====
Arvind Sharma, Advaita Vedänta. An Introduction, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 2004, pp. vii+125. ISBN 81-208-2027-4, Rs 295.00
Reviewed by Kazimieras Seibutis
Sri Aurobindo Cultural Center, Vilnius
Any book about such a challenging matter as Advaita Vedänta is fascinating, therefore it is no wonder that reading a short introduction on the subject by Arvind Sharrna is an exciting experience indeed, not only because the author manages to avoid getting involved in conflicting aspects of different schools of classical intellectual trend of India that is not yet widely known in the West, but also because the subject matter is presented in a condensed and very succinct manner.
Sharma, Birks Professor of Comparative Religion at McGill University, attempts to overcome this challenge by consistently relying on three approaches: scriptural, rational and experiential.
Sharma says that he "tries to accord an independent status to each of these approaches without losing sight of their interconnectedness".
In a short preface prior to the analysis, Sharma calls the readers' attention to a fundamental fact that in the West philosophy represents an intellectual movement which has achieved an independent status by shaking off constrains of theology.
Meanwhile, within the framework of Indian culture such a divergence between philosophy and religion did not occur, and according to Sharma "the two, even when they become dual, remain undivided." Sharma also draws attention to the concept of jivanmukti and the pivotal idea, which supports the concept of jivanmukti, that the results of one's faith can be attained while still living in this world.
Sharma goes on saying that according to this notion faith is understood as "faith pending realization — it denotes the trust one must have in order to undertake an experiment, but the outcome of the experiment is independent of such a faith".
In view of this, while toting to define ultimate reality or Brahman, Advaita Vedänta is relying not only on revelation and reason, but also on the teachings of those who achieved the state ofjivanmukti and became jivanmuktas or living embodiments of Brahman.
In the first chapter devoted to a scriptural approach, the author mainly discusses the scriptural authority of Upanisads and the hermeneutical attempts of Advaita Vedänta in a unified way to interpret and harmonize four key statements called mahäväkyas. These are accepted as the authority by other schools of Vedanta as well, but they interpret them using a rather different exegetical clue. Each of the four mahäväkyas has been given a detailed analysis in separate subsections.
Sharma stresses that acceptance of Vedic authority is not as binding for philosophical purposes as it is for social cohesion.
The second chapter explains the subtleties of the rational approach. Using classical examples of a bracelet of silver and silver (rüpyakundalanyäya) and of a rope and a snake (rajjusarpanyäya), the author compares doctrines of Asatkäryaväda and Satkäryaväda. He emphasizes that for a rational presentation of Advaitic ontology we must rely upon the paradoxical logic of contradiction between the non-contradictable and contradictable.
Chapter Three, the last one, contains analysis of experiential approach to the study of Advaita Vedänta. Here Sharma says that our experience of life compels us to take into account all the three states of consciousness as postulated in the revealed scripture. These are waking, dreaming and deep sleep. Invoking the assumption of the triad points out that rationality is only one aspect of manifold mental activities and that it cannot be regarded as encompassing the whole of life. Also, this implies the existence of unchanging consciousness which undergirds the consciousness of change of the three states of consciousness and constitutes the unchanging core of our being — self or ätman, which in turn is identical with Brahman. Trying to underscore this "experientially most resonant dimension of Advaitic nondualism", the author produces some accounts of mystical experience from the hagiographies of the twentieth century yogis Swämi Vivekänanda, Ramana Maharsi and Krishnamurti.
The author expresses hope that his attempt to present Advaita Vedänta with pedagogical variation will be a refreshing one, and surely it will be a useful addition to the literature available on this particular school of Vedänta, especially for students of comparative philosophy of religion.
====
Full text of "Advaita Vedanta An Introduction"
See other formats
The novelty of this book consists of the
fact that it introduces the reader to
the basic tenets of Advaita Vedanta in
three independent but com¬
plementary ways: scripturally,
rationally and experientially. All the
three elements are usually found
intertwined in accounts of Advaita
Vedanta. They are presented
distinctly here in the hope that each
perspective will enrich one’s
understanding of Advaita Vedanta as
a whole and also allow the reader to
form his or her own opinion about the
relative merits of each approach.
ADVAITA VEDANTA
ADVAITA VEDANTA
An Introduction
Arvind Sharma
MOTILAL BANARSIDASS PUBLISHERS
PRIVATE LIMITED • DELHI
First Edition: Delhi, 2004
====
Contents
Preface vii
Introduction 1
Religion, Philogophy and Advaita Vedanta 3
Parti 15-49
Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 17
Part II 51-76
Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach 53
PartHI 77-110
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach 79
Conclusion 111
Note 113
Bibliography 121
Index 125
======
Preface
The Biblical recognition of the fact that to the writing of
books there is no end must surely not be used as an excuse
for writing books indiscriminately. The readers therefore
have a right to ask : why another book on Advaita Vedanta?
Most of the existing books on Advaita Vedanta rely on the
scriptural approach in presenting it. Some books mix it with
the rational and experiential approaches as well, without always
distinguishing clearly between them. This book tries to
accord an independent status to each of these approaches
without losing sight of their interconnectedness in the hope
that the readers will find such a presentation refreshing.
I hope that this pedagogical variation in the way Advaita
Vedanta is thematically presented will be welcomed by the
readers.
—Arvind Sharma
INTRODUCTION
Religion, Philosophy and Advaita Vedanta
I. Religion and Philosophy in India and the West
It might be helpful to say a few words about the nature of
philosophy as it is pursued in India, prior to providing an
introduction to the school of Indian philosophy known as
Advaita Vedanta.
Both Western and Indian philosophers admit that the
nature of the relationship between philosophy and religion
follows a different pattern in Western and Indian civilization
but they tend to differ in their assessment of the significance
of this divergence. Both accept that philosophy essentially
consists of a rational investigation into the nature of Reality.
The nature of the Reality, however, also constitutes, in its own
way, the subject matter of religion, so the nature of the
relationship between the two needs to be considered.
A relationship between religion and philosophy is
considered peripheral in Western culture for historical and
philosophical reasons. In the West, philosophy represents an
intellectual movement which first distinguished itself from
theology and then proceeded to achieve an independent
status. This meant that the attitude of Western philosophy
towards religion came to be marked by indifference, aversion
and perhaps even rejection. Such a development did not occur
within Indian culture. Thus, although the distinction between
philosophy and religion can also be drawn in the Indian
context, such a distinction therein tends to be analytical
without being antagonistic. It can even be claimed that the
4
Advaila Vedanta
two, even when they become dual, remain undivided.
