bracelet, but we cannot separate the 
bracelet of silver from silver. The bracelet of silver is shot 
through with silver, through and through. 

So the first realization is that the effect is nothing more 
than the material cause, and the second is that the effect is 
inseparable from the material cause. These points are more 
or less obvious but no less significant is a third point—that 
the effect must pre-exist in the material cause. The ‘idea’ 
of a bracelet can exist apart from the material cause, but 
the actual bracelet, as effect, must pre-exist in the material 
cause. If this were not the case, 

then it would in principle be possible to produce 
any effect from any material cause. In fact, we 
cannot even think of a non-[pre]-existent entity 
coming into existence. We can only think of a 
substance changing from one form into another. If 
something non-existent could ever be brought into 
existence, there would be no reason why we could 
not press oil out of sand (where it is non-existent), 
and why we should have to select only a particular 
material, namely oilseed, to produce the particular 
effect oil.” 64 

It might be helpful to locate the discussion somewhat, at 
this stage, both in terms of Indian and Western philosophy. It 
should be clarified, in terms of Western philosophy, that the 
discussion is proceeding by way of material cause in terms of 
Aristotle’s four-fold formulation of material, efficient, formal 
and final causes. From this perspective, for instance, “the 
activity of the efficient cause, the oilman, the potter or the 




Advaita Vedanta: /I Rational Approach 


55 


goldsmith [or the silversmith in the case of the silver bracelet] 
cannot produce any new substance, it only manifests the 
form of the substance concealed in its previous state.” 65 

In terms of Indian philosophy, the context is provided by 
the doctrines of Asatkaryavada and Satkarayavada. According 
to the former view the effect is something “new” and doesn’t 


pre-exist in th 


e material cause. According to the lattei the 


effect pre-exists in the material cause. It should be obvious 


from the trend of the arguments made earlier that Advaita 


Vedanta inclines towards the second view. 


Hindu thinking further diverges in relation to the latter 
view on the point as to whether such effect represents an actual 
or apparent transformation of the material cause. According 
to the Sahkhya school, the effect represents an actual 
transformation of the material cause, as when a piece of silver 
is transformed into bracelet of silver, which it was not before. 

The Advaitin joins issue with the Sahkhya school here 
because to claim that silver has been changed into a “new” 
form in the process implies that what was not has come into 
being—for that is what “new” must mean here; or the claim 
that silver has been transformed into what it was not earlier. 


From this point of view it can be said that according to Advaita, 
Sahkhya fails to realize the full significance of Satkaryavada: 


For, it holds that though the effect exists previously 
in its material cause, there is real change (parinama) 
of the material into the effect, since the material 
assumes a new form. Now this view amounts to the 
confession that this form, which did not exist 
previously, comes into existence. The doctrine of 
Satkarya-vada, that nothing, which didn’t exist 
previously, can come into existence, thus breaks 
down. If the grounds on which that doctrine stands 
are sound, then we must be prepared to accept all 
that logically follows from it, and cannot hold any 
view which implies any violation of this doctrine, 
rationally established. 66 



56 


Advaita Vedanta 


Some have even suggested that the Advaita doctrine 
should, by contrast, be called Satkaranavada, because 
according to the Advaita doctrine that effects can never 
overreach or outreach the cause. 

At stake here is the question : What is the logical, ‘as 
distinguished from the perceptual’, status of change of form 
? Or, m other words, dues change of form amount to change 
of reality ? The reality, which underlies all changes of forms, 
is the substance itself. Change of form doesn’t amount to 
change of substance and if the substance remains the same 
through the various forms it assumes, can the changes be 
said to be real ? As there is no real change in this sense, can 
change be said to be real ? Thus : 

We have no reason, therefore, to interpret the 
perception of a change in form as a change of 
reality. On the contrary, it is found that in spite of 
changes in form a substance is recognized by us as 
the identical entity. Devadatta, sitting, standing or 
lying is recognized as the identical person. How can 
this be, if change in form implied change in 
reality? 67 

In this analysis the rational status of anything characterized 
by a quality, or any form characterized by change, is 
challenged. To go back to the silver bracelet. Thus the silver 
bracelet possesses this quality of having curved. Let us now 
pose the question: what is the relationship of the curve of the 
bracelet to the bracelet ? The curve does not consist of 
anything other than the bracelet itself, i.e.; it characterizes 
nothing else than the bracelet. Nor is the curve separable 
from it materially. Nor could the curve have come into being 
if it had not existed in the bracelet of silver as a potential. 
Thus the quality of the curvature of the silver bracelet has no 
existence apart from the silver bracelet. 

Similarly, the silver bracelet has no existence apart from 
silver, as established earlier. 



Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach 


57 


At the heart of the issue lies the question of the 
relationship of the quality to object (curvature to bracelet ) 
or of object to substance ( silver bracelet to silver ). If the 
identity of effect to cause is rejected, although argued for 
by Advaita, then one is left with the following logical options: 
1 ) that the effect is distinct from the cause; or that 2) the 
effect constitutes an identity-cum-difference with the cause. 

Let us now examine these two options. 

We begin by assuming that the effect is distinct from the 
cause. This means that there is one thing called cause and 
another called effect and the two are distinct. If the two are 
distinct, but the cause produces the effect, then they must be 
linked in some way; that is to say, there must be a third entity, 
which links these two entities. But if such be the case then 

We would fail to explain the relation between the 
quality and its substance. For, two distinct realities 
cannot be conceived to be related without the help 
of a third entity to connect them. Now, as soon as 
we think of this third entity (which must be distinct 
from the two terms it attempts to relate) we have to 
think of a fourth relating entity, and also a fifth, 
which would relate the third with each of the first 
two terms respectively. Similarly, these fourth and 
fifth entities would require other similar media for 
relating them to the terms they themselves want to 
relate, and so on. There would then be an infinite 
regress (anavastha). We can thus never come to the 
end of our supposition and there will never be a 
complete explanation of the relation between the 
quality and its substance. In other words, the 
supposition of any distinction in reality between any 
quality and its substance would be logically 
indefensible. So a form cannot be treated as a 
distinct reality, and no change in form can be 
logically accepted as a real change, unless there is 
change in substance. 68 



58 


Advaita Vedanta 


Entity A 


Entity B 


Entity C 
Entity D 

(Connecting A and C) 

Entity E 

(Connecting A to D) 

Entity F 

(Connecting A and E) 

But perhaps treating them as two distinct entities involves 
ontological violence and the relationship is more properly 
conceived of as identity-in-difference. Thus both silver and 
silver-bracelet are after all identical as silver, but the silver- 
bracelet is also different in also being a bracelet. Advaitins 
claim that this is no more logically helpful in solving the issue 
of the relationship between silver-bracelet and silver, than 
treating the two as distinct, although on the face of it seems 
to resolve the problem. If two objects are related by identity- 
cum-difference then it must mean that in some respect they 
are identical and in some respect different. However 
“neither of them can as such be both identical with and 
different from the other. It would mean that M is both N 
and not-N and that N is similarly both M and not-M, which is 
a violation of the law of contradiction. When two things are 
distinct in fact, they cannot be the same.” 69 In other words 
they do not constitute identity-in-difference directly. But as 
M. Hiriyanna points out further: 

Thus we may say that M and N possess one or more 
common feature which may be represented by a 
and, at the same time exhibit differences 
represented by x and y respectively. According to 
this explanation, what is identical is quite distinct 



Advaila Vedanta: A Rational Approach 


59 


from what is different; yet the entities, viz. M and 
N, by virtue of such features, it may be said, are 
identical with and, at the same thing different from 
each other. Such an explanation may seem to solve 
the difficulty, but the solution is only apparent, for 
it merely shifts the difficulty to another set of things. 

It assumes that M and N are characterized by a x 
and a y respectively, and the assumption leaves us 
where we were, for we cannot satisfactorily explain 
the relation between a thing and its so-called 
characteristics. Now the relation between M and a 

x, to take only one of the entities, cannot be identity, 
for then the distinction between a and x would 
vanish, both being identical with the same M; and 
with it also the relation of idendty-in-difference 
between M and N. Nor can a and x be different 
from M, for then their character, whatever it may 

be, will cease to affect M, and therefore also its 
relation to N. So we are driven to think of identity- 
in-difference as the only possible relation between 
these. That is, in explaining the relation in question 
between M and N, we presuppose the same relation 
within each of them; and pursuing the inquiry 
further will only lead to an infinite process. 70 

To illustrate: Let us propose that the color of silver is the 
common property (a) shared by the silver bracelet and silver 
but the differences between them consist of (x) in the form 
of undetermined form of silver as a mere lump and (y) in the 
form of the special shape of the bracelet. 

Now, in the case of silver (M), what is the relationship of 
silver to (a) its color and (x) its indeterminate shape? The 
difference between (a) color and (x) indeterminate shape 
would vanish, if both are identical with the same M (silver). 
Nor can (a) and (x) be different from M, for then they would 
have no connection with M. Hence this relationship too would 
have to be described as identity-cum-difference. 



60 


Advaita Vedanta 


Thus: 

M N 

Silver Silver-bracelet 

Identity-cum-difference 

Color Indeterminate Color Bracelet 

(a) Shape (x) (a) Shape (y) 

Identity-cum-difference Identity-cum-difference 

The characterization (of identity-cum-difference) between 
M and N merely shifts within them, and so down the pike. 

Thus, no logically satisfactory resolution in terms of other 
logical options seems possible. Nevertheless, the change is 
perceived, although it is rationally unexplained and, 
therefore, logically unacceptable. Hence the need to 
characterize it as appearance. The point may be elaborated 
as follows: 

...we have seen that no causation involves any 
change in substance. Hence causation does not 
imply any real change. Moreover, as every change 
is a process of causation; there cannot be any 
change in reality. This amounts to the position that 
though we perceive changes we cannot rationally 
accept them as real. We have therefore to 
understand them in the same way as we do, when 
we perceive an illusory object. We do perceive a 
rainbow, a blue sky, movement of the sun and many 
other things which we cannot believe as real 
because reasoning proves them to be unreal. Such 
a perceived but unreal phenomenon is called an 
appearance and distinguished from reality. On the 
same ground we must call change also an 
appearance and distinguish it from reality. We can 
thus reach, on purely logical grounds supported 
by common observation, the theory of vivarta or 
apparent change, as a rational doctrine required 
for the explanation of the world. 71 



Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach 


61 


One might be tempted to argue here in rebuttal, in terms 
of practical rather than pure reason, that the silver-bracelet 
is surely different from plain silver in that it can be worn on 
the wrist in a way one cannot wear plain silver. The Advaitin 
would counter argue that the fact that the bracelet is 
serviceable doesn’t affect the truth of the proposition, no 
more than the apparent movement of the sun across the sky 
can be accepted as real just because it is helpful in organizing 
our daily activities. It is of service too but that doesn’t make 
it true. 


II 

So we started with the examination of the relationship of 
the curve of the silver bracelet to the silver bracelet, 
preceded to an examination of the relationship of silver- 
bracelet to silver and found that the new relationship 
reincarnates the old problem. One might, however, at this 
point raise the following objection—what you say seems to 
hold for the objects in the universe, but does this also hold 
for the universe itself treated as an object, as it were. In 
other words, does what holds for the parts also hold for the 
whole? 

Even this objection can be logically nuanced as follows: 
why speak of the universe, you speak of forms and substance 
but does what you say of forms apply to the substance also? 

Both of these issues may now be dealt with in this section. 

One must begin by recognizing that silver was chosen as a 
substance because, in relation to it, bracelets and other 
ornaments could be viewed as its modifications (vikara) into 
form. 

From a broader perspective, however, even silver is subject 
to modification (vikara). That is, it too is the form of some 
other substance X. Just as the bracelet arose out of silver, was 
in silver in some way before it so arose and dissolved into it 
again, so also silver itself is apparently the form of some 
substance X in which it pre-exists, from which it arises as silver 
and into which it disappears. Or to ring a metaphorical change, 
and talk of a pot of clay rather than a bracelet of silver: 



62 


Advaita Vedanta 


The qualities of a pot have no reality apart from 
the pot, and also that the pot itself has no reality 
apart from its cause, the clay, which is the real 
substance of which the pot is only one form of 
manifestation. But as clay itself is liable to 
modification and may cease to be clay, even it 
cannot be called a real substance; it is only a form 
of manifestation, though more abiding than a pot, 
of some other substance which persists through all 
the modifications of clay, and is also present in what 
clay itself comes from and in what it is changed into, 
after its destruction. If all so-called substances are 
thus liable to modification (vikara), then the 
substance underlying all objects of the world would 
be that which persists through all forms of objects. 
Existence is revealed in the perception of every 
object, whatever be its nature. It can, therefore, be 
called the substance, the material cause, or the 
underlying reality behind the world of objects. 72 

And now when we move to the level of the universe we do 
see a shift and a change in quantity does lead to change in 
quality in a quirky Marxian manner: 

If all so-called substances are liable to modification 
vikara then the substance underlying all the objects 
of the world would be that which persists through 
all forms of objects. And we observe that existence 
(not in any specific form but existence pure and 
simple) is what is common to all forms of objects. 
Existence is revealed in the perception of every 
object, whatever be its nature. It can, therefore, 
be called the substance, the material cause of the 
underlying reality behind the world of objects.” 

The qualitative change in the general conclusion should 
not go unnoticed. The attempt to analyze the nature of 
specific objects in the universe has led to the identification 



Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach 


63 


of non-specific existence as the material cause. The material 
cause has turned out to be immaterial existence! But this 
should not be considered unduly abstract. It is the neutral 
or unengaged gear in the car, which allows all specific gears 
to be engaged. 