Moreover, the distinction between philosophy and religion
in the West additionally rests on the distinction between reason
and faith, with reason constituting the cornerstone of
philosophy and faith that of religion. This distinction is
strengthened by the fact that the results of faith are typically
accessible only posthumously, while the results of rational
investigation are typically available here and now.
A separation of philosophy and religion is intellectually
approved of in the West, as this allows for the pursuit of
philosophical truths untrammelled by religious scruples. Many
Indian thinkers, however, take a different view of the matter.
According to them this divorce of philosophy from religion
runs the risk of reducing philosophy to a merely intellectual
pastime, far removed from the kind of ultimate concern which
should ideally characterise philosophy. In this context they
make a further point: that although the claims made by Indian
philosophy may sometimes seem to possess a religious nature,
they are attainable within this life, and are therefore, in
principle, verifiable.
The successful attainment of such results is characterised
by the term jivanmukti. Not all schools of either Indian
philosophy, or of Hindu philosophy, make such a claim but
Advaita Vedanta does'—along with the Hindu systems of
Sarikhya and Yoga. The claim also characterises much of
Buddhist and Jaina thought. The term jivanmukti is often
translated as living liberation, as the word mukti means liberation
and jivan means while living. The idea underlying jivanmukti
thus seems to be that one can attain the results of one’s faith
while still living in this world. There is no reason in principle
why faith in reason could not also represent such faith.
These ideas contrast, perhaps even sharply, with those
found in the thought of other religious systems such as those
of Christianity and Islam. In Christianity and Islam, specifically
in their more traditional versions of Catholicism and Sunni
Islam, the benefits of faith are to be enjoyed in a post-mortem
Religion, Philosophy and Advaita Vedanta
5
existence. That is to say, one does not experience the results
of one’s faith until after death, or perhaps not even until
the Day of Judgement, which takes place not at the time of
one’s death but at the end of the world or of Time itself.
This leads to the curious situation that one of the questions
critically debated in those traditions which accept jivanmukti
is What happens to the liberated one after his or her death”
rather than “What happens after death”! The grand question
is not what happens after death as in Christianity and Islam,
but what happens to the liberated person after his or her
death.
It is clear that the concept of faith itself also carries very
different connotations in the schools which accept jivanmukti,
compared with those of the West. In schools which accept
jivanmukti, faith is understood as faith pending realization - it
denotes the trust one must have in order to undertake an
experiment, but the outcome of the experiment is
independent of such faith. It is even possible that the revealed
results might contribute towards strengthening faith, just as
one’s faith in science is strengthened when one experimentally
discovers that water is made of two gases.
It is in the light of these considerations that Indian thinkers
take a more positive view of the fact that philosophy and religion
have not been sundered in India, as in the West. This atdtude
is also reflected in their treatment of Advaita Vedanta.
To recapitulate: Philosophy in the Western world consists
of rational investigation into the nature of reality. For Indian
philosophers, however, philosophy in the Western world is
only half of what it should be. They like to say that Western
philosophy is a purely intellectual activity, and that in the West
religion and philosophy have been broken apart. In the West,
then, reason is opposed to faith. This split, they argue, has
not occurred in the Indian tradition. Thus many schools of
thought in the Indian religious traditions feel no awkwardness,
embarrassment or self-consciousness in discussing the ultimate
nature of reality both from a philosophical and a religious
perspective. Advaita Vedanta is one such school.
6
Advaita Vedanta
II. Advaita Vedanta and other Schools of Indian Thought
Since religion cannot be completely overlooked when
dealing with philosophy in the Indian context, it is useful to
draw a distinction between Indian religions and Indie
religions. The term Indian religions refers to all the religions
found in India such as Hinduism, Buddhism, Jainism,
Sikhism, Judaism, Zoroastrianism, Christianity, Islam and so
on. The term Indie religions, by contrast, is used to refer
only to the religions of Indian origin collectively, namely
Hinduism, Ruddhism, Jainism and Sikhism. Indian
philosophy, again by contrast, is classically taken to refer to
the philosophical systems which characterise the Indie
religions.
In one classification, which has gained wide acceptance
since 1900 when it was adopted by Max Mueller, Indian
philosophy includes nine schools of Indian thought. 2 A school
of philosophy in India known as darsana, a word which may
be translated in several ways. It is derived from the verbal
root which means to see, thereby yielding such meanings as
insights into reality or worldviews. These nine systems are further
classified into the non-orthodox and orthodox systems of
Indian thought as follows:
Indian Philosophy ( Darsana )
Non-Orthodox schools
of Hindu thought
Nastika (3)
Indian Materialism
Buddhism
Jainism
Orthodox Schools of
Hindu thought
Astika (6)
Nyaya
Vaisesika
Sankhya
Yoga
Mimarhsa
Vedanta
Asti in the word astika above means yes and na in the word
nastika changes the meaning into no. The three non¬
orthodox schools of Indie thought do not accept Vedic
Religion, Philosophy and Advaita Vedanta
7
authority; to be nastika is to say no to the Vedas. Astika, then,
means saying yes to the Vedas. Among the six schools which
accept Vedic authority, the first four, that is Nyaya, Vaisesika,
Sankhya and Yoga, indeed accept the authority of the Vedas
but they do so basically a posteriori rather than a priori. The
last two schools of Mlmarhsa and Vedanta, however, actually
base themselves on the Vedas.
It is obvious that orthodoxy here has been defined from a
Hindu perspective, and the acceptance of the authority of
the Vedas, the foundational scriptures of Hinduism, has been
identified as its hallmark. It should now be added that the
Mlmarhsa and Vedanta schools are to be further
distinguished from the above-mentioned astika schools in
that they not only acknowledge the authority of, but also
base their teachings on the Vedas. Therefore, in order to
understand these schools, it is important to understand the
traditional view of the Vedas.
The term Veda comes from the root vid, which means to
know, as in video (to know visually). The Vedas are said to
have been revealed to or seen by the sages. It is traditionally
understood that the Vedas are not works of human authors.
This idea also exists in the Islamic tradition, where the Qur’an
is understood to have been received by the Prophet Muhammad
frpm God. In Hindu Vedantic thought, however, even God is
eliminated as the author. The Vedas are woven into the fabric
and texture of the universe, which is eternal. This in turn
means that the Vedas are eternal, and are periodically
discovered, and not created or invented.
The Vedas have never been formalised into a closed canon,
although a certain degree of informal consensus does exist.
This uncertainty has the subtle effect of making the person
who speaks with authority more influential than the text.