Ill 

The next logical question to arise in the context is the 
following: this logical analysis pertains to the objective world. 
Does it also apply to the subjective world of the individual? 
Does Advaita Vedanta offer a different rational analysis for 
the internal world of being as opposed to the external? 

This conclusion, that the material cause of the universe is 
immaterial existence, is also applied to the internal states in 
Advaita Vedanta, for these states also exist. 

...when we examine the changing states within our 
minds what we also find there is that every state, 
every idea, whatever its object, exists. Even an 
illusory idea, which lacks an external object, exists 
as an idea ( avagati). A state of deep dreamless sleep 
or of swoon also exists, although no objective 
consciousness is present there. Existence is thus 
found to be the one undeniable reality persisting 
through all states, internal and external. It can, 
therefore, be accepted as the substance, and 
material cause of which all determinate objects and 
mental states are the diverse manifestations. 

We find then that pure existence which is the 
common cause of the entire world is itself formless, 
though appearing in various forms; partless, though 
divisible in different forms; it is infinite though it 
appears in all finite forms. Sankara thus reaches 
the conception of an infinite, indeterminate 
nirvisesa existence as the essence or material cause 
of the world. He calls this Absolute or Brahman. 74 



64 


Advaita Vedanta 


IV 

This is how the rational investigation of everyday reality by 
Advaita leads it to question and then reconfigure the 
conceptual framework with which we operate in everyday life. 
In the course of ordinary living, we draw a sharp distinction 
between our experience of the external universe and our 
own inner life. Advaita Vedanta, however, pools our 
experiences of the external world and the internal world as 
data to be explained in common and is thus counter-intuitive 
in terms of our quotidian philosophical framework. 

It questions this framework at an even deeper level, when 
it raises the question of the relationship of consciousness to 
existence. In terms of our quotidian or even commonsensical 
philosophy of life, we associate “existence” with our experience 
of the external world, and “consciousness” with our experience 
of the internal world. Thus for us external objects “exist” and 
we are “conscious” of our internal states. 

In this context Advaitic rationality raises the question: What 
is the criterion of consciousness? Note the Advaitin answer to 
the parallel question: What is the criterion of existence? is 
the following: that which is perceived. The totally non-existent 
—the barren woman’s son and the horns of a hare—cannot 
be perceived. Let a similar question now be posed in relation 
to consciousness. 

But what is the criterion of consciousness? A mental 
state is conscious, because its existence is self- 
revealing. But when we perceive the external world 
its existence also reveals itself. The power of 
appearing bhati is common to both internal and 
external forms of existence; and it can, therefore, 
be argued that existence which is common to the 
internal and external world must posses the power 
of revealing itself. Therefore, it is more reasonable 
to hold that Absolute existence is of the nature of 
self-revealing consciousness. In fact, a little 
reflection shows that self-revelation may even be 



Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach 


65 


taken as the differential that distinguishes 
existence from non-existence. What is non¬ 
existent (e.g. the son of a barren woman) cannot 
even appear or reveal itself for a moment . 75 

The gulf we tend to sense between existence and 
consciousness is bridged in Advaita Vedanta by arguing that 
when we speak of the existence of the silver-bracelet it boils 
down to the consciousness of the existence of the silver- 
bracelet and that we would not be able to speak of the 
existence of silver apart from the consciousness of its existence. 

In terms of another metaphor: 

Wherever there is appearance of existence there 
is awareness invariably present. Even an external 
object, say clay, which appears to us is presented by 
an awareness of clay (mrt-buddhi). When we 
perceive clay becoming a pot, our clay-consciousness 
turns into pot-consciousness (ghata buddhi). An 
imaginary object is just the idea of the object, and 
so also is an illusory object. So we find that awareness 
pervades all forms of existence known to us. 

By a series of arguments like these Sankara reaches 
logically what he accepts on the authority of the 
revealed texts, namely that the world originates 
from Brahman, which is Absolute Existence and 
Consciousness and that Brahman has the power of 
manifesting itself in diverse apparent form, without 
really undergoing any modification . 76 


The tenor of our analysis of the world, however, has so far 
taken the smooth and easy route. We started out with the 
curve of the silver-bracelet, and moved through on to silver 
and to that substance of which the silver might only be one 
form, and ended up by identifying general existence as the 
material cause of the universe. 



66 


Advaila Vedanta 


But the course of the universe is not that smooth. For one 
thing we find one experience of existence contradicted by 
another. What we thought was a snake turns out to be a rope. 
Similarly, the universe doesn’t consist of just silver-bracelets 
or silver. It contains many other objects. In other words, our 
analysis of the universe needs to be made more complex by 
incorporating two new features of our experience into it: (1) 
the contradictability of objects and 2) the immense variety of 
objects. The question we must now answer is : how do these 
twin considerations affect the logic of the arguments advanced 
so far ? 

We argued earlier from form to substance in a seamless 
way—but forms can contradict or replace one another over 
time and they vary in space. What bearing then do these factors 
have on the logical outcome of our discussion? 

When experiences contradict one another, then the 
contradicting form takes precedence over or is considered 
more real than the contradicted form. Thus normal waking 
state is considered more real than dream state and within 
waking state, as when a piece of shell is experienced as silver, 
the contradicting experience (here shell) is considered more 
real than the contradicted experience (here silver). 

But in spite of such contradictions among the 
different forms, existence or (consciousness) as 
such remains uncontradicted. When we disbelieve 
an illusory serpent we only deny that the existence 
there is of a form of a serpent, but we do not deny 
that there is some existence. Again, even when we 
deny a dream object, we don’t deny that the 
experience or idea existed. And when we think of a 
time or place where nothing exists, we are thinking 
of the existence of at least that time or place. So 
existence, in some form or another, is as wide as 
thought and we cannot conceive of the absence 
or denial of existence. This universal, pure 
existence (or consciousness ) is thus the only thing 



Aavaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach 


67 


whose contradiction is unthinkable. Sankara calls 
it, therefore, supreme reality (Paramarthika satta.) 

He thus logically arrives also at his conception of 
reality as that which persists uncontradicted through 
all forms of existence in all place and times. 77 

Rut on what logical basis, we might wish .to ask, was the 
contradicting experience considered superior to the 
contradicted, experience? A little reflection leads to the 
conclusion that the contradicting experience is considered 
more real than the contradicted experience, because it 
endures longer than the contradicted experience. Thus 
waking state outlasts the dreaming state, and the experience 
of the rope lasts longer than that of the serpent. 

This provides a clue to the Advaitic concept of reality 
namely, that that which persists is real. One is led in this 
direction by an examination of both the original argument 
and the complications introduced into it in this section. Thus, 
to revert to the original argument, the silver in a sense is more 
real since the bracelet was a form of it and the substance X, of 
which silver might be the form, is more real than silver because 
each respectively endures longer, and existence itself—pure 
indeterminate existence—was identified as the material cause 
of the universe because it was the most enduring of all. 

This thrust is confirmed when one takes the fact that forms 
might contradict one another into account—as when the 
experience of a snake is contradicted by it turning out to a 
rope, or dream experience by waking experience. Existence 
as such persists through them also. 

As for the diversity of objects exhibited by the universe, it 
needs to be noted that they are all undergoing modification, 
although at different rates. Even more important than the 
difference in the rate at which they are undergoing 
modification is the fact that they are all undergoing 
modification. Now 


This theoretical possibility of change in perception, 
and of consequent contradiction, then makes the 



68 


Advaita Vedanta 


status of every particular object precarious, in 
respect of its reality. We can never be absolutely 
certain that what appears now as pot will not appear 
otherwise later. We see, therefore, how different 
particular forms of existence, like pot and cloth, 
weaken and undermine each other’s claim to 
indubitable reality. If, however, these claimed only 
pure existence, and not existence of particular 
forms, their claims would not have been mutually 
exclusive. The rival claims of particulars as 
particular existents thus prevent them from having 
the position of indubitable reality such as pure 
existence enjoys. 78 


VI 

The upshot of such a rational analysis of the objective universe 
along Advaitic lines leads one to the following conclusion: 

On such rational grounds Sankara grades and 
classifies common experience. As we saw, he first 
of all, distinguishes all objects of possible and actual 
experience from utter unreality, like the child of 
the barren mother. The former again are classed 
under there heads : 1) those that only appear 
momentarily in illusions and dreams, but are 
contradicted by waking experience, 2) those that 
appear in normal waking experience—the 
particular and changing objects, which form the 
basis of our ordinary life and practice, but which 
are still not acceptable to reason as completely real 
(because they exhibit contradiction or are open to 
future contradiction), and 3) pure existence which 
reveals itself through all experience, and is neither 
contradicted nor contradictable. 79 

How is such a world, the world not only of common 
experience, but one in which common experience is rationally 
described? 



Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach 


69 


The world is thus not a homogeneous conception, 
and if, in spite of this, one insists on being told 
what such a world, as a whole is, the fairest reply 
can only be, what Sankara gives, namely that is 
indescribable ( anirvacaniya ) either as real or as 
unreal. But if the word world is confined only to 
the second aspect, it would be again fair to say, 
that the world is real only for practical purpose, 
more real than the first and less real than the third 
kind of existence. But if the world is taken in the 
third sense, Sankara would emphatically assert that 
the world is eternally real. As he puts it : “As the 
cause, Brahman, doesn’t lack existence at any time, 
past, present or future, so does the world not lack 
existence in any of the three periods of time.” 
Again, “ All particular modes of existence with 
different names and forms as real as existence, 
but unreal as particulars.” st> 

VII 

So much of the objective world—what now of the individual 
subject? 

The rational analysis of the individual subject in Advaita 
seems to follow three routes: 1) an analysis of the subject’s 
experience of itself; 2) an analysis of the subject’s experience 
of the states in which it exists in the world and 3) and analysis 
of the subject in the light of its relation to the external world. 

The subject’s experience of itself is usually described 
through the use of the personal pronoun “I”. One way in which 
Advaita arrives at its concept of the individual is through a 
rational analysis of this linguistic phenomenon. 

The word “I” can be employed in various ways and if the 
common denominator underlying these various uses could 
be identified, then one might have here the key by turning 
which the secrets of the self may be unlocked. Some of such 
uses of the “I” may be listed as follows: 



70 


Advaita Vedanta 


1. I am tall 

2. I see you 

3. I walk home 

4. I think of it 

’5. I feel he is wrong 

6. I will do it 

7. I know, I just know 

The first use refers to the body. So the “I” possesses a body. 
Thus people say: ‘I am tali’, ‘I am short’, ‘I am fat;, T am 
thin’ and so on. 

The second use refers to an organ of perception—the eye. 
One also says: I hear, I touch, I taste, and I smell. Thus the 
organs of perception located in the body and their function 
are some of the things the “I” identifies with. It does the same 
when it says: I balance myself on a beam. 

The third use refers to an organ of action, that of 
locomotion. One also says: I talk, I grasp, I empty my bladder, 
and I have sex. Thus the organs of ac tion located in the body 
and their function are some of the other things the “I” 
identifies with. 

The fourth, fifth, and sixth uses point to the psyche in its 
three dimensions of thinking, feeling and willing. The “I” 
identifies itself with each of these. 

The seventh use points to the sense of intuition possessed 
by us—a sense of knowing somewhat different from our usual 
way of knowing things. The I identifies with it too. 

Now what persists through all these states as a common 
denominator? One might be tempted to say the body, but 
the body could not identify with any of the descriptions offered 
earlier, were it not conscious. Neither would the mind be able 
to identify with any were it not conscious. In fact, the 
identification of the / with any of the descriptions offered 
earlier presuppose consciousness. Thus 

Consciousness is, therefore, the essence of the self 
in whichever form it may appear. But it is not 
consciousness of any particular form, but simple 



Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach 


71 


consciousness common to all its forms. Such 
consciousness is also pure existence since existence 
persists throughout all forms of consciousness. The 
different particular and changing forms of 
consciousness can be shown, from their 
contradictory natures, to be mere appearance, in 
the same way as the different forms of existence 
were shown to be so before. 81 

There arc ostensibly moments, however, when 
consciousness is not present, as when we swoon or are asleep. 
At these moments, however, our sense of / also disappears. 
Thus the correlation between / and /-consciousness in terms 
of our conscious self is obvious. But what when we are 
dreaming? We are not conscious of our body when we are 
dreaming, although consciousness in some form is present. 
In deep sleep it seems to be absent at first sight. 

This brings us to the second approach adopted in Advaita 
for identifying the nature of the self. All of us assert that I am 
awake, I dreamt, and I slept. Thus the / clearly persists 
through these three states of waking, dreaming and deep 
sleep. But does consciousness persist through these three 
states? According to Advaita an analysis of these three states 
reveals that consciousness does persist through them. 

Moreover, as a bonus, this analysis also enables us to identify 
the nature of this consciousness more clearly, if we argue as 
follows: 

The essence of the self must remain in all these or 
the self would cease to be. But what do we find 
common to all these states ? In the first state there 
is consciousness of external objects; in the second 
also there is consciousness, but of internal objects 
present only to the dreamer. In the third state no 
objects appear, but here is no cessation of 
consciousness, for otherwise the subsequent 
memory of that state , as one of peace and freedom 
from worries, would not be possible. The persistent 



72 


Advaita Vedanta 


factor then is consciousness, but not necessarily of 
any object. This shows again that the essence of 
self is pure consciousness without necessary 
relation to objects. 82 

The identification of objectless consciousness through the 
rational analysis of deep sleep is very important from the point 
of view of Advaita. Normally, we always associate consciousness 
with an object but the phenomenon of deep sleep reveals 
that although consciousness need not always be associated 
with an object, it must always be associated with the subject. 

The third approach to the individual subject identified in 
Advaita enables one to say more about the nature of pure 
consciousness. In this approach that fact that the individual 
subject stands face-to-face with a world of objects is subjected 
to radical rational scrutiny. The first result of such an 
investigation is the reconfiguration of the concept of subject 
and object as commonly understood in philosophy as follows: 

The cognitive situation is usually taken to involve a 
subject and object. The Advaitin substitutes for them 
drk and drsya, the former meaning the self or what 
reveals and the latter, what is revealed. The reason 
for this substitution is that the other division is not 
logically quite satisfactory. The subject includes not 
only drk but also drsya. It is really a complex of the 
self and the not self. This is clear from statements 
like I know myself-,, where myself refers to some 
thought or feeling or, as Hume said, ‘some 
particular perception or other, of heat or cold, light 
or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure.’ These 
perceptions, being observable, are drsya and 
necessarily point to some center of consciousness 
beyond them. 85 

The drk or the individual subject, as the center of pure 
consciousness, upon analysis, displays certain striking 
properties. 



Advaila Vedanta: /I Rational Approach 


73 


It is impossible to think of the absence of drk —as 
having ceased to be or as not having yet come to 
be, for that thought itself would imply the presence 
of drk. Hence drk, in some sense, should be regarded 
as having neither beginning nor end, and therefore 
as eternal or timeless. 

...We have seen that ark cannot have internal parts. 

It cannot be externally related to other drks, for a 
similar reason, viz., that it is not possible to think of 
any dividing line between them. The only way in 
which we can distinguish between one drk and 
another is by reference to their content or the 
objects they reveal. In themselves, they are 
indistinguishable. That is, drk is one or, more strictly, 
not many. 84 

In this way the pure subject is not only external and one, it 
can also be considered all-comprehensive, if the drsya is 
considered dependent on the drk and therefore accounted 
for by drk, for then drk becomes “all-comprehensive, in the 
sense that there is nothing outside it”, directly or indirectly. 

VIII 

The concept of contradiction plays a special role in logical 
analysis. We would do well, therefore, to analyze its role in 
Advaitic rationality. 

In terms of pragmatic reason, Advaitic thinking would 
distinguish between contradiction between one thought and 
another, and between thought and practice. One could 
think of a situation, for instance, in which an individual is 
constantly changing his pattern of thought, so that what one 
says today may contradict what one said fifteen days ago. 
However, one might yet, in both these phases, be consistent 
in terms of thought and practice. Suppose, for instance, that 
fifteen days ago a person believed in violence and also behaved 
violently. Now, fifteen days later, the same person comes to 



74 


Advaita Vedanta 


believe in non-violence and also behaves non-violently. Then 
over this fifteen-day period he would have exhibited 
contradiction at the level of thought and also at the level of 
practice, but not at the level of the relationship between 
thought and practice. In terms of practical reason, as it were, 
one could display a pattern of four possibilities. 1) 
contradiction between thought and thought ; 2) 
contradiction between practice and practice; 3) thought 
contradicted by practice (when one thinks oneself to be 
detached and may not be) and 4) practice contradicted by 
thought (one may actually be modest and not think of 
oneself as such, as part of being modest!) . Then there is 
the case of th ejivanmukta, a case in which such contradictions 
might be considered unthinkable. This is then how the 
discussion of contradiction might well proceed in terms of 
Advaitic ethics and soteriology. 

In the realm of Advaitic epistemology and ontology, 
however, the discussion of contradiction must be set on a 
different course. The referents of contradiction here are 
thought and experience. In terms of these referents one can 
again came up with a four-fold pattern; 1) the contradiction 
of one experience by another; 2) the contradiction of one 
thought by another; 3) the contradiction of thought by 
experience and 4) the contradiction of experience by thought. 

An example of the contradiction of one experience by 
another is provided by the experience of what was thought to 
be snake turning out to be a rope. The experience of the 
rope contradicts the experience of the snake. Similarly, the 
experience of waking contradicts the experience of sleep. 
Note, however, that while in the first case the contradicting 
experience of the rope falsified the contradicted 
experience; this cannot be said of the contradiction involved 
in the waking and sleeping states. One can either accept 
both on their face value, or claim that each falsifies the other. 
This is possible because they belong to two different kinds 
of consciousness, unlike the case of the rope-snake example. 



Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach 


75 


An example of the contradiction of one thought by 
another is provided when it is argued that the effect and 
(material) cause may be two distinct entities. This is 
contradicted by the thought that the two distinct entities 
require a third entity to relate them, but then this third 
entity will have to be related by a fourth and fifth entity to 
the first and so forth, leading to infinite regress. 

The example of the contradiction of thought by experience 
will be provided by the case in which one might think it 
unthinkable that one could experience a state in which one 
is neither aware of oneself nor of the world. Yet the experience 
of dreamless sleep provides precisely an example of such a 
state, and so might samadhi. 

The example of the contradiction of experience by thought 
is provided by the apparent movement of the sun across the 
sky. It is given by experience but contradicted by astronomical 
knowledge. 

For the rational presentation of Advaitic ontology, however, 
this grid has to be ratched up a notch to another level: to the 
contradiction between the non-contradictable and the 
contradictable. 

It was mentioned earlier how “universal, pure existence 
(or consciousness) is the only thing whose contradiction is 
unthinkable. Sankara calls it, therefore, Supreme reality 
(Paramarthika Satta). He thus logically arrives also at this 
conception of reality as that which persists uncontradicted 
through all forms of existence in all places and times.” 22 As 
distinguished from such existence in general, existence in 
the particular suffers from a liability. “About any definite or 
particular form of existence, which may appear in our 
experience, we can never be certain that it may not be 
supplanted by a contradictory experience arising in future. 
So the theoretical or logical possibility of it being contradicted 
is always there.” 86 

The distinction between the contradiction of snake by 
rope; and of sleep by waking become relevant when it is 



Advaita Vedanta 


claimed that rationally speaking, even two objects like pot 
ghata and cloth pata falsify each other. 

Rope and snake experienced in the same waking state as 
distinct objects do not falsify each other; when the same object 
which was perceived as a snake turns out to be a rope, one 
(snake) is falsified by the other (rope); waking and dreaming 
may be credibly said to falsify' each other but they belong to 
two different orders of experience. It is true that both pot 
and cloth may be falsified, as particulars, in relation to 
universal existence but they can be said to mutually falsify 
each other only from the perspective of universal existence, 
as the uncontadictable reality in the light of which not only 
are both contradicted but also mutually so, even though they 
are at the same ontological level. In other works, change 
involves the possibility of contradiction, possible change 
therefore involves the possibility of contradiction but note 
that experientially the pot can never change into cloth because 
of acceptance of satkaryavada. From the point of view of 
satkaryavada both effects are false and doubly so but only 
mutually in relation to the highest level. 

The paradox is that although logically the pot and cloth 
falsify each other on account of changeability, experientially 
they cannot change into each other. Logic from the highest 
level delimits experience of particulars, while logic at the same 
level limits experience to particulars. The rope can apparently 
turn into a snake but can the pot turn into cloth? No, but 
what they do is “weaken and undermine each other’s claim 
to indubitable reality” by reinforcing each other’s 
particularity. 



PART III 




Advaita Vedanta: 

An Experiential Approach 


The experiential approach to the study of Advaita Vedanta 
provides a third possible way of approaching the subject. An 
initial validation for such an approach is provided by an 
attempt to answer the following question : Why should not a 
rational approach suffice either by itself, or in combination 
with the scriptural approach, to provide an introduction to 
Advaita Vedanta? Of course from a certain point of view it 
can. In fact, either the scriptural or the rational could suffice 
by itself for that matter. However, a more comprehensive 
perspective might lead one to conclude otherwise. Our 
experience of life reveals that life is characterized by three 
states of consciousness—waking, dreaming and deep sleep. 
A philosophy of life must take all three into account and 
account for all three. Rationality, however, is a characteristic 
of human mind only during the waking state, although 
mental activity in some form is common to both the waking 
state and the dreaming state. In the state of deep sleep, 
even mental activity, or at least conscious mental activity, 
also ceases. Thus rationality only characterizes a part of life; 
can it be used to account for the whole of life? The same 
argument can be given another form in terms of conscious 
mental activity, even during the waking state. Mental activity, 
in the waking state, also includes aesthetic and emotional 
experience. Thus rationality is only one, if privileged, aspect 
of this manifold mental activity. We give premium to 
rationality because we associate it with the philosophical 
enterprise in which we are engaged. Thus, its role gives it a 
certain status in view of the nature of the task we are engaged 
in but it is useful to be reminded of the fact that there is 



80 


Advaita Vedanta 


more to life than logic. What an electrifying insight this must 
have been before it became a cliche. 

How then might Advaita Vedanta be presented, if it took 
all the states of existence and not just one (of which the 
experience of rationality is so striking a feature) into account? 

II 

One important feature of the experiential exposition of 
Advaita Vedanta is to question the finality of the distinction 
between waking and dreaming and deep sleep. In our 
everyday approach to life, if we were asked to pair out any 
two of them and separate the one left out as an indication 
in our judgement of their relative importance, then nine 
times out of ten we will be inclined to pair dreaming and 
deep sleep as one unit, and separate the waking state as the 
one in which we are really alive. The waking state lies at the 
center of our life. After all, we live from day-to-day, not night- 
to-night. The night is spent in repose and in experiencing 
the states of dreaming and deep sleep. 

The Advaita approach to the matter, however, is more 
inclined to pair the states of waking and dreaming, and 
prefers to separate deep sleep from them for reasons which 
will now be explained. Advaita Vedanta is inclined to pair 
the waking and dreaming states together, notwithstanding 
their differences, because both of them are equally 
characterized by mental activity. According to the Advaitic 
view our concepts of space, time and causality differ in the 
waking and dreaming states, in contrast to the common view 
that these concepts are present in the waking state and absent 
in the dreaming state. According to Advaitins the only real 
difference between the two is duration—waking is a longer 
stretch of dreaming and that is why in the waking state we 
can recall we slept but not vice versa. 

Many thinkers—both Eastern and Western—have felt that 
drawing a firm distinction between waking and dreaming 
presents difficulties. Among Western thinkers Descartes and 
Pascal may be specially mentioned. Descartes wrote: 



Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


81 


When I consider the matter carefully, I do not find 
a single characteristic by means of which I can 
certainly determine whether I am awake or 
whether I am dreaming. The vision of a dream 
and the experience of my waking state are so much 
alike that I am completely puzzled and I don’t 
reallv know if I am not dreaming at this moment. 87 

And Pascal said : 

If a dream comes to us every night we should be as 
much occupied with it as by the thing we see every 
day, and if an artisan were certain that he would 
dream every night for twelve hours that he was a 
king, then he would be just as happy who dreams 
every night for twelve hours that he is an artisan. 88 

In the East, the Indian king Janaka and the Chinese 
philosopher Chuang Tzu were baffled, it seems, by similar 
experiences. There was once a famous Indian king called 
Janaka. “King Janaka had a dream that he was a beggar. On 
his waking up he asked his guru ‘Am I a king dreaming of 
being a beggar or a beggar dreaming of being a king?” 89 

Chuang Tzu (c. 369-286 B.C ), second in importance only 
to Lao Tzu as a representative of Taoism, raises for “epistemo¬ 
logy... the ultimately unanswerable question”: 90 

Once upon a time, Chuang Chou [ i.e. Chuang 
Tzu] dreamed that he was a butterfly, a butterfly 
fluttering about, enjoying it. It did not know that 
it was Chuang Chou again. But he didn’t know 
whether he was Chuang Chou who had dreamed 
that he was a butterfly, or whether he was a 
butterfly dreaming that he was Chuang Chou. 
Between Chuang Chou and the butterfly there 
must he some distinction. This is what is called 
the transformation of things. 91 

In a less celebrated and more elaborate passage Chuang 
Tzu further considers the plausibility of the dream-like nature 
of life. 



82 


Advaila Vedanta 


Those who dream of a merry drinking party may 
the next morning wail and weep. Those who 
dream of wailing and weeping may in the morning 
go off gaily to hunt. While they dream they do not 
know that they are dreaming. In their dream, they 
may even try to interpret their dream. Only when 
they have awakened do they begin to know that 
they have dreamed. By and by comes a great 
awakening, and then we shall know that it has all 
been a great dream. Yet all the while the fools 
think that they are awake; this they are sure of. 

With minute nicety, they discriminate between 
princes and grooms. How stupid! Confucius and 
you are both in a dream. And when I say that you 
are in a dream, this is also a dream. This way of 
talking may be called paradoxical. If after ten 
thousand generations we could once meet a great 
sage who knew how to explain the paradox, it 
would be as though we met him after only one 
morning or one evening. 92 

A similar tendency to treat the waking state as analogous 
to dreaming also appears in Buddhist thought, as the 
following passage indicates: 

‘The senses are as though illusions and their objects 
as dreams. For instance a sleeping man might 
dream that he had made love to a beautiful 
country girl, and he might remember her when 
he awoke. WTiat do you think ...does the beautiful 
girl he dreamed of really exist?” 

“No, Lord.” 

“And would the man be wise to remember the 
girl of his dreams, or to believe that he had really 
made love to her ?” 

“No, Lord, because she doesn’t really exist at all, 
how could he have made love to her—though of 



Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


83 


course he might think he did under the influence 
of weakness or fatigue.” 