Because the Vedas are numerous and the canon loosely
defined, it stands to reason that one would turn to a person
Who has experienced jivanmukti for authoritative opinion,
4'ather than sift through a mass of confusing, indeterminate,
tecl sometimes contradictory information.
8
Advaila Vedanta
The Vedas are four in number. Each of the four Vedas
(Rg, Sama, Yajur, Atharva) can be divided into four different
layers, just as the Christian Bible ran be divided into two
layers, the Old Testament and the New. Judaism and
Christianity differ in that they do not accept the same layer
as authoritative. In a somewhat similar fashion, Mlmarhsa
thought regards the earlier parts of the Vedas as of primary
importance, whereas Vedanta accords greater authority to
the last layer, consisting of the Upanisads. The Upanisads,
according to Vedanta, mark the consummation of all the
previous layers, and thereby reveal the final truth contained
in the Vedas.
The basis of the classification of the darsanas, or schools of
thought, provided above was textual, the text involved being
the Veda. The point however should not be overstated. As
already noted, the word astika comes from the verbal root
which literally means to be or yes it is\ which means that these
schools have responded with a yes to the question: “do you
accept the authority of the Vedas?” The six astika schools:
Nyaya, Vaisesika, Sarikhya, Yoga, Mlmarhsa and Vedanta were
mentioned earlier. It was also mentioned that the first four
of these, although they accept Vedic authority, do not base
.their teaching on the Vedas. These schools simply
acknowledge the authority of the Vedas, and then proceed to
go on and do what they like. Because the corpus of Vedic
scripture is vast, one could justify almost any view, and
therefore nominally acknowledge the authority of these texts.
Thus acceptance of Vedic authority is not as binding for
philosophical purposes as it is for social cohesion. Hence the
four schools are listed before the two schools of Mlmarhsa and
Vedanta because they accept Vedic authority only nominally
and after the three non-orthodox schools because
nevertheless they do accept it, instead of rejecting the Vedas
like the three non-orthodox schools.
III. A Philosophical Explanation of the Classification
It is also possible to provide a more philosophical justification
Religion, Philosophy and Advaita Vedanta
9
for the nature and order of this system of classification-
specially from the perspective of Advaita Vedanta, the subject
of our study. This has to do with the concept of the self or
atman, which plays such a key role in Advaita Vedanta that
the system itself has been referred to as atmadvaita.
One can detect a pattern in the progression of thought
through these nine schools, if one examines their concept
of the atman, the self or soul. The materialists believe that
natural elements suffice to give rise to consciousness in
human beings. As materialism does not acknowledge an
atman, the materialists encourage people to live for the
moment, for death is final. They believe in happiness
through materialism, in keeping with the maxim: “eat, drink
and be merry.” Buddhism also does not acknowledge an
atman but it accepts allied concepts such as a belief in the
cycle of rebirth. Jainism accepts an atman, but it is considered
coextensive with the physical body. Nyaya and Vaisesika also
believe in an atman. However, in these systems although the
atman does exist, it cannot exhibit consciousness
independently of accessories, that is, by itself. Sankhya and
Yoga also believe in an independent atman. But they also
posit a strict dualism between matter and spirit, although
the two are not on par. Matter is subservient to spirit and all
matter is integrated into one category. (In other schools
matter, is sometimes split into different ultimate parts.)
However, in these systems, all atmans retain their individuality
to the very end. They do not merge into one. The concept
of atman in Advaita Vedanta, however, unites all entities in
the realm of the spirit into Brahman, just as Sankhya and
Yoga unite all entities in the realm of matter into prakrti.
The school of Advaita Vedanta thus arguably represents a
Culmination of the underlying philosophical thrust around
the concept of the atman or self as found in Indian philosophy.
TV. Another Philosophical Explanation of the Classification
Another philosophical justification of classification can be
found in the attitudes of the various schools towards the
10
Advaita Vedanta
relationship between the realms of matter and spirit. Both
matter and consciousness are equally given in human
experience: we see material objects all around us, and it is
immaterial consciousness which enables us to be aware of
them.
Since both matter and spirit in this sense are empirically
given, three fundamental philosophical positions can be
postulated on this point: (1) that it is matter alone which is
the ultimate reality, consciousness being its epi-phenomenon,
a position which may be characterised as materialism, (2) that
both matter and spirit constitute ultimate reality in their own
right, a position which may be described as that of
fundamental dualism (3) or that spirit alone is ultimately real,
matter being its byproduct, a position which may be
characterised as idealism.
In terms of this schema, the classification of the nine schools
starts with materialism, then moves through the fundamentally
dualistic schools which accept the reality of both matter and
spirit, to end with Vedanta which is idealistic in its orientation,
Advaita Vedanta being specially so.
V. Advaita Vedanta: What Does it Mean?
Let us begin with the word Advaita itself, which perhaps
appears formidably foreign when first encountered. It can
however be de-exoticised quite easily with the help of a
brief foray into philology. It can be broken up as a-dvaita.
The initial a here has the same meaning as the letter a in
ahistorical, that is, of negating what follows. Thus just as
ahistorical means not-historical, a-dvaita means rcot-dvaita.
But what does dvaita mean? This word is etymologically
connected with the English word dual - a connection which
can be phonetically heard if one says the two words dvaita
and dual out aloud. The word dvaita, moreover, not only
sounds like dual, but shares its meaning as well. Thus dvaita
means dualism or twoness.
The word advaita ( a-dvaita ) thus means not-two or non¬
dual.
Religion, Philosophy and Advaita Veddnla 1 1
The word is however an adjective — so the question arises:
what is it being applied to? In other words, what is it about
which this claim is being made that it is not two ?
So let us put the word advaita on hold for a moment and
tty to find out what the word which it qualifies means; namely,
Vedanta. The two can then be brought together again to
reveal their meaning in its fullness.
The word Vedanta might also, like the word advaita ,
appear forbiddingly alien at first sight. But once again it yields
its meaning easily with the help of a mercifully brief excursion
into philology.
The word Vedanta is made of two words - veda + anta.
The word Veda is derived from a root which means to knoio —
the same root which appears in three English words: wit,
wisdom and video, that is, to know intelligently (wit); to know
sagely (wisdom) and to know visually (video). The word Veda,
derived from the same root vid (to know) as noticed earlier,
denotes wisdom, that is to say, spiritual wisdom, and by
implication the texts which embody such wisdom. Thus it is
that the sacred scriptures of the Hindus are called the Vedas,
just as the sacred scripture of the Christians is known as the
Bible, and of the Muslims as the Qur’an. Note that unlike the
Bible and the Qur’an, the word Veda often takes a plural
ending. This is so because traditionally one speaks of the
four Vedas, a fact also noticed earlier. Sometimes, however,
the word Veda is also used in the singular to refer to the
Vedas collectively. The fact that, even to begin with,
Hinduism possesses four sacred books and not just one tells
us something about the inherently plural ethos of the
tradition.