“In just the same way a foolish and ignorant man 
of the world sees pleasant forms and believes in 
their existence. Hence he is pleased, and so he 
feels passion and acts accordingly 91 ’ 

Mystics even more than philosophers are inclined to 
disregard the distinction, at some level, between waking and 
dreaming, as in the following story narrated by Sri Ramakrsna 
Paramhamsa (1836-1886): 

A son was born to a king. He was the only child 
and was therefore the apple of the eye of both the 
king and queen. The prince became a favorite with 
all and as he grew older he was taught all the arts 
and the sciences. One day, all of a sudden, the 
prince fell ill. The malady went on getting worse 
and even the best physician of the kingdom found 
that all treatments were of no avail. Both the king 
and the queen never left his side day and night 
and the most competent physician and nurses 
continuously attended him. The king was 
exhausted by his constant vigil and one night he 
could not resist falling asleep. He was awakened 
by the sound of crying and weeping and learnt 
that prince had passed away while he was asleep. 

The king sat as if he was stupefied, without 
speaking a single word. The queen asked him how 
it was that on the passing away of the only a child 
whom he loved so much there was not a single 
drop of tears in his eyes. The king said, ‘Oh queen, 
when I fell asleep I dreamt that I had become a 
monarch of a large kingdom, much larger than 
mine, and the father of seven worthy and ideal 
princes, each of whom was well trained in the art 
of administration. I handed over the charge of my 
kingdom to them and thereafter I was spending 



Advaita Vedanta 


8'i 


my days in peace and happiness with you. And now 
this tragedy has taken place and I am unable to 
make up my mind whether I should lament for 
the child that has left us today or whether I should 
mourn the loss of the seven sons and a vast 
kingdom: I see no difference in the two bereave¬ 
ments and to me the world has become nothing 
but a dream’. 94 

Ramana Maharsi (d. 1950) asserts even more directly the 
elusiveness of the distinction. 

All that we see is a dream, whether we see it in the 
dream state or waking state. On account of some 
arbitrary standards about the duration of the 
experience and so on, we call one experience a 
dream and another waking experience. With 
reference to reality both the experiences are 
unreal. A man might have such an experience as 
getting anugrah (grace) in his dream and the 
effects and influence of it on his entire subsequent 
life may be so profound and so abiding that one 
cannot call it unreal, while calling real some trifling 
incident in the waking life that just flits by is causal 
and of no moment and is soon forgotten. Once I 
had an experience, a vision or a dream whatever 
you may call it. I and some others including 
Chadwick who had a walk on the hill. Returning 
we were walking along a huge street with great 
buildings on either side. Showing the street and 
the buildings, I asked Chadwick and others 
whether anybody could say that what we were 
seeing was dream and they all replied, What fool 
■will say so ? and we walked along and entered the 
hall and the vision or dream ceased, or [we] woke 
up. What are we to call this? 95 

A story told about the fifth Sikh Guru, Guru Arjun (1563- 
1606) also makes a similar point. It is said that a king came 
to visit him but 



Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


85 


when he heard the musicians hymning the Guru’s 
composition saying “O friend, the Writ thy God 
has written out for thee can be obliterated not”, 
he became anxious in the mind. On being 
questioned, the Guru explained to the visitor that 
the Writ that God writes is based upon one’s own 
deeds. This gravely disappointed the King who 
asked:—“If such be the case what is the need of 
the Guru’s Grace or even of doing or being good, 
if what has to happen must come to pass.” The 
Guru replied:—-“Of this we would talk tomorrow.” 

In the night, the King dreamt that he had become 
a sweeper, clothed in tatters, dealing with filth all 
the time and living the life of a miserable wretch. 

He woke up, disturbed, in the morning and told 
the Guru so. The Guru replied: “O devotee, you 
slept as a King and in the dream became a poor 
wretch. Your dream-state was as valid at the time 
of your dreaming, as is your kingly state which you 
really possess. Such is the nature of the Guru’s 
Grace that no matter what your past or present, 
you pass through, and are affected by it, only as 
one passes through a dream, till one’s self awakens 
to realise the essential kingly nature of one’s 
soul”. 96 

The state of deep sleep presents a radical contrast to the 
states of waking and dreaming. The most striking features 
of this contrast are two-fold: (1) that in deep sleep one loses 
awareness of both oneself and of the world—outer as well as 
inner. In the waking state, one is aware of the world of 
external objects; in the dream state, one is aware of a world 
of external objects also (which upon waking are discovered 
to have been inner); but this crucial distinction disappears 
in deep sleep. (2) Although one thus undergoes loss of 
individuality in deep sleep yet upon waking one identifies 
oneself with the same person who went to sleep. This 
establishes that identity can survive loss of individuality. These 



86 


Advaila Vedanta 


two facts—that in deep sleep one loses all sense of 
individuality (as well as of the world) and further that despite 
this lapse in individuality one doesn’t suffer loss of identity— 
are considered such sensational features of deep sleep that 
they—for the Advaitin—place deep sleep in a category by 
itself, in comparison with waking and dreaming taken 
together. 

III 

We revert now to the discussion of three states as separate 
ones, after noticing that the analysis of deep sleep leads us 
to the conclusion that there must be some entity which 
survives discontinuity as sharp as the one involved in the state 
of deep sleep* wherein even our sense of individuality is 
lost. We are now led to a larger question: what constitutes 
the underlying link even between the two different senses 
of individualities experienced by us in the waking and 
dreaming state respectively? Thus there is something which 
underlies and sustains both the changing individualities in 
waking and dreaming states, and the loss of individuality as 
such in the state of deep sleep. 

One, thus, arrives at the concept of the pure subject, in 
the absence of which the three separate states couldn’t 
possibly constitute the experience of a single person. 

This is the experiential counterpart to the scriptural saksi 
and the rational drk. 

IV 

Another way of approaching Advaita Vedanta experientially 
is to view the hierarchy of the three states—listed in that 
order as waking, dreaming and deep sleep—in two different 
but complementary ways. 

One can employ the analysis of the three states in order 
to indicate both the nature of this pure subject, and how it 
might be discovered. This dual thrust of the fresh analysis of 
the three states is the clear implication, for instance, of some 
of the remarks by Ramana Mahar?i. On the one hand, he 



Advaila Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


87 


admits that, in a sense, the state of deep sleep is closer to 
the state of the pure subject as “the sleep state is free from 
thoughts and their impression on the individual.” 97 Yet, at 
the same time, he warns that one should not “therefore desire 
to be always in sleep” because the “incentive to realize” the 
self “can arise only in the waking state and efforts can only 
be made when one is awake.” 98 

This distinction between what is to be realized and how it 
is to be realized is crucial to an understanding of the way 
these three states of waking, dreaming and deep sleep are 
approached in experiential Advaita. In effect, Ramana, and 
earlier thinkers of Advaita, set up these three states in a 
pattern of opposing hierarchies (somewhat like structure 
and anti-structure). One may designate them as a theoretical 
and the practical approaches to the issue. “The theoretical 
approach shows us where we want to go, i.e., to the 
interiorisation and the unification of consciousness, while 
the practical approach indicates the means to achieve that 
end, i.e., through Advaitic knowledge or yogic will.” 99 

The theoretical approach may be elaborated first. It could 
be argued that as one moves from the waking states 
progressively to dreaming and deep sleep in the world of 
ordinary experience, consciousness becomes increasingly 
rarefied in the empirical subject. In the waking state, objects 
are experienced in the external world. In the dreaming 
state, objects become a product of the person’s interior 
consciousness. In deep sleep, the distinction between the 
subject and the object dissolves—even the internal division 
within a dream between the experiencing subject and the 
experienced object vanishes. All that is left is the sleeping 
person. But as on waking up the person remembers having 
slept, there must have been some conscious subject that 
witnessed the unconsciousness of sleep. This pure subject 
has to be realized. Its realization is said to put an end to all 
unhappiness. Such is the Advaitin claim, that except for one 
who experientially comes to “know” this pure subject, which 
is known solely by means of itself “on account of its self- 




88 


Advaita Vedanta 


luminosity”, according to Ramana “every man, from king to 
peasant has a certain account of sorrow. Even in cases where 
it seems absent it is only a time factor that makes you think 
so —sooner or later it comes.’’ 1 " That is, until Self-realization 
is achieved. 

This analysis is suggestive in several ways. First, it suggests 
that a radical discontinuity is involved in realizing the pure 
subject, on account of its purity: its total absence of any 
relationship with any object as in deep sleep, as distinguished 
from its interiorised relationship as in dreams or an external 
relation as in the waking state. Thus the knowledge of the 
pure subject is categorically different from the knowledge 
or absence of it which arises in a subject-object context, even 
though this latter type of knowledge is itself qualitatively 
different in waking, dreaming and deep sleep. Second, as 
the realization of pure subjectivity entails the total elimination 
of any form of object-contextuality, the realization of the 
pure subject is a purely negative enterprise, in the sense 
that all objects have to be eliminated at all levels—including 
the possibility of a subject in a state of relation to no objects. 
The subject must be just that. “When non-self disappears, 
the self alone remains. To make room it is enough that 
cramping is removed. Space is not brought in afresh. Say 
more space is there even in cramping.” 101 This passage serves 
to explain the comment that while in ordinary experience 
the “true self-cannot be known, it doesn’t therefore remain 
unrealized, for it is self-revealing. In fact it can never be 
wholly suppressed.” 102 It is in this sense perhaps that one 
must understand Ramana’s remark: “The feeling that I have 
not realized is the obstruction to realization. In fact, it is 
already realized...”” 103 

The practical approach toward the realization of the self 
and its relation to the three states of waking, dreaming and 
deep sleep may now be examined. Any effort at realization 
involves volition, so from a practical point of view the 
hierarchy must now be reversed: no volition is possible in 
deep sleep, perhaps more in dreaming but most in the 
waking state. 



Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


89 


The overall point may be graphically presented as follows: 


Deep Sleep 

Dreaming 

Waking 

The three states in terms 
of unification of 
consciousness 


Waking 

Dreaming 

Deep Sleep 
The three states in 
terms of degrees of 
volition in Consciousness 


The special point to note is that one cannot just jump 
from one pyramid to the other. It is somewhat like the 
experience in mountaineering, when we may be standing 
on a cliff atop one mountain and within close reach of 
another mountain. It would be foolhardy, however, to just 
try to jump from the top of a cliff on to the other mountain. 
One must come down all the way and then climb to the top 
of the other. 




What, it might be asked, is the exact nature of the problem 
towards solving which efforts must be directed in the waking 
state? 

The problem is best illustrated with the help of an 
example. Let us take the case of a young lady who is in love 
with her beau and goes out to buy a nice dress to please him. 
She brings that dress home and places it on the table. She 
then reclines on the chair and begins to speculate on the 
romantic possibilities this addition to her wardrobe could 
set in motion. 

She imagines how she will wear the dress in the evening 
and go out for a candle-lit dinner with her friend. She will 
iron the dress with particular care and wear a perfume with 
it. She imagines the possibility of spilling wine on it and 
spoiling the dress (God forbid), and how she will preserve it 
and after years of marriage still keep it though it may be 
worn out by then, and how she will show it to her daughter 
as the dress she wore on the evening her husband proposed 
to her. While she is thus thinking, the phone rings and she 



90 


Advaila Vedanta 


talks to her friend about this fabulous dress she bought in 
the morning, describing in great detail the way it came to 
be purchased. 

Throughout this series of events the actual dress has simply 
been lying on the table. So all her experiences don’t really 
pertain to the dress but to the dress-thought. When she 
thinks of wearing the dress it is really the dress-thought she 
is concerned with—the dress as such is merely lying on the 
table. The web of romantic associations she has woven are 
also woven not around the dress itself, which just lies as an 
item on the table, but around the dress-thought, in her mind. 
When she talks with her friend on the phone she really talks 
of the dress-thought, not the dress itself, which lies on the 
table and is indifferent to the vicissitudes of fortune the 
dress-thought is undergoing. The moment the lady stops 
thinking or talking of the dress-thought—which is what is 
really involved in the thinking or talking about it rather than 
the dress itself—the dress-thought may be said to go back 
into the dress. 

This example serves to illustrate several aspects of the 
problem at hand. It is the Advaitin contention that what we 
are concerned with in the process of ordinary living is not 
the real /but the I-thought, just as what the lady was concerned 
with in exploring her romantic situation was the dress- 
thought and not the dress, even though she may find it 
difficult to draw this distinction. Although the dress as dress- 
thought was the object of so much activity, the dress as such 
just lay passively on the table. It is the Advaitin contention 
that just as it was not the dress but the dress-thought which 
ran the young lady’s life for a while, it is not pure subject— 
the pure I —but the /- thought which runs our lives, divorced 
from the real I but deriving its existence from it, just as the 
dress-thought is divorced from the dress and yet derives its 
existence from it! This I-thought is also called the ego and it 
is said that “those alone who have found out the real nature 
of the ego have seen reality. They will have no more doubts 
or anxiety. ” 104 Even this point can be clarified analogically: 



Advaila Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


91 


just as once one has discovered the nature of the dress- 
thought—which one constantly confused with the dress 
itself—one would also discover the real nature of the dress 
as such, unclouded by the dress-thought. 

In Advaita, it is said that realization of one’s true nature 
entails realizing how the I-thought rises from the real /. ‘To 
say / am this or I am ihat there must be the I. This / is only 
the ego or the I-thought is therefore the root-thought ...find 
out its source. Then all these [other thoughts] will vanish 
and the pure self will remain over .”" 15 Similarly one is told 
that the ego proceeds from the self as a spark from fire. 
“The spark is called the ego. In the case of the ignorant 
man it identifies itself with an object simultaneously with its 
rise. It cannot remain independent of such association with 
objects If its objectifying tendency is killed it remains pure 
and also merges into the source .”" 1 ' 1 This point can also be 
made in relation to the analogy of the dress-thought and 
the dress. When we perceive the dress qua dress without 
dress-thoughts, one can describe the process as either tracing 
dress-thoughts back to their source, the dress, or making 
dress-thoughts merge into the dress. 

Just as one needed to distinguish between the dress and 
the dress-thought, one needs to distinguish between the I 
and the I-thought. “You must distinguish between the I, pure 
in itself, and the I- thought .” 107 “If you stay as the /, your 
being alone, without thought, the /-thought will disappear 
and the delusion will vanish forever .” 108 

This raises the interesting question: are there two Is ? The 
parallel question in terms of the analogy would be—are there 
two dresses ? There is only one dress. Similarly, there is only 
one I. But just as the dress gives rise to the dress-thought, 
the I-thought emerges from the I. Or, one can even say that 
once the dress-thought has arisen, several dress-thoughts in 
various phases arise based on the original dress-thought. 
Thus the sequence runs as follows: dress > dress-thought > 
dress thoughts. This helps explain the following: “The I of 
the dream has vanished. Another I speaks of the dream. 



92 


Advaita Vedanta 


This / was not in the dream. Both the r s are unreal. There 
is the substratum of the mind which continues all along, 
giving rise to so many scenes. With every thought rises /, and 
with its disappearance the I disappears too. So the Is are 
born, and die every moment ,’’" 11 like dress-thoughts 
emerging from moment to moment. Once one knows that 
the dress is lying safely on the table the vicissitudes of the 
dress-thoughts cease to be a cause for concern. 

There are other ways as well in which the analogy of the 
dress and dress-thought is illuminating. For instance, it is 
said in Advaita : “That which makes the enquiry is the ego. 
The / about which the inquiry is made is also the ego. As a 
result of the enquiry the ego ceases to exist .”" 0 Parallel: 
starting as we do from the realm of the dress-thought, it is 
the dress-thought, which inquires into itself. Then it realizes 
it is just the dress-thought and disappears, yielding place to 
the actual dress lying on the table. Again, in Advaita one is 
encouraged to enquire who undergoes the vicissitudes of 
life and discover that only the ego is affected by them, not 
the self, and that “the ego is non-existent.” Parallel: the dress- 
thoughts undergo all the vicissitudes, they do not bind the 
dress itself and the dress-thoughts are non-existent in the 
sense that what really exists is only the dress. Again it is said: 
“Reality is simply the loss of ego.”"' Parallel: the recognition 
of the reality of the dress is simply the loss of dress-thoughts. 
Thus the analogy is helpful in many ways. Let me close by 
poindng out two more instances in which it is helpful in a 
much more dynamic sense—in shedding light on the actual 
pursuit of the spiritual goal. 

It is sometimes said that the realization could be sudden 
or gradual, that is, taking time to steady itself. At times 
Ramana said that “there are no degrees of liberation ,”" 2 
and at other times that “realization takes time to steady 
itself .”" 3 This could also be understood in terms of our 
analogy. Let us imagine that the young lady in the parable is 
suddenly told that her beau has run off with someone else! If 



Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


93 


the lady is shocked to her sense by this revelation the dress 
would immediately become a piece of cloth for her—the 
dress-thoughts would disappear. If, however, she still retained 
affection for the heel who left her, dress-thoughts might 
still occasionally arise from the dress and may only gradually 
subside till the dress become just a piece of cloth (that is, till 
she finds another beau). 

It is also sometimes said that realization is not possible so 
long as one is “aware of an /”; it is only possible upon “being 
the /’. So long as one has thoughts of the dress, one is in a 
sense in a state of alienation from the dress and still in the 
realm of dress-thoughts. But when the dress becomes the 
dress —that is, when all dress-thought disappear, then alone 
it is in its natural and primal state. 

The process of realization may be said to consist of three 
stages. In the first stage one is aware of only the I-thought to 
begin with. One is so carried away by this identification with 
the I-thought to begin with that one doesn’t know there is an 
underlying real / which is quite different from the I-thought, 
although the source of it. In other words, the pure subject, 
though ever present, is never known because of one’s 
identification of existence with the three states of 
consciousness which conceal the pure witness. One must, in 
the second stage, lose sight of the world to experience the 
pure subject. As Ramana explains in this catechetical series: 

When will the realization of the self be gained ? 
When the world, which is what is seen as, has been 
removed, there will be realization of the self which 
is the seer. 

Will there not be the realization of the self—even while 
the world is there (taken as real)? There will not be . 114 

In the third stage, once the pure subject is realized, the 
world is again seen but now as part of the self and not apart 
from it as was the case in the beginning. In terms of our 
analogy one begins with the young lady with her mind full 



94 


Advuiia Vedanta 


of dress-thoughts. In stage two she experiences the actual 
dress to be worn. She cannot see it unless the dress-thoughts 
depart from the mind, so that she can see and experience 
the actual dress. While actually experiencing it ever, the 
thought “this is the dress” is a distraction from it. Finally, 
emerging from the absorption in the dress she can again 
lose herself in dress-thoughts going down the aisle but she is 
aware of the relationship of these dress thoughts to the real 
dress, which was not the case the first time. 

The relation between the dress and the dress-thought 
continues to possess considerable illustrative and therefore 
explanatory power. This becomes apparent, when we explore 
the nature of the /-thought as analyzed in Advaita Vedanta a 
little further. When the “I” thought arises in the context of 
person, it is worth noting that it often takes the form “I-am- 
the-body ”. 113 That is to say—it is not a vague free-floating “I” 
thought and it has a definite if fully undetermined referent. 
Similarly, the dress-thought, in relation to the dress, is not a 
dress thought in general, but assumes the form of “a dress- 
thought” rather than “dress thought” in general, or a 
collection of dresses as it were. “Is there not a name for the 
body? It is that which we take as the name of that particular 
person. When asked who you are, one says, I am Rama. If 
someone calls Rama, that person alone looks back. While 
other bodies have other names, this particular body becomes 
Rama ”" 6 Similarly, other chains of dress thoughts may have 
their own identities, and may arise in different contexts, 
but this chain of dress-thought possesses its own identity— 
and destiny. 

The metaphor on hand can even be developed to indicate 
the relation between the various sheaths mentioned in the 
Upanisads, and its relation to the I and the I-thought. In 
accordance with the doctrine of the various kosas or sheaths, 
an individual is presented as “sheathed” in five of them— 
and at their core lies the true atman or I. But empirically, 
the person exists as an entity covered in these sheaths and 



Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


95 


generated by an “I-thought”. The person is like the young 
lady wrapped up in the dress, but still carried away by the 
“dress-thought” into the reverie she is in. In fact one can 
come to point even more directly here, by undertaking a 
simple exercise. Please sit down at a desk quietly and just 
think of yourself as someone sitting down by the desk quietly. 
What you have in your mind is an 1-thought of yourself sitting 
down by the desk. Similarly, the young lady sitting by herselt 
thinking of doing all kinds of things with the dress on, is 
trafficking in the dress-thought just as we traffic in I-thought. 

Experiential Advaita also draws a distinction between what 
is called manolaya and manonasa. The first term stands for 
the temporary suspension of mental activity and the second 
term for final elimination of mental activity as an obstacle to 
self-realization. The distinction is important in experiential 
Advaita because it is on the basis of this distinction that it 
distinguishes its own samadhi from that which results from 
the practice of Yoga. Ramana Maharsi explains the point as 
follows: 

In deep sleep the mind is merged and not 
destroyed. That which merges reappears. It may 
happen in meditation also. But the mind which is 
destroyed cannot reappear. The yogi’s aim must 
be to destroy it and not to sink into laya. In the 
peace of meditation, laya sometimes ensues but it 
is not enough. It must be supplemented by other 
practices for destroying the mind. Some people 
have gone into yogic samadhi with a trifling 
thought and after a long time awakened in the 
trail of the same thought. In the meantime 
generations have passed in the world. Such a yogi 
has not destroyed his mind. The true destruction 
of the mind is the non- recognition of it as being 
apart from the Self. 117 

The metaphor of the dress is useful here. So long as the 
idea of the wedding persists, the dress-thoughts will continue 



96 


Advaila Vedanta 


to reappear even if they disappear for a while, but once the 
idea of wedding is abandoned altogether, the dress-thoughts 
will cease and stop interfering with one’s perception of the 
dress as such. 

We often talk of the mind. It is one of the claims of 
experiential Advaita that the concept the mind doesn’t bear 
scrutiny. 

What is the mind? The reply which Bhagavan 
[Ramana Maharsi] gives us is thaL mind is nothing 
but (a bundle of) thoughts. If one investigates what 
this mind is, keeping off all thoughts, he will find 
that there is no such thing as mind. 118 

The link between the I and the 1-thought is the mind. When 
it is claimed that there is no mind what is meant is that there 
is no mind apart from the thoughts, just as there is no river 
apart from its flow. Similarly, then, there is no dress-thought 
apart from the bundle of thoughts which have arisen from 
the dress or flow from it. And further: just as if one probed 
these “dress-thoughts” uninterruptedly one will be led back 
to the dress, so also the uninterrupted interrogation of I- 
thoughts will jolt one back to the true /. 

At another level the whole metaphor of the dress and 
dress-thought in a way helps elaborate the way the subtle 
body is said to operate in the psychology of Advaita Vedanta. 
The following account is self-explanatory in this respect. 

Let it not be considered that the mind takes a subtle 
body only in dreams. The same phenomenon takes 
place even in the waking state during flights of 
the mind, for instance in a revery. Suppose we sit 
and imagine in the waking state that we travel to 
far off countries, meet a friend there, talk with 
him or undergo all the vicissitudes of life. The 
mentally projected body in which we seem to 
undergo all these experiences is also our subtle 
body. We know that these subtle bodies we take 
up now and then are transient. When one wakes 



Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


97 


up from a dream, the dream body is gone. In the 
same way the body assumed in day-dreams 
(reveries) is also found to be false, i.e. these bodies 
are the false forms that come to and go away from 
us. Because we exist even in the absence of these 
bodies, they are not WE." 9 

In the course of developing this illustration so far we have 
focused on the emergence of the dress-thought (and then 
even dress-thoughts) from the dress as an example of how 
the I-thought (and then even the many I-thoughts) can arise 
from the real “I”. With a little shift in focus, however, the 
application of this I metaphor to our existential situation 
can also be enlarged. In order to see how this might be 
possible let’s go back to the young lady who imagines wearing 
the dress she has bought when she goes out with her beau 
for the candle-light dinner. 

Let us now visualize her imagining this scene while relaxing 
in her room—that she is sitting next to her beau on a table in 
the restaurant in the dress she has bought. Now note that 
not only is she wearing a dress-thought as she imagines herself 
in the restaurant, she herself, as she imagines herself in the 
restaurant, is not she herself but a thought of herself. For 
she, as she really is, is sitting right there in the room! So it is 
a she-thought (and not she, although the she-thought 
proceeds from her) who is wearing the dress-thought! Now 
note that the dress-thought is an object and she-thought is a 
subject, and the sAe-thought is also wearing the dress-thought— 
that is—the object and subject are interacting but in a world 
of thought —so that their interaction also partakes of the same 
character. The ontological status of all of them, though 
derivative, is the same! This is how Advaita Vedanta is able 
to combine an empirical realism with a transcendental 
idealism. 

Or to put the matter more philosophically: a major issue this 
school of thought has to contend with is not an unexpected 
one: how to reconcile its claim of a metaphysical non-dual reality 
with the apparent plurality of our empirical existence. 




98 


Advaita Vedanta 


Here is a glimpse of the ways in which such a reconciliation 
might be proposed. The range of our experience in the 
empirical world is vertiginously diverse, but a little reflection 
suggests that all of it occurs in one of three states of 
consciousness: when one is awake, when one is dreaming 
and while one is in deep sleep. These three states of 
experience provide a useful handle for talking of our 
empirical world because all the varied experiences we have 
in this world can be slotted as falling within one of these 
three states of consciousness. Now in the waking state physical 
objects are real (at the empirical level). It can thus be 
described as sat or real. Compared to them objects and persons 
encountered in a dream are merely mental in nature and it 
can thus be described as tit, or characterized by immaterial 
conscious-ness. Finally, the experience of deep sleep is 
universally considered restful, blissful and happy. Thus this state 
of consciousness qualifies as dnanda or bliss. Thus the empirical 
reality we experience can be described as follows: 

Waking Sat 

Dreaming Cit 

Deep Sleep Ananda 

Readers will recall, however, that the ultimate reality, at 
the transcendental level, was also described in part I of this 
book as saccidananda Brahman, where Brahman denoted the 
ultimate reality to which the words sat (reality), cit 
(consciousness) and dnanda (bliss) are applied as ways of 
orienting ourselves towards it. 

In other words, the question we are dealing with may be 
rephrased as follows: what is the relationship of the ultimate 
reality as sat, cit and dnanda and our experience of the 
empirical world, which is also capable of being so described. 

The question may be answered with the help of a chart. 



Sat, Cit, Ananda, 

Brahman 

Sat 

Waking 


Git 

Dreaming 

World 

Ananda 

Deep Sleep 





Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


99 


How could the horizontal line become the vertical, in other 
words? Just as a straight rod appears bent when placed in a 
tub full of water, say Advaita Vedanta. That is to say, there is 
something in the nature of the empirical world which 
apparently distorts the ultimate reality when viewed in 
relation with it. The word used to denote this something in 
Advaita Vedanta is maya or avidya. 

But matters get straightened out when one achieves 
enlightenment. One way of moving towards such 
enlightenment or Realisation is to ask the question: if I 
undergo the experience of waking, dreaming and deep 
sleep which as states of consciousness differ so radically from 
one another, then how do I retain my sense of identity 
despite undergoing these different states of experience, and 
the different experiences I have within these states of 
waking, dreaming and deep sleep. There must be some 
unchanging consciousness in me which undergirds my 
consciousness of change of these states of consciousness and 
the changes within them. Such unchanging consciousness 
is called dtman in Advaita Vedanta—which constitutes the 
unchanging core of our being. 