Not only are the Vedas four in number, four layers can be
identified in each of them. The following chart may help
clarify the picture in this respect.
12
Advaita Vedanta
Vedas
Rg Yajur Sama Atharva
Mantra or
Sarhhitd — — — —
Brahmana — — — —
Aranyaka — — — —
Upanisad — — — —
Each of the Vedas contains (1) hymns (many shared by
them in common) in praise of the gods; (2) prose explanations
of the ritual use of these hymns; (3) reflections on the
significance of ritual and (4) secret texts meant to
communicate the highest mysteries which go beyond ritual
into the realm of spiritual knowledge. These layers are
respectively called (1) mantra or samhitd (i.e. hymns, or
collections of hymns); (2) brahmana (i.e. authoritative
utterances of priests); (3) aranyakas (i.e. forest-books) and
(4) upanisads (or mystic texts revealed to disciples as they
sat up close to the masters).
The rest of our presentation will focus on the upanisads.
Because they come at the end of the Vedas, or constitute the
last of the four layers, they are also called Vedanta, that is,
Veda’s end. The word anta in Sanskrit has the same meaning
as the English word end.
The texts which constitute the Upanisads, or Vedanta, deal
with the central issues of philosophy: what is the ultimate
reality about the universe around us and about us who are
asking this question? And what is the ultimate nature of this
ultimate reality?
The Upanisads, (more than two hundred of which have
been identified, among which close to a dozen or more are
considered major ones) do not offer, at least on the face of it,
a single answer to these questions. They are closer to being
works of religious inspiration than systematic treatises on
Religion, Philosophy and Advaila Vedanta
13
theology, and the inspired statements found therein lend
themselves to many interpretations. Thus different schools
of philosophy arose in India out of an attempt to present
their teachings in a systematic way. These various schools of
philosophy are known as schools of Vedanta, and they differ
in their interpretation regarding the final teaching of the
Upanisads. Thus questions such as: is the ultimate reality
ultimately personal or impersonal in nature? are answered
differently by these schools. Similarly, the schools differ in
the answer they come up with to such questions as: what is
the relationship of the ultimate reality ( Brahman) to the
world, or what does Realization consist of.
Advaita Vedanta is one such school of Vedanta. It is
labeled Advaita because it does not ultimately regard either
us or the universe as different from the ultimately reality -
they are not-two. It prefers to call them not-two rather than
one. because not-two implies a lack of fundamental division
to begin with, whereas one may imply the coming together
of two items that are in fact apart. Hence it prefers to speak
in terms of an “undivided” ( a-dvaita ) Reality, in preference
to one Reality, because according to it the positing of such a
fundamental division is itself a product of error.
Are all living beings ultimately identical with Brahman ? Is
the universe also identical with it? Is there any difference
between the way the living beings are identical with Brahman
compared to the way the universe is? If the ultimate reality
is a single undivided Reality, what reality do the different
things and different people around us possess? Are they
defilements or embellishments, and how can they exist
without involving duality on the part of an undivided reality?
The school of Advaita Vedanta tries its best to answer these
questions by relying (1) on revelation, (2) on reason and
(8) on the teachings of those who are said to be living
embodiments of the Realization of Brahman or the ultimate
Reality.
====
PART I Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
The scriptural approach relies on scriptural authority as the
basis for the claims it makes regarding the nature of the
ultimate reality. This reality is regularly referred to in the
Upanisads as Brahman.
The Upanisads, however, make several pronouncements
regarding the nature of the objective world, the nature of
the individual subject and the nature of the ultimate reality
{Brahman), with the result that “there are great, almost
insurmountable difficulties in deciding what exactly is the
teaching of the Upanisads in certain important respects. This
accounts for the emergence in later times of diverse schools
of Vedanta, all of which claim to propound the Upanisadic
teaching”. 3 It is also worth adding that:
The vagueness of Upanishadic teaching is
particularly in reference to the relation of
Brahman to the individual soul on the one hand,
and to the physical universe on the other.
Though... statements about their identity are many
and prominent, those distinguishing them are not
altogether wanting. The first problem to solve for
any one attempting to systematize the teaching of
the Upanishads is accordingly to harmonize these
two sets of statements. 4
Each system of Vedanta has evolved its own method of
harmonizing these statements on the underlying assumption
(contained in Brahmasiitra 1.1.4) that these Upanisadic
teachings have to be understood in a unified way. Advaita
18
Advaita Vedanta
Vedanta, as a system of Vedanta, has devised its own
understanding of the Upanisads in keeping with this
assumption.
it was noted above that the Upanisads seem to contain
two streams of thought: one which recognizes the diversity
of the objective universe, the subjective individual and the
ultimate reality ( Brahman) and another which emphasizes
their unity. The great exponent of Advaita Vedanta :
Sarhkara recognizes, that there arc two streams of
thought in the Upanishads; but he thinks that one
of them, viz. that which affirms the reality of
diversity, is only a concession to empirical modes
of thought. All diversity being thus only
conditionally true, the only teaching of the
Upanishads, according to him, is that of unity.
Since, however, there can be no unity apart from
variety, he does not describe his teaching as
monism but only as “non-dualism” ( advaita ). 5
How, it might now be asked, does Sankara achieve such a
result?
He achieves this outcome through an exegetical
manoeuvre according to which the Upanisads are said to
contain certain key statements called mahavakyas, and
through the subsequent claim that their teachings as a whole
are to be understood through the lens of these seminal
utterances. It is like claiming that if one wants to understand
the New Testament, this is best done in the light of the
overarching statement that ‘Jesus is the Messiah”. All other
parts of the New Testament which do not directly confirm
this—as when Jesus asks Peter: who do you think I am?—or
when Jesus wonders on the cross whether God has forsaken
him—are all to be understood subject to the mahavakya :
“Jesus is the Messiah”.