According to Advaita Vedanta this dtman is identical with 
Brahman. They are not two. It is this understanding of non¬ 
dualism—that the dtman and Brahman are not two distinct 
entities but identically one—which represents experientially 
the most resonant dimension of Advaitic non-dualism. This is 
the truth but somehow it has become warped and it is the 
goal of Advaita Vedanta to help us straighten it out. 

VI 

In analysing the experiential approach so far we have stuck 
to the experience of ordinary human beings. It may not be 
out of place now at least to refer to the experiences of an 
extraordinary kind which have a bearing on Advaita Vedanta. 

We have some accounts of mystical experiences of the 
Advaitic variety from the accounts of the lives of mystics of 
the twentieth century, which bear on the present discussion. 



100 


Advaita Vedanta 


They are such as are best shared rather than explained. 

The first of these is from the life of Swami Vivekananda 
(1863-1902) who bore the name Narendra Nath Dutt, or 
Naren for short, before he became a monk. He ultimately 
came to acknowledge Sri Ramakrsna Paramhamsa(1836- 
1886) as his master. The relevance of the following account 
of a spiritual incident between the two will not be lost on 
students of Advaita Vedanta. 

Thus one day the Master told Narendranath many 
things indicating the oneness ofjlva and Brahman 
of the non-dual philosophy. He heard those words, 
undoubtedly with attention, but he could not 
comprehend them and went to Hazra at the end 
of the Master’s talk. Smoking and discussing those 
things again with Hazra, he said, ‘Can it ever be 
possible that the waterpot is God, the cup is God, 
whatever we see and all of us are God?’ Shri Hazra 
also joined Narendra in thus ridiculing the idea 
and both of them burst into laughter. The Master 
was till then in the state of partial external 
consciousness. Hearing Narendra laugh, he came 
out of his room like a boy with his wearing cloth in 
his armpit and, coming to them smiling, said 
affectionately, ‘What are you both talking about?’ 

He then touched Narendra and went into 
samadhi. 

Narendra said to us afterwards, ‘There was a 
complete revolution in the state of my mind in a 
moment at the wonderful touch of the Master. I 
was aghast to see actually that there was nothing 
in the whole universe except God. But I remained 
silent in spite of seeing it, wondering how long 
that state would last. But that inebriation did not 
at all diminish that day. I returned home; it was all 
the same there; it seemed to me that all that I saw 
was He. I sat far my meal when I saw that all -food, 



Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


101 


plate, the one who was serving as well as myself— 
were nothing but He. I took a mouthful or two 
and sat quiet. My mother’s affectionate words— 
“why do you sit quiet; why don’t you eat?”— 
brought me to consciousness and I began eating 
again. Thus, I had that experience at the time of 


eating or drinking, sitting or lying, going to the 


college or taking a stroll. I was always overwhelmed 


with a sort of indescribable intoxication. When I 


walked along the streets and saw a carriage coming 
along before me I did not feel inclined, as at other 
times, to move away, lest it should collide with me. 
For, I thought, “I am also that and nothing but 
that”. My hands and feet always remained 
insensible at that time. I felt no satisfaction 


whatever when I took my food. It seemed to me as 
if some one else was eating the meal... When that 
overwhelming intoxication diminished a little, the 
world appeared to me to be a dream. Going for a 
walk on the bank of the Hedua tank, I knocked 
my head against the iron railings round it to see 
whether what I saw were dream-rails or actual ones. 


On account of the insensibility of my hands and 
feet I was afraid whether I was not going to have 
paralysis. I could not escape that terrible 
intoxicating mood and overwhelming condition 
for some time. When I came to the normal state, I 
thought that that was indication of non-dual 
knowledge. So what is written in the Sastras about 
it is by no means untrue. Since then I could never 
doubt the truth of non-duality. 120 


The second account is drawn from the life of Ramana 
Maharsi (1879-1950) who is regarded as one of the great 
Advaitins of our age. He underwent the following precocious 
experience in 1896. 


It was about six weeks before I left Madurai for good 



102 


Advaita Vedanta 


that the great change in my life took place. It was 
so sudden. One day I sat alone on the first floor of 
my uncle’s house. I was in my usual health. I seldom 
had any illness. I was a heavy sleeper. When I was at 
Dindigul in 1891 a huge crowd had gathered close 
to the room where I slept and tried to rouse me by 
shouting and knocking at uie door, all in vain, and 
it was only by their getting into my room and giving 
me a violent shake that I was roused from my torpor. 
This heavy sleep was rather a proof of good health. 
I was also subject to fits of half-awake sleep at night. 
My wily playmates, afraid to trifle with me when I 
was awake, would go to me when I was asleep, rouse 
me, take me all round the playground, beat me, 
cuff me, sport with me, and bring me back to my 
bed—and all the while I would put up with 
everything with a meekness, humility, forgiveness, 
and passivity unknown to my waking state. When 
the morning broke I had no remembrance of the 
night’s experiences. But these fits did not render 
me weaker or less fit for life and were hardly to be 
considered a disease. So, on that day as I sat alone 
there was nothing wrong with my health. But 
sudden and unmistakable fear of death seized me. 
I felt I was going to die. Why I should have so felt 
cannot now be explained by anything felt in my 
body. Nor could 1 explain it to myself then. I did 
not however trouble myself to discover if the fear 
was well grounded. I felt I was going to die, and at 
once set about thinking out what I should do. I did 
not care to consult doctors or elders or even friends. 
I felt I had to solve the problem myself then and 
there. 

The shock of fear of death made me at once 
introspective, or introverted. I said to myself mentally, 
i.e., without uttering the words—‘Now, death has 
come. What does it mean? What is it that is dying? 



Advaila Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


103 


This body dies.’ I at once dramatised the scene of 
death. I extended my limbs and held them rigid 
as though rigor-mortis had set in. I imitated a corpse 
to lend an air of reality to my further investigation, 
I held my breath and kept my mouth closed, 
pressing the lips together so that no sound might 
escape. Let not the word I or any other word be 
uttered! Well then, said I to myself, ‘this body is 
dead. It will be carried stiff to the burning ground 
and there burnt and reduced to ashes. But with 
the death of this body, am “I” dead? Is the body 
“I”? This body is silent and inert. But I feel the full 
force of my personality and even the sound “I” 
within myself,—apart from the body. So “I” am a 
spirit, a thing transcending the body. The material 
body dies, but the spirit transcending it cannot be 
touched by death. I am therefore the deathless 
spirit.’ All this was not a mere intellectual process, 
but flashed before me vividly as living truth, 
something which I perceived immediately, without 
any argument almost. 1 was something very real, 
the only real thing in that state, and all the 
conscious activity that was connected with my body 
was centred on that. The / or my self was holding 
the focus of attention by a powerful fascination 
from that time forwards. Fear of death had 
vanished at once and forever. Absorption in the 
self has continued from that moment right up to 
this time. Other thoughts may come and go like 
the various notes of a musician, but the /continues 
like the basic or fundamental sruti note which 
accompanies and blends with all other notes. 
Whether the body was engaged in talking, reading, 
or anything else, I was still centred on I. Previous 
to that crisis I had no clear perception of myself 
and was not consciously attracted to it. I had felt 
no direct perceptible interest in it, much less any 



104 


Advaita Vedanta 


permanent disposition to dwell upon it. The 
consequences of this new habit were soon noticed 
in my life. 121 

Paul Brunton offers the following abbreviated account. 


Maharsi told once how he got realization. On the 
day his father died he felt puzzled by death and 
pondered over it, whilst his mother and brothers 
wept. He thought for hours and after the corpse 
was cremated he got by analysis to the point of 
perceiving that it was the / which makes the body 
to see, to run, to walk and to eat. “I now know this 
/but my father’s / has left the body”. 122 


The third account is the report of a talk byj. Krishnamurti 
(1895-1986). Whether Krishnamurti should be installed in 
the Advaitic pantheon is a matter of debate, therefore a 
word of explanation might be required by way justifying the 
inclusion of the excerpt. One of the chief tenets of Advaita 
Vedanta, as scripturally propounded, is the claim that 
realization is achieved not by action {karma) but jnana 
(insight); that what transcends action cannot be achieved 
by action. The following discourse of Krishnamurti is 
potentially illuminating in this respect. 

Krishnamurti : For most of us, our whole life is based 
on effort, some kind of volition. And we cannot 
conceive of an action that is not based on it. Our 
social, economic, and so-called spiritual life, is a 
series of efforts, always culminating in a certain 
result. We think effort is essential. So we are now 
going to find out if it is possible to live differently, 
without this constant battle. 


Why do we make effort? Put simply, it is in order 
to achieve a result, to become something, to reach 
a goal, isn’t it? If we do not make an effort, we 
think we shall stagnate. We have an idea about 
the goal towards which we are constantly striving; 



Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


105 


and this striving has become part of our life. If we 
want to alter, to bring about a radical change in 
ourselves, we make a tremendous effort to 
eliminate old habits, to resist the habitual 
environmental influences, and so on. So we are 
used to this series of efforts in order to find or 
achieve something, in order to live at all. 

Now, is not all such effort the activity of the self? Is 
not effort self-centred activity? And, if we make 
an effort from the centre of the self, it must 
inevitably produce more conflict, more confusion, 
more misery. Yet we keep on making effort after 
effort; and very few of us realize that the self- 
centred activity of effort does not clear up any of 
our problems. On the contrary, it increases our 
confusion and our misery and our sorrow. Or we 
know this, and yet continue hoping somehow to 
break through this self-centred activity of effort, 
the action of the will. 

This is our problem—Is it possible to understand 
anything without effort? Is it possible to see what 
is real, what is true, without introducing the action 
of the will, which is essentially based on the self, 
the me? And if we do not make an effort, is there 
not a danger of deterioration, of going to sleep, 
of stagnation? Perhaps, as I am talking, we can 
experiment with this individually, and see how far 
we can go through this question. For I feel that 
what brings happiness, quietness, tranquillity of the 
mind, does not come through any effort. A truth 
is not perceived through any volition, through any 
action of will. And if we can go into it very carefully 
and diligently, perhaps we shall find the answer. 

How do we react when a truth is presented? Take, 
for example, the problem of fear. We realize that 
our activity and our being and our whole existence 



106 


Advaita Vedanta 


would be fundamentally altered if there was no fear 
of any kind in us. We may see that, we may see the 
truth of it; and thereby there is freedom from fear. 
But for most of us, when a fact, a truth, is put before 
us, what is our immediate response? Please, 
experiment with what I am saying; please do not 
merely listen. Watch your own reactions; and find 
out what happens when a truth, a fact, is out before 
you—such as ‘any dependence in relationship 
destroys relationship’. Now, when a statement of 
that kind is made, what is your response? Do you 
see, are you aware of, the truth of it, and does 
dependency thereby cease? Or have you an idea 
about the fact? Here is a statement of truth. Do we 
experience the truth of it, or do we create an idea 
about it? 

If we can understand this process of the creation 
of idea, then we shall perhaps understand the 
whole process of effort. Because once we have 
created the idea, then effort comes into being. 
Then the problem arises, what to do, how to act? 
That is, we see that psychological dependence on 
another is a form of self-fulfilment; it is not love; 
in it there is conflict, fear, the desire to fulfil 
oneself through another, jealousy, and so on, 
which corrode. We see that psychological 
dependence on another embraces all these facts. 
Then, we proceed to create the idea, do we not? 
We do not directly experience the fact, the truth 
of it; but, we look at it, and then create an idea of 
how to be free from dependence. We see the 
implications of psychological dependence, and 
then we create the idea of how to be free from it. 
We do not directly experience the truth, which is 
the liberating factor. But out of the experience of 
looking at that fact we create an idea. We are 
incapable of looking at it directly, without ideation. 



Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


107 


Then, having created the idea, we proceed to carry 
out that idea into action. Then we try to bridge 
the gap between idea and action—in which effort 
is involved. 


So can we not look at the truth without creating 
ideas? It is almost instinctive with most of us: when 


ccsm utfiirsrr 
jouie l.llllig 


iv.uiatv.ij 


create an idea about it. And I think if we can 
understand why we do this so instinctively, almost 
unconsciously, then perhaps we shall understand 
if it is possible to be free from effort. 


Why then do we create ideas about truth? Surely 
that is important to find out, is it not? Either we 
see the truth nakedly, as it is, or we do not. But 
why do we have a picture about it, a symbol, a word, 
an image, which necessitates a postponement, the 
hope of an eventual result? So can we hesitantly 
and guardedly go into this process of why the mind 
creates the image, the idea—that I must be this or 
that, that I must be free from dependence, and 
so on? We know very well that when we see 
something very clearly, experience it directly, 
there is a freedom from it. It is that immediacy 
that is vital, not the picture or the symbol of the 
truth—on which all systems and philosophies and 
deteriorating organizations are built. So is it not 
important to find out why the mind, instead of 
seeing the thing directly and simply, and 
experiencing the truth of it immediately, creates 
an idea about it? 


I do not know if you have thought about this. It 
may perhaps be something new. And to find the 
truth of it, please do not merely resist. Do not say, 
‘What would happen if the mind did not create 
the idea? It is its function to create ideas, to 
verbalize, to recall memories, to recognize, to 




108 


Advaila Vedanta 


calculate’. We know that. But the mind is not free; 
and it is only when the mind is capable of looking 
at the truth totally, completely, without any barrier, 
that there is freedom. 

So our problem is—why does the mind, instead of 
seeing the thing immediately and experiencing it 
directly, indulge in sll tHese idecis. Is this not one 
of the habits of the mind? Something is presented 
to us, and immediately there is the old habit of 
creating an idea, a theory about it. And the mind 
likes to live in habit. Because without habit the 
mind is lost. If there is not a routine, a habitual 
response to which it has become accustomed, it 
feels confused, uncertain. 

That is one aspect. Also, does not the mind seek a 
result? Because in the result is permanence. And 
the mind hates to be uncertain. It is always seeking 
security in different forms—through beliefs, through 
knowledge, through experience. And when that is 
quesdoned there is a disturbance, anxiety. And so 
the mind, avoiding uncertainty, seeks security for 
itself by making efforts to achieve a result. 

I hope you are actually observing your own minds 
in operation. If you are not, then you will not 
experience, your mind will remain on the verbal 
level. But—if I may suggest—if you can observe 
your own mind in operation, and watch how it 
thinks, how it reacts, when a truth is out before it, 
then you will experience step-by-step what I am 
talking about. Then there will be an extraordinary 
experience. And it is this direct approach, this 
direct experience of what truth is that is so 
essential for bringing about a creative life. 

So why does the mind create these ideas, instead 
of directly experiencing? Why does the mind 



Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 


109 


intervene? As we have said, it is habit. Also, the 
mind wants to achieve a result. We all want to 
achieve a result. In listening to me, are you looking 
for a result? You are, aren’t you? The mind is 
seeking a result; it sees that dependence is 
destructive, and therefore it wants to be free of it. 
Rut the very desire to be free creates the idea. 
The mind is not free; but the desire to be free 
creates the idea of freedom as the goal towards 
which it must work. And thereby effort comes into 
being. And that effort is self-centred; it does not 
bring freedom. Instead of depending on a person, 
you depend on an idea or on an image. So your 
effort is only self-enclosing; it is not liberating. 

Now, can the mind, realizing that it is caught in 
habit, be free from habit—not have an idea that it 
should achieve freedom as an eventual goal, but 
see the truth that the mind is caught in habit, 
directly experience it? And, similarly, can the mind 
see that it is pursuing incessantly a permanence 
for itself, a goal that it must achieve, a God, a truth, 
a virtue, a state of being, or whatever, and is 
thereby bringing about this action of will, with all 
its complications? And when we see that, is it not 
possible to experience the truth of something 
directly without all the paraphernalia of 
verbalization? You may objectively see a fact, in that 
there is no ideation, no creation of idea, symbol, 
desire. But subjectively, inwardly, it is entirely 
different. Because there we want a result; there is 
the craving to be something, to achieve, to 
become—in which all effort is born. 

I feel that to see what is true from moment to 
moment, without any effort, but directly to 
experience it, is the only creative existence. Because 
it is only in moments of complete tranquillity that 



10 


Advaita Vedanta 


you discover something—not when you are making 
an effort, whether it is under the microscope or 
inwardly. It is only when the mind is not agitated, 
not caught in habit, not trying to achieve a result, 
not trying to become something—it is only when it 
is not doing these things, when it is really tranquil, 
when there is no effort, no movement—that there 
is a possibility of discovering something new. 

Surely, that is freedom from the self, that is the 
abnegation of the me —and not the outward 
symbols, whether you possess this or that virtue or 
not. But freedom comes into being only when you 
understand your own processes, conscious as well 
as unconscious. It is possible only when we go fully 
into the different processes of the mind. And as 
most of us live in a state of tension, in constant 
effort, it is essential to understand the complexity 
of effort, to see the truth that effort does not bring 
virtue, that effort is not love, that effort does not 
bring about the freedom that truth alone can 
give—which is direct experiencing. For that, one 
has to understand the mind, one’s own mind— 
not somebody else’s mind, not what somebody else 
says about it. You may read all the volumes ever 
written but they will be utterly useless. For you 
must observe your own mind, and penetrate it 
more and more deeply, and experience the thing 
directly as you go along. Because there is the living 
quality, not in the things of the mind. And the 
mind, to find its own processes, must not be 
enclosed by its own habits, but must be free 
occasionally to look. Therefore, it is important to 
understand this whole process of effort. For effort 
does not bring about freedom. Effort is only more 
and more self-enclosing, more and more 
destructive, outwardly as well as inwardly, in 
relationship with one or with many. 123 



Conclusion 


A verse, popular in India, claims to summarize the teachings 
of the school of Advaita Vedanta in just half of a verse: 

Brahman is real; the world is an illusory appearance; 
and the individual soul (jiva) [in its true character] 
is Brahman alone, none other. 124 

Or to put the matter more formally: 

The non-duality of Brahman, the non-reality of the 
world, and the non-difference of the soul [Atman] 
from Brahman—these constitute the teaching of 
Advaita. 125 

The reader would have noticed that whether we approach 
Advaita Vedanta scripturally, or rationally, or experientially, 
in the end one finds oneself face-to-face with the pedagogical 
structure which bears a family-resemblance to this statement. 

While following the scriptural approach one starts out with 
Brahman and Atman and has to confront the issue of their 
identity in the face of the apparent plurality which 
characterizes our life. In adopting the rational approach one 
starts out with the world—or an object of the world—and 
finds oneself confronting indeterminate existence. In 
adopting the experiential approach one starts out with oneself 
only to see one’s self facing experiential dissolution. In all 
three cases one finds oneself at an interface between reality 
and unreality—but an unreality which cannot be severed from 
Reality and vice versa, as it were. 

The aim of this book was not much to convey the technical 
details of the system of philosophy of Advaita Vedanta, on 



112 Advaiia Vedanta 

which many books exist, as to convey its spirit, for it is as 
much a spirituality as a philosophy. Whether it has succeeded 
in this is for the reader to decide. 



Notes 


1. Andrew O. Fort, fivanmukti in Transformation: Embodied Liberation in 
Advaita and Neo-Vedanta (Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York 
Press, 1998). 

2. Wilhelm Halbfass, India and Europe: An Essay in Understanding (Albany, 
N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1988) p. 353. 

3. M. Hiriyanna, The Essentials of Indian Philosophy, (London: George Allen 
& Unwin, 1949) p. 19. 

4. Ibid., p. 152. 

5. Ibid., p. 154. 

6. For a good discussion of this point see John Grimes, Problems and 
Perspectives in Religious Discourse: Advaita Vedanta Implications (Albany, 
N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1994). 

7. Ibid.,p. 156-157, 

8. Ibid, p. 157-158. 

9. Ibid, p. 158. 

10. Ibid. 

11. Ibid., p. 157. 

12. Ibid., p. 158. 

13. Ibid. 

14. Ibid., p. 47-48. 

15. Ibid., p. 159-160. 

16. K. Satchidananda Murty, Revelation and Reason in Advait a Vedanta. (Delhi: 
Motilal Banarsidass, 1974) p. 40. 

17. M. Hiriyanna, Indian Philosophical Studies. (Mysore: Kavyalaya Publishers, 
1957) p. 89. 

18. M. Hiriyanna, The Essentials of Indian Philosophy, p. 21. 

19. Ibid. 

20. Robert Ernest Hume, tr. The Thirteen Principal Upanishads. (London: 
Oxford University Press, 1968) p. 113-114. 

21. Thomas J. Hopkins, The Hindu Religious Tradition (Encino, California 
and Belmont, California: Dickenson Publishing Company, Inc., 1971) 
p. 37. 

22. Robert Ernest Hume, tr., op. til., p, 132-133. 



114 


Advaila Vedanta 


23. Ainslie T. Embree, ed., Sources of Indian Tradition (second edition) (New 
York: Columbia University Press, 1988) Vol. I, p. 32. 

24. Ibid., p. 33 

25. Ibid. 

26. S. Radhakrishnan, The Principal Upanisads. (Atlantic Heights, NJ: 
Humanities Press, 1992) p. 695-705. 

27. Ibid., p. 36. 

28. Ainslie T. Embree, ed., The Hindu Tradition (New York: Random House, 
1972) p. 52. 

29. Ibid., p. 55. 

30. Ibid., p. 55. 

31. Ibid, p. 21. 

32. Ibid., p. 22. 

33. Ibid., p. 22. 

34. Ibid. 

35. Troy Wilson Organ, Hinduism: Its Historical Development^ Woodbury, 
N.Y.: Barron’s Educational Series, 1974) p. 114. 

36. M. Hiriyanna, Outlines of Indian Philosophy, p. 378. 

37. Troy Wilson Organ, Hinduism: Its Historical Development, p. 114. 

38. Ibid., p.114-115. 

39. Chandradhar Sharma, A Critical Survey of Indian Philosophy (London: 
Rider, 1960) p. 282-283. 

40. I incorporate material here, which also appears in Arvind Sharma, The 
Philosophy of Religion and Advaila Vedanta: A Comparative Study of Religion 
and Reason (University Park, Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State 
University Press, 1995) p. 97-99. 

41. Satchidananda Murty, Revelation and Reason in Advaita Vedanta, p. 81. 

42. Robert Ernest Hume, op. cit. p. 240-241. 

43. See the discussion of the Honey-Doctrine (madhu-vidya), R.E. Hume, 
op. cit., p. 102-105. 

44. M. Hiriyanna, The Essentials of Indian Philosophy, p. 157. 

45. Heinrich Zimmer, Philosophies of India. (Edited by Joseph Campbell. 
New York: Princeton University Press, 1969) p. 337-338. 

46. Patrick Olivelle, The Early Upanisads (New York: Oxford University Press, 
1998) p. 561. 

47. S. Radhakrishnan, ed., op. cit., p. 462. 

48. Ibid., p. 463. 

49. Franklin Edgerton, “Studies in the Veda "Journal of the American Oriental 
Society 35:242 (1915). 

50. In the case of some ordeals it is possible to propose a psychological 
basis for the confidence that the innocent party may get acquitted, 
although it is doubtful if it applies here: 



Notes 


115 


Specially interesting is the ordeal of the ploughshare, in which the 
accused man had to touch a red-hot iron ploughshare with his tongue; 
if it was not burned he was deemed innocent—psychologically a fairly 
sound test of his own confidence in the result: since if he had a guilty 
conscience his salivary glands would not function properly, and his 
tongue would be burnt." (A.L. Basham, The Wonder that was India [New 
Delhi; Rupa & Co., 1999] p.l 17.) Curiously enough, a similar claim is 
made in a similar context in Islamic mysticism, as in the Upanisadic 
passage, see Reynold A. Nicholson, The Mystics of Islam (Harmondsworth: 
Penguin, 1889 [1914]) p. 182-183. 

51. Ibid., p. 245-250, with subheadings removed. 

52. Sacchidananda Murty, op. cit., p. 89. 

53. Ibid., Chapter VI passim. 

54. Ibid., p. 89-90,97. 

55. Ibid., p. 92. 

56. Ibid., p. 93. 

57. Ibid., p. 93. 

58. Ibid., p. 96. 

59. Ibid., p. 98. 

60. See Arvind Sharma, The Philosophy of Religion and Advaila Vedanta: A 
Comparative Study in Religion and Reason, p. 46-47. 

61. M. Hiriyanna, The Essentials of Indian Philosophy. P. 160-161. 

62. Ibid., p. 59. 

63. Ibid., p. 22-23. 

64. Satischandra Chatterjee and Dhirendramohan Datta, An Introduction 
to Indian Philosophy (Calcutta: University of Calcutta, 1950) p. 382. 

65. Ibid., p. 382. 

66. Ibid. 

67. Ibid., p.383. 

68. Ibid., p. 383. 

69. M. Hiriyanna, Outlines of Indian Philosophy (London; George Allen & 
Unwin, 1932) p. 370. 

70. M. Hiriyanna, Outlines of Indian Philosophy p. 370-371. 

71. Satishchandra Chatterjee and Dhirendramohan Datta, op. cit., p. 383- 
384. 

72. Ibid., p.384. 

73. Ibid. 

74. Ibid., p. 385. 

75. Ibid. 

76. Ibid., diacritics supplied. 

77. Ibid., p. 386-387. 

78. Ibid., p.388. 



116 


Advaita Vedanta 


79. find., p. 392. 

80. Ibid. 

81. Ibid., p. 467. “This conclusion is further supported by the linguistic 
cxpiessiuu 'my body', ‘my sense', 'my intellect’, 'etc. which show that 
the self can alienate itself from there ( body, sense, etc.) and treat them 
as external objects distinct from itself. These cannot, therefore, be 
regarded as the real essence of the self. It is true, one also sometimes 
says, ‘my consciousness.’ But such an expression cannot be taken 
literally, as implying a distinction between the self ( as possessor )and 
consciousness ( as possessed). For, if the self tries to distinguish itself 
from consciousness, it only assumes the form of distinguishing 
consciousness. Consciousness thus proves inseparable and 
indistinguishable from the self. So ‘my consciousness’ must be taken in 
the metaphorical sense. The possessive case here doesn’t really imply 
distinction, but rather identity or apposition ( as in ‘The city of 
London’). By comparing and analyzing the different meanings of the 
self expressed by T and ‘mine’ we discover thus pure consciousness as 
the real essence of the self’ ibid., p. 407-408). 

82. Ibid., p. 408. 

83. M. Hiriyanna, Indian Philosophical Studies ( Mysore : Kavyalaya Publishers, 
1957 )p. 135. 

84. Ibid.,p. 135-136. 

85. Satishchandra Chatterjee and Dhirendramohan Datta, op. til., p. 387. 

86. Ibid. 

87. Quoted in P. Sankaranarayanan, What is Advaita? (Bombay: Bharatiya 
Vidya Bhavan, 1970) p. 46. 

88. Ibid., p. 47. 

89. Maurice Frydman, tr., I Am That: Conversations With Sri Nisargadatta 
Maharaj (Bombay: Chetana, 1973) Part I, p. 263. 