These mahavakyas , in the light of which the Upanisads
should be understood according to the hermeneutical
tradition of Advaita Vedanta, are the following:
Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
19
I. All this is verily Brahman.
II. I am Brahman.
III. This Atman is Brahman.
IV. That thou art.
To this a fifth is sometimes added:
V. Brahman is spirit (or consciousness).
These statements, however, need to be understood with
extreme exegetical care, for they can be easily
misunderstood. Indeed these rnahavakyas are accepted as
authoritative by other schools of Vedanta as well, so it is not
so much the fact of singling out these statements as
rnahavakyas as their understanding within Advaita Vedanta,
which sets this system apart from other schools of Vedanta. 6
All This is Verily Brahman
The reader will, for instance, note that this first statement
identifies the objective universe with Brahman. The reader
will also note that the second statement (I am Brahman)
identifies the individual with Brahman. However, the exact
manner in which the objective universe is held to be identical
with the Brahman ; and the individual subject (or jiva is held
to be identical with Brahman, are not identical.
Before explaining this difference, it is necessary
to draw attention to an important distinction
between two types of illusion in common
experience. A person may fancy that he sees a
serpent at a distance, while closer scrutiny reveals
to him that it is only a rope. The latter or
correcting knowledge, like practically all
knowledge of the kind, affirms the existence of
something; but it contradicts that object as which
(i.e., serpent) that something appeared before.
He says to himself or feels when he discovers his
error: “It is a rope, not a serpent.” Again a person
looking at a white conch through a sheet of yellow
glass, of whose existence he is not aware, takes it
20
Advaila Vedanta
to be yellow. But a suitable change in his
standpoint will disclose to him that the yellowness
belongs to the glass and not to the conch. Here
also, as in the previous case, the later knowledge
affirms the existence of some reality; unlike it,
however, it does not deny the object as which it
appeared, viz. the conch, but only an aspect of it -
its yellowness. He still sees it as a conch, but only
adds that it is white and not yellow. The illusion in
the first case consists in mistaking a given object
for another that is not given; in the second, it
consists merely in attributing to an object which is
given, a feature that does not really belong to it,
though it also is presented at the time. But for the
interposition of the sheet of glass (upadhi) to which
the yellow actually belongs, there would be no
illusion at all in the latter case. Now these types of
illusions serve to illustrate the difference in the
manner in which, according to Sankara, one and
the same Brahman comes to appear both as the
world and as the individual self (jiva). It gives rise
to the illusion of the world, as the rope does to
that of a serpent in the first example. 7
The relationship of the jiva to Brahman, however, must
be explained with the help of the other example, for the
‘Jiva is not false or illusory as the world is.” 8 Rather it is “its
limitations which are false,” 9 and “these limitations, which
are really its empirical adjuncts, appeared transferred to it,
as in our second example of illusions, the yellowness of the
glass appeared transferred to the conch.” 10 As a result:
The ultimate truth, as realised by a jivanmukta,
denies the world while affirming the underlying
reality of Brahman which is given in all
presentations as positive being (sat) and with which
we may therefore be said to be constantly, though
not consciously, in touch. The individual self, on
Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
21
the other hand, is not illusory in this sense. It is
Brahman itself appearing through media or
limiting adjuncts ( upadhi) like the internal organ
( antahkarana ) which, we may state by the way, are
all elements pertaining to the physical world and,
as such, are illusory. Or, to state the same
otherwise, the individual self when seen sub specie
aeternitatis, is Brahman itself. When this fact is
realized in one’s own experience, what is denied
is not the jivci as a spiritual entity, but only certain
aspects of it, such as its fmitude and its separateness
from other selves. Its conception may thereby
become profoundly transformed, but the
important point is that it is not negated ( badhita )
in the same way in which the physical world is. It
is, on the other hand, reaffirmed, though only as
Brahman. We cannot thereby say that the
individual self is false ( mithya ), as we may that the
world is false. We can only say that it is not truly
the agent, the enjoyer, etc."
The overall picture which emerges on the basis of this
discussion may be presented succinctly as follows:
We now know the advaitic world-view in general.
Brahman is the sole reality, and it appears both as
the objective universe and as the individual subject.
The former is an illusory manifestation of
Brahman, while the latter is Brahman itself
appearing under the limitations which form part
of that illusory universe. 12
I am Brahman
The second statement, “I am Brahman” must now be
examined in more detail. The subjective individual - the I -
is regularly referred to in Advaita as the jivdtman, or jiva for
short. The importance of this compound form will become
clear at the end of this exposition, although the term
22
Advaila Vedanta
jivatman will be referred to as jiva, during the exposition for
the sake of brevity.
In the case of the distinction between the first two
mahavakyas —one which identified the Brahman with the
universe and the other which identified it with the jiva —it
turned out to be the case that although both were said to be
identical with Brahman, the exact nature of this identity was
not identical. The clue to the understanding of the second
mundvakya and the kind of identity it involves is provided by
the fact that although the jiva is referred to as anddi, or
beginningless, from both an empirical and a transcendental
point of view, this “beginninglessness” in the two cases is not
identical in nature.
It was noted earlier that the notion of the jiva is “that of a
complex ( visista ), and points not only to an element which
is identical with Brahman, but also to limiting adjuncts like
the internal organs.” 1 ’ It is important to keep this in mind as
we proceed. The empirical reality about the jiva consists of
the fact that it is caught up in the process of samsara, bound
by its karma, or actions.
Here no doubt, a question will be asked as to when
the responsibility for what one does first occurred.
But such a question is really inadmissible, for it
takes for granted that there was a time when the
self was without any disposition whatsoever. Such
a view of the self is an abstraction as meaningless
as that of mere disposition which characterises no
one. The self, as ordinarily known to us, always
means a self with a certain stock of dispositions;
and this fact is indicated in Indian expositions by
describing karma as beginningless (anddi). It
means that no matter how far back we trace the
history of an individual, we shall never arrive at a
stage when he was devoid of all character. 14
This is one sense in which the jiva is anddi, or beginning¬
less. The other sense in which it is anddi, or beginningless,
Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
23
may be identified by asking the question: does the jlva, in its
true, nature, undergo any change in the process of being
involved in the universe? In this context:
It is desirable to distinguish further between actual
and apparent change. Actual change ( parinama)
signifies that when a particular thing is destroyed,
it does not disappear entirely. A rope when pulled
to pieces remains as fibres. A pot, when broken,
exists as potsherds. In apparent transformation
( vivarta ), on the other hand, the disappearance
is complete. When the illusion of “serpent” is
overcome, there will be nothing of zHeft. It remains
only to add that the jiva is not an effect in either
of these senses. It is not a real transformation, nor
even an illusory appearance of Brahman, so that
no principle of causation is at all involved there. If
we yet speak of the individual self as born, we only
mean that its adjuncts like the physical body come
into being and not the spiritual element in it.
Hence the jiva is described as beginningless
( anadi ). It is, as already indicated. Brahman
appearing in an empirical dress. 15
The distinction between the nature of this example with
the one cited earlier should be noted. In the first example
the difference between the two illusions—of the rope-snake
and tinted-conch—consisted of the fact that while in the
case of the rope-snake, what is not given at all (snake) was
taken as given, in the case of the tinted-conch, only a feature
of the conch, the yellow-tint was taken as given when not
given. The conch as such is given forever, and because it is
'given for ever, no concept of change, whether apparent or
actual, applies to it. It is not the argument that the white
conch was transformed into a yellow conch and when the
error was discovered, was transformed back into a white
conch, when the yellow colour was removed. The yellow colour
was never part of the conch.
24
Advaita Vedanta
Anything which is beginninglessness is assumed under
normal philosophical assumpdons to be endless, i.e. eternal.
So we discover that the jiva is eternal in two senses: (1) It is
eternal in the sense that it is part of sarhsara which, as a
process is eternal, (2) it is etemalin the sense that it is identical
with Brahman , which is eternal. It is perhaps because it is
eternal in both the senses that it can be referred to as ji.va.tman.
As the permanently still witness to its eternally fluctuating
fortunes the jivdlman is known as the sdksi or witness; the
permanent as the witness of the constant.
But this leads to the view that there can be two kinds of
eternalities. Such indeed is the case.
In Indian philosophy two kinds of eternity are
distinguished, a) kutastha nityata and b)
pravaharupa nityata. A thing is kutastha nitya if it is
unchanged forever, while a thing is pravaharupa
nitya if though incessantly changing it does not
alter its pattern ( niyati ). Roughly speaking, a rock,
for example, has the former kind of reality, and a
river the latter kind. The nature of a river is to
flow incessantly, and so long as it does not swerve
from this nature of its, it may be said to be mutably
real ; though not enduringly real as a rock. 16
The jiva part of jivatman partakes of pravaharupa-nityata,
and the atman element in it partakes of kutastha-nityata.
Thus when it is said that “I am Brahman”, it is not the jiva
but the atman element of the complex which is referred to.
Be it also noted that the statement “aham brahma asmi,” (I
am Brahman) while it may lead to the conviction that all
spirit is one, “leaves out of account the entire physical
universe” 17 , thereby indicating the importance of the first
mahavdkya.
Atman is Brahman
We turn now to the third mahavdkya : that atman is Brahman.
Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
25
One may begin by recognizing the importance of this
identification in the light of Vedic and Upanisadic literature.
M. Hiriyanna writes:
Thus Brahman means the eternal principle as
realized in the world as a whole; and atman, the
inmost essence of one’s own self. These two
conceptions—Brahman and atman—are of great
importance and occur not only independently in
the literature of this period, but are sometimes
corelated with each other; and their parallelism is
pointed out by representing the self of the world
as related to the physical universe in the same
manner in which the individual self is related to
the body. Thus in Atharva Veda, the universal self
or world-soul is stated to have “the earth for its
feet, the atmospheric region for its belly, the sky
for its head, the sun and moon for its eyes and the
wind for its breath.” 18
He then goes on to say:
The two conceptions are also sometimes identified;
and it is this happy identification of them that
constitutes the essential teaching of the
Upanishads. They mean that the principle
underlying the world as a whole, and that which
forms the essence of man, are ultimately the same.
Here ended the long Indian quest for the
pervasive cause of all things—the search, as the
Upanishads express it, for “that by knowing which
all will be known.” Passages descriptive of Brahman
alone or of atman alone occur frequently in the
Upanishads; but they are not peculiar to them,
being also found in the earlier literature. Their
explicit identification, on the other hand, is
specifically Upanishadic. 19
What, however, is the philosophical importance of this
identification apart from its textual significance?
26
Advaita Vedanta
The answer to this question is best provided by the
perspective that the search for the ultimate reality in the
Upanisads followed two routes: an external route and an
internal route. The external approach was represented by
the search for the ultimate ground of the external universe.
The following passage from the Upanisads provides a glimpse
of such an approach in operation:
The regressus to Brahma, the ultimate world-ground.
Then Gargi Vacaknavl questioned him. Yajhavalkya, said
she, since all this world is woven, warp and woof, on water, on
what, pray, is the water woven, warp and woof?
‘On wind, O Gargi.’
‘On what then, pray, is the wind woven, warp and woof?’
‘On the atmosphere-worlds, O Gargi.’
‘On what then, pray, are the atmosphere-worlds woven,
warp and woof?’
‘On the worlds of the Gandharvas, O Gargi.’
‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of the Gandharvas
woven, warp and woof?’
‘On the worlds of the sun, O Gargi.’
‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of the sun woven,
warp and woof?’
‘On the worlds of the moon, O Gargi.’
‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of the moon woven,
warp and woof?’
‘On the worlds of the stars, O Gargi.’
‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of the stars woven,
warp and woof?’
‘On the worlds of the Gods, O Gargi.’
‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of the Gods woven,
warp and woof?’
‘On the worlds of Indra, O Gargi.’
‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of Indra woven, warp
and woof ?’
‘On the worlds of Prajapati, O Gargi.’
‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of Prajapati woven,
warp and woof?’
Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
27 .
'On the worlds of Brahma, O GargT.’
‘On what then, pray, are the worlds of Brahma woven,
warp and woof?’
Yajnavalkya said: ‘GargT, do not question too much, lest
your head fall off. In truth, you are questioning too much
about a divinity about which further questions cannot be
asked. GargT, do not over-question.’
Thereupon GargT VacaknavT held her peace. 20
The internal route took the form of the search for the
ultimate ground of one’s being or personality.
But what was the essential self of man? The term
introduced into Vedic inquiry was the common
word for “self,” atman, used generally as a reflexive
pronoun. From this general usage, atman was given
a more specific meaning as the essential part of
man, his basic reality. At times this was taken to be
the body or the trunk of the body as distinguished
from the limbs. Gradually, however, the atman was
distinguished from the gross physical body; it was
the inner self, the principle or entity that gave man
his essential nature. 21
The following Upanisadic passage (Brhadaranyaka
Upanisad IV. 1-6) also provides a useful scriptural if simple
illustration of this kind of an internal approach.
The light of man is the soul
1. Yajnavalkya came to Janaka, [king] of Videha. He
thought to himself: I will not talk.