90. John A. Hutchinson, Paths of Faith (New York: McGraw-Hill Book 
Company, 1969) p. 222. 

91. Wm. Theodore de Bary ed., Sources of Chinese Tradition (New York: 
Columbia University Press, 1960) Vol. I, p. 73. 

92. Ibid., p.72. 

93. Ainslie T. Embree, ed.. Sources of Indian Tradition (second edition) (New 
York: Columbia University Press, 1988) Vol. I p. 175-176. 

94. Swami Sambuddhananda, Vedanta Through Stories (Bombay: Sri 
Ramakrishna Ashram, 1959) pp. 44-45. 

95. A. Devaraja Mudaliar, compiler, Gems From Bhagavan 
(Tiruvannamalai:Sri Ramanasramam, 1985) p. 24-25. 

96. Gopal Singh, The Religion of the Sikhs (Bombay: Asia Publishing House, 
1971) p.93-94. 

97. Talks With Sri Ramana Maharshi (Tiruvannamalai: Sri Ramanasramam, 
1984) p. 563. 




Notes 


117 


98 find 

99. William M. Indich, Consciousness in Advaita Vedanta (Delhi: Motilal 
Banarsidass, 1980) p. 65. 

100. Paul Brunton, Conscious Immortality (Tiruvannamaalai: Sri 
Ramanasramam, 1984) p. 127. 

101. Ibid., p. 184. 

102. M. Hiriyanna, Essentials of Indian Philosophy, p. 166. 

103. Ibid., p. i 16. 

104. A. Devaraja Mudaliar, compiler, op. tit., p. 35. 

105. Paul Brunton, op. til., p. 91. 

106. David Godman, ed.. The Teachings of Sri Ramana Maharshi (New York: 
Arkana, 1985) p. 53. 

107. Ibid., p. 52. 

108. Ibid. 

109. Swami Rajeswarananda, compiler, Erase The Ego (Bombay: Bharatiya 
Vidya Bhavan, 1974) p. 39. 

110. A. Devaraja Mudaliar, compiler, op. tit., p. 17. 

111. Swami Rajeswarananda, compiler, op. tit., p. 55. 

112. Arthur Osborne, ed., The Teachings o/Bhagavan Ramana Maharshi in his 
Own Words (Tiruvannamalai: T.N. Venkataraman, 1971) p. 249. 

113. Ibid., p.228. 

114. T.M.P. Mahadevan.tr., WhoAmP (Tiruvannamalai: Sri Ramanasramam, 
1976) p. 2. 

115. Sadhu Om, The Path of Shri Ramana (Kanpur: The City Book House, 
1971) p. 28. 

116. Ibid., p. 32. 

117. David Godman, ed., op. tit., p. 158. 

118. Sadhu Om, op. tit., p. 26. 

119. Sadhu Om, op. tit., p. 46. 

120. Swami Saradananda, Sri Ramakrishna: The Great Master (Madras: 
RamakrishnaMath, 1952) pp. 128-129. 

121. B.V. Narsimha Swami, Self-Realization: The Life and Teachings ofSriRamana 
Maharishi. (Tiruvannamalai: Sri Ramanasramam, 1985; first published 
1931) p. 20. 

122. Paul Brunton, op. tit., p. 68. 

123. J. Krishnamurd, On Truth. (San Francisco: Harper, 1995) pp. 24-29. 

124. T.M.P. Mahadevan, Outlines of Hinduism (Bombay: Chetana Limited, 
1971 [1956]) p. 141. 

125. Ibid. 




Bibliography 


Basham, A.L. The Wonder That Was India, Rupa & Co, New Delhi, 1999 
[1954], 

Brunton, Paul. Conscious Immortality, Sri Ramanasramam, Tiruvannamalai, 

1984. 

Chatterjee, Satischandra, and Dhirendramohan Datta. An Introduction to 
Indian Philosophy, University of Calcutta, Calcutta, 1950. 

De Bary., Wm. Theodore, Ed. Sources of Chinese Tradition, Columbia University 
Press, New York, 1960. 

Edgertion, Franklin. “Studies in Veda”, Journal of the American Oriental Society, 
35:242,1915. 

Embree, Ainslie T., Ed. Sources of Indian Tradition (second edition), Columbia 
University Press, New York, 1988. 

Fort, Andrew O.Jtvanmukti in Transformation: Embodied Liberation in Advaita 
and neo-Vedanta, Albany, State University of New York Press, N.Y. 1998. 
Frydman, Maurice, Tr. I Am That: Conversations urith Sri Nisaragadatta Maharaj, 
Part I, Chetana, Bombay, 1973. 

Godman, David, Ed. The Teachings of Sri Raman Maharshi, Arkana, New York, 

1985. 

Halbfass, Wilhelm. India and Europe: An Essay in Understanding, Albany, State 
University of New York Press, N. Y., 1988. 

Hiriyanna, M. Indian Philosophical Studies, Kavyalaya Publishers, Mysore, 1957. 

-. The Essentials of Indian Philosophy, George Allen & Unwin, London, 1949. 

-. Outlines of Indian Philosophy, George Allen & Unwin, London, 1932. 

Hopkins, Thomas J. The Hindu Religious Tradition, Encino, California and 
Belmont, Dickenson Publishing Company, California, 1971. 

Hume, Robert Ernest. The Thirteen Principal Upanishads, Oxford University 
Press, London, 1968. 



120 


Advaila Vedanta 


Hutchinson, John A. Paths of Faith, McGraw-Hill Book Company, New York, 

1969. 

Indirh, William M. Consciousness in Advaita Vedanta, Motilal Banarsidass, 
Delhi, 1980. 

Krishnamurti.J. On Truth, Harper, San Francisco, 1995. 

Mahadevan, T. M. P., Tr. Who Am I f Sri Ramanasramam, Tiruvannamalai, 
1976. 

-. Outlines of Hinduism, Chetana Limited, Bombay, 1971 [1956]. 

-. Talks With Sri Ramana Maharshi, Sri Ramanasramam, Tiruvannamalai, 

1984. 

Mudaliar, A. Devaraj (compiler). Gems From Bhagvan, Sri Ramanasramam, 
Tiruvannamalai, 1985. 

Murty, K_ Satchidananda. Revelation and Reason in Advaita Vedanta, Motilal 
Banarsidass, Delhi, 1974. 

Nicholson, Reynold A. The Mystics of Islam, Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1914 
[1889], 

Olivelle, Patrick. The Early Upanisads, Oxford University Press, New York, 
1998. 

Om, Sadhu. The Path ofShri Ramana, The City Book House, Kanpur, 1971. 
Organ, Troy Wilson. Hinduism: Its Historical Development, Woodbury, Barron’s 
Educational Series, N. Y., 1974. 

Osborne, Arthur, Ed. The Teachings of Bhagavan Ramana Maharshi in His 
Own Words, T. N. Venkataraman, Tiruvannamalai, 1071. 
Radhakrishnan, S. The Principal Upanisads, N. J.: Humanities Press, Atlantic 
Heights, 1992. 

Swami Rajeswarananda (compiler). Erase the Ego. Bharatiya Vidya Bhavan, 
Bombay, 1974. 

Swami Sambuddhananda. Vedanta Through Stories, Sri Ramakrishna Ashram, 
Bombay, 1959. 

Sankaranarayanan, P. What is Advaita ? Bharatiya Vidya Bhavan, Bombay, 

1970. 

Swami Saradananda, Tr. Sri Ramakrishna: The Great Master, Ramakrishna 
Math, Madras, 1952. 

Sharma, Arvind. The Philosophy of Religion and Advaita Vedanta: A Comparative 
Study in Religion and Reason, The Pennsylvania State University Press, 
University Park, Pennsylvania, 1995. 



Bibliography 121 

Sharma, Chandradhar. A Critical Survey of Indian Philosophy, Rider, London, 
1960. 

Singh, Gopal. The Religions of the Sikhs, Asia Publishing House, Bombay, 1971. 

Swami, B. V. Narasimha. Self-Realization: The Life and Teachings of Sri Ramana 
Maharshi, Sri RamasramamTiruvannamalai, 1985 [1931]. 

Zimmer, Heinrich. Philosophies of India, (Edited by Joseph Campbell), 
Princeton University Press, New York, 1969. 




Index 



Astika&S 

Atman9, 24, 28, 30, 33, 43,99 
Advaita Vedanta 10-13 
Advaita 18 
Antahkarana 21 
Anadi 22-23 
Asatkaryavada 55 
Anavastha 57 
Aniruacaniya 69 
Avidyd 99 


Brahmasutra 17, 34 
Brahman 19 

Brhadaranyaka upani$ad 27 
Brereton, J. 40 
Buddish 83 
Brunton, Paul 104 


Chandogya Upani$ad 29,35 
Causation 53 ff, 
Consciousness 70,100-101 
Chuanglzu 81 
Contradiction 67, 74 


Darsana 6,8 


ZM 72-73,86 
Drsya 72 - 73 
Descartes 80 
Dress metaphor 89 - 94 
Dreaming 80 ff 
Deep sleep 85 - 86 


Edgerton, Franklin 42 
Experience 79 ff 
Existence 62 

Experential approach 79 ff 
Exbree, Ainslie 30 


Falsification 74,76 
Five sheaths 29,94 
Father and Son 36 
Fire 28 
God 31,100 


Gargi 26 - 27 
Guru Arsun 84 
Gandharas 42 
Gandharvas 26 


Hiriyanna, M 31, 48, 58 



124 


Advaita Vedanta 


Hume 72 
History 10 
Hinduism 6 


I-Th ought 90 - 92 
India 3 
Islam 4 

Identity-cum-Difference 57 - 59 


Jivanmukti 4 - 5 
Jiva 19, 20, 24, 34,45 
JIvatman 21 
Janaka27, 81 
Jivanmukla 74 
Jnana 104 


Karma 22 
Kosa 94 

Krishnamurti 104 
King 81,83 


Liiiga 35 

Life-Its Three States 79 - 80 
Logic 79 - 80 
Laya 95 
Limitations 20 


Mahavakya 18 ff. 

Mandukya Upanisad 29 
Mimamsa 35 
Materialism 46,48 


Maya. 45,99 
Mueller, Max 6 


Nityata24 
Nine Schools 6 
Niyati 24 

Name and Form 36, 39 


Organ, Troy Wilson 32 
Otto, Rudolph 33 
Ocean, Mataphor of 38 
Origin of Karma 22 


Pascal 81 
Parinama 23, 55 
Pramanas 35 
Prakrti9 


Questioning 26 - 28 
Quantity 62 
Quality 46,57 

Questions in Advaita Vedanta 13 
Qur'an 7 


Religion and Philosophy 3 - 4 
Ramakrsna 83,100 
Ramana Maharsi 84, 86 - 88, 93, 95, 
96,101 

Rational Approach 53 ff 
Rationality 79 
Ramanuja 45 




Index 


125 




Sankara 18,44,47,63,65,68,69,75 

Vedanta 11 

.Sal 20 

Vedas 12 

Samsara 22 

Vikdra 61-62 

Sadlihga 35 

Vivaria 23 

Qi'otnl/otn A A 

k_» » V- IU1\V- tu »/ X X 

T ~ on 

V ISlflU 

Saccidananda 48 

Vivekananda 100 

Satkaryavada 55, 76 


Sdthkhya 55 


Sattd 67, 75 

West 4-5 

Samadhi 75, 95 

World 68 

Saksi 86 

Worlds 26-27 

Scriptural Approach 17 ff 

Waking State 89 - 80 



Taittiriya Upani$ad 29 
Time and Eternity 24 
Truth 43 

Text and Interpretation 34 ff 


Upanisads 12,17,25,28 
Upadhi 20-21 
Uddalaka 35 
Upapatti 35 



X and Y 59 
X substance 67 


Yajnavalkya 26 - 28 
Yoga 4, 6 


Zimmer, Heinrich 39 




Arvind Sharma is the 
Birks Professor of 
Comparative Religion in 
the faculty of Religious 
Studies at McGill 
University; and was the 
first Infinity Foundation Visiting 
Professor of Indie Studies at Harvard 
University. His previous works on 
Advaita Vedanta include: The 
Experiential Dimension of Advaita Vedanta 
(1993); The Philosophy of Religion and 
Advaita Vedanta (1995); and The Rope 
and the Snake: A Metaphorical Exploration 
of Advaita Vedanta (1997). 


He lives in Montreal, Canada. 




The history of the Vedanta school is well-known since the time of 
Sankara but its prehistory before Sankara is quite obscure. However, 
there is a period of a thousand years between the compilation of 
the major Upanisads to Sankara without loss of the tradition of the 
Upanisads; there appeared many philosophers and dogmaticians, 
although their thoughts are not clearly known. 

The author made clear the details of the pre-Sankara Vedanta 
philosophy, utilizing not only Sanskrit materials, but also Pali, Prakrit 
as well as Tibetan and Chinese sources. In this respect, this epoch- 
making work was awarded the Imperial Prize by the Japan Academy. 

Parts One and Two will be important literature indispensable 
not only to those, who are specialists in the study of Vedanta but 
also to those engaged in the study of Indian thought in general. 

Part Two is a complete English translation of Vols. Ill and IV of 
the Japanese version, with many additions and revisions done by 
the author himself. 


This is a unique work discussing the teachings of four of the great 
Advaita Acaryas: Gaudapada, Sankara, and his two disciples, 
Suresvara and Padmapada. 

The author combines close textual scholarship with the 
perspective of one is a teacher (Acarya) within the tradition of 
Advaita. This work will prove useful for the student who wishes to 
obtain clear and detailed information about these four Acaryas, and 
it will also be of value to one who is seeking to develop their own 
spirituality within the Advaita tradition. 


E-mail: mlbd@vsnl.com 
Website: www.mlbd.com 

Rs. 295 Code: 20274 


1S BN 81-208-2027-4