But [once] when Janaka, [king] of Videha, and
Yajnavalkya were discussing together at an Agnihotra,
Yajnavalkya granted the former a boon. He chose
asking whatever question he wished. He granted it to
him. So [now] the king, [speaking] first, asked him”
2. Yajnavalkya, what light does a person here have?
He has the light of the sun, 0 king, he said, ‘for with the
28
Advaita Vedanta
3.
sun, indeed, as in his light one sits, moves around,
does his work, and returns.’
‘Quite so, Yajnavalkya.
‘But when the sun has set, Yajnavalkya, what light does
a person here have?’
‘The moon, indeed, is his light,’ said he, ‘for the
1 i 1 ww 11
in his
4.
does his work, and returns.’
‘Quite so, Yajnavalkya.
‘But when the sun has set, and the moon has set, what
light does a person here have?’
‘Fire, indeed, is his light,’ said he, ‘for with fire,
indeed, as in his light one sits, moves around, does his
work, and returns.’
‘Quite so, Yajnavalkya.
But when the sun has set, Yajnavalkya, and the moon
has set, and the fire has gone out, what light does a
person here have?’
‘Speech, indeed, is his light,’ said he, ‘for with speech,
indeed, as in his light one sits, moves around, does his
work, and returns. Therefore, verily O king, where
one does not discern even his own hands, when a voice
is raised, then one goes straight towards it.’
‘Quite so, Yajnavalkya.
But when the sun has set, Yajnavalkya, and the moon
has set, and the fire has gone out, and speech is
hushed, what light does a person here have?’
‘The soul ( atman ), indeed, is his light,’ said he, ‘for with
the soul, indeed, as in his light one sits, moves around,
does his work, and returns. 22
Elsewhere in the Upanisads a more detailed analysis of
the human personality is carried out in an attempt to identify
the atman. One such analysis is characterised by its division
of the human person into five sheaths, while another focuses
on the states of consciousness experienced by the human
being.
Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
29
The Taittinya Upanisad (2. 1-6) speaks of the five sheaths
or kosas, which the human personality may be said to consist
of. “In this passage an attempt is made to analyze man at five
levels—proceeding from the grosser forms to the subtler,
and, therefore, more real forms. The real man transcends
the physical, vital, mental, and intellectual aspects and even
the beatific aspect. It is in the end suggested that the real
self of man is identical with Brahman, the ultimate principle,
the absolute, which is its raison d’etre’.”"
Similarly, in another account ( Chandogya Upanisad 8: 7-
12) “the real essential self is successively identified with the
bodily self, the dream self, and the self in deep sleep, and it
is suggested that all these three teachings are quite
inadequate, for none of the three conditions, namely, of
wakefulness, of dream and of deep sleep, can the nature of
the self be said to conform.” 24 The point is pressed that “the
real self is neither body, mind nor complete negation of
consciousness. The self is certainly conscious but of nothing
else but itself. It is pure self consciousness as such and it is in
this condition that it is identical with the highest reality.” 25
This picture is fully elaborated in the Mandukya Upanisad} 6
State of Consciousness
State of Self
Waking
Vaisvanara
Dreaming
Taijasa
Deep Sleep
Prajna
The Fourth
Atman
In the foregoing passages one notices how, as a result of
going inward within the human personality, the Upanisadic
seers identified the Atman, as the real self, whether such an
exercise focused on the constituents of the self (as in the
case of the five sheaths) or on the states of consciousness
experienced by the self (namely waking, dreaming and deep
sleep). One needs to remind oneself now that as a result of
going outward into the universe, the Upanisadic seers
identified its real basis as Brahman, while looking inward the
30
Advaita Vedanta
Upanisadic thinker realised the inner self to be Atman}'
Now the great discovery the Upanisads made was of the
identity of the ground of the universe with the ground of
our own being. Ainslie Embree elaborates this point with
the help of three passages cited below. In the first he
describes the quest of the ultimate ground of the objective
universe, in the second of the individual subject. The two
are brought together in the final passage.
1) In their quest for some ultimate ground for the
world of natural phenomena, of time and space,
and of human existence, the Upanishadic sages
came to the conception of brahman, an
undeniable, impersonal, unknowable power. 28
2) Over against the questions concerning the
ground of the external world are to be set those
that probe inward, asking what is meant by the
concept of the Self. The Self could be identified
with the physical body, or “food,” as some of the
Upanishadic thinkers were inclined to say. But
consciousness, breath, will, all had claims to be
regarded as the Self, and all were unsatisfactory as
final definitions. What was needed was something
that could be identified as being beyond change,
something that was in fact immortal. This was
found in the conception of the atman . 29
3) In the macrocosm of the universe, the sages saw
brahman-, in the microcosm of their own being they
saw the atman. The realization that there is no
distinction between the two, that the ground of
one’s own being is identical with the ground of
the universe, is the great discovery of the
Upanishadic thinkers. “Whoever thus knows, 1 am
brahman," declares the sage, “becomes this all.
Even the gods have not the power to prevent him
from becoming thus, for he thus becomes the self.”
It should be carefully noted that this is not
Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
31
described as merging with the divine or union
between God and man or reaching a state of unity.
It is rather a recognition that there is no “divine”
as distinct from the individual, no being over
against the self, no process of becoming what once
was not, but only the knowledge of the truth that
always existed. ,0
This identification of atman and brahman may be said to
strengthen both, as it were. M. Hiriyanna points out, for
instance, that the approach to the ultimate reality via
Brahman runs into some difficulties:
Such a principle need not be spiritual in its nature,
and may well be a material or physical entity.
Further, an objective conception like the above is
little more than a hypothesis to account for the
origin of the universe; and as there is nothing
compelling us to regard it as actually existing, there
being no logical absurdity in denying it. Some
thinkers already seem to have done so in the
Upanishadic period and maintained that ‘in the
beginning this world was just non-being.” 1
Similarly, the approach to the ultimate reality via atman is
also not free from difficulties:
If we start from the idea of the self, instead of that
of Brahman, we meet with a similar difficulty, for,
while the self points to what is spiritual and is an
incontrovertible certainty, it is, as known to us,
necessarily limited in its nature. Whatever view we
may take of its nature, it is determined on one
side by the world of nature, and on the other by
the other selves. 12
But when the two are identified they seem to have the
effect of helping overcome each others’ shortcomings. It
was pointed out that Brahman as such might appear too
hypothetical to be real. But by “its identification with atman
the establishment of the spiritual character of this principle
32
Advaita Vedanta
and the removal of the uncertainty about its existence are
both accomplished.” 13 Similarly, it was hinted that the atman
may appear too personal, to the point of being limited, and
finite, if very real; “it is this deficiency of fmiteness that is
made good by its identification with Brahman or the all-
comprehensive first cause of the universe.” 14
This identification of atman and brahman is capable of
being interpreted in several ways. Troy Wilson Organ notes
some of these in the following passage:
The question to be asked first is about the meaning
of the connective “is.” The word “is” has at least
five logically discernible meanings: 1) predication,
e.g., “This apple is green”; 2) class inclusion, e.g.,
“Fido is a dog”; 3) class membership, e.g., “Brown
pelicans are vanishing”; 4) equality, e.g., ‘Two and
two is four”; 5) identity, e.g., ‘TV is [equivalent to]
4.” Atman is Brahman seems to be a form of idendty
or equivalence. There are many classes of identity:
1) absolute physical identity, e.g., “A is identical
with A”; 2) relative physical identity, e.g., identical
twins; 3) same entity at various stages of
development, e.g., Joe Doakes as boy andJ.D. as
man; 4) same species, e.g., Harry Truman as man
and Herbert Hoover as man; 5) same being in
different contexts, e.g., Jane as mother and Jane
as wife; 6) whole and part, e.g., a cup of water
dipped from the Atlantic Ocean and the Atlantic
Ocean; 7) appearance and reality, e.g., a
photograph and the person of whom it is a
photograph; 8) the same object considered from
different perspectives, e.g., the duck-rabbit
example of perception. Probably the last subclass
of identity is the identity of Atman and Brahman:
Atman is Totality viewed internally; Brahman is
Totality viewed externally. 35
The main point to note here is that the identity must be
Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
33
understood ontologically. The passage cited above helps
explain what is meant by identity. It is equally important to
realize what is wot meant by identity. First, when it is claimed
in Advaita Vedanta that Atman is Brahman, it is not claimed
that Atman becomes Brahman, as, for example, in a moment
of realization. If anything, the realization consists of the fact
that Atman is Brahman, was Brahman, and will ever be
Brahman. The point may be explained with the help of the
parable “Like the King’s Son,” in which “a prince, brought
up as a hunter from infancy, discover[s] afterward that he is
of royal blood. It involves no becoming, for he has always
been a prince and that all he has to do is to feel or realize
that he is one.” 56 The metaphysical moral of the whole story
is that there was never a time when the mountaineer was
not the Prince. He did not become a Prince when told he
was one. He already was. He only recognized as a fact
something that was already true.
Second, when it is claimed in Advaita Vedanta that Atman
is Brahman it is not meant that Atman merges into Brahman.
An example from astronomy will be helpful here. For a long
time astronomers identified two distant stars—a “morning
star” and an “evening star,” till it was discovered that both
were Venus. Did it then mean that the morning star merged
into the evening star, or the evening star merged into the
morning star? As both were already and always Venus,
nothing of this sort can be said to have happened.
Third, it is sometimes suggested that “ Atman is Brahman
is not a metaphysical statement but a soteriological
statement.” 37 Consider the following interpretation offered
by Rudolph Otto: ‘The word is in the mystical formula of
identification [Atman is Brahman] has a significance which
it does not contain in logic. It is no copula as in the sentence:
s is P; it is no sign of equality in a reversible equation. It is not
the is of a normal assertion of identity.” In order to suggest
what the statement is attempting to express, Otto adds, “For
instance one might say instead of lam Brahman, lam “existed"
34
Advaita Vedanta
by Brahman or essenced by Brahman, or Brahman exists me."
“The suggestion is intriguing but not acceptable as such
within Advaita Vedanta.
Fourth, Atman is Brahman does not mean that Atman is a
portion of Brahman. The jiva as the embodied Atman may,
in an extended sense, be said to be comprised in Brahman
as parts of the universe of which it is the substratum but that
is as much as one can say, for the truth of the matter is that
‘just as a pure transparent white crystal is wrongly imagined
to be red on account of a red flower placed near it, or just as
the colorless sky is wrongly imagined to be sullied W'ith dirt
by the ignorant, or just as the rope is wrongly taken to the
be a snake in the twilight, or just as the shell is mistaken for
silver, similarly the non-dual Atman and Brahman is wrongly
imagined to be the empirical self.” 39 Sankara’s comment
on Brahmasutra 2.3.50 must be employed here to point out
that “the individual soul is not directly the highest Atman...
nor is it different from Atman.” It is not the former because
it is subject to the limiting adjuncts, but it is not different
for it is also bereft of the limiting adjuncts. All the empirical
selves are also comprised in Brahman, but the exact nature
of their relationship is a matter of debate. 40
That Thou Art
The fourth mahavakya is: That Thou Art. An analysis of how
this great utterance is to be understood provides a useful entry
into the hermeneutics of Vedic statements.
It was pointed out earlier that, as distinguished from the
other four orthodox schools of Hindu philosophy, those of
MImamsa and Vedanta actually base their philosophy on the
text of the Vedas rather than merely accepting Vedic
authority as such in common with these other schools. It is
therefore in these two schools that the issue of Vedic exegesis
is squarely addressed. The key exegetical question as always
is: how is the purport of a textual passage to be determined?
Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
35
The Mlmamsa school of thought reached the conclusion
that the purport of a textual passage should be determined
by keeping six factors in mind. This six-fold criteria is
technically called the sadlinga and is said to consist of the
following six elements:
1) unity of the initial and concluding passages
(upakramopasarhkdraikya ); 2) the recurrence of
theme ( abhyasa ); 3) the new conclusion sought
to be brought out ( apiirva ); 4) the fruitfulness of
such a conclusion ( phala ); 5) the commendation
or criticism of it throughout ( arthavada ); 6) the
argument throughout {upapatti). The Advaita
Vedanta also accepts these criteria as the pramanas
for finding purport."
However, although both Mlmamsa and Advaita Vedanta
accept these criteria, they assign interpretive priority to
different parts of the Vedas—namely, the earlier sections and
the latter sections respectively, and this accounts for the fact
that they arrive at different conclusions regarding the
purport of the Vedas while applying the same criteria. It
should not be forgotten, however, that other systems of
Vedanta besides Advaita also accept these criteria yet reach
different conclusions regarding even the purport of the
meaning of the “latter portion” of the Vedas. These
differences, nevertheless, are the result of differences in
interpretation of the same Vedic texts, whereas the
difference between Mimarhsa and Vedanta, and particularly
Advaita Vedanta, arise from the application of the same
exegetical criteria to different sets of Vedic texts.
One may now proceed to examine how Advaitic exegesis
works by applying it to a particular scriptural passage. The
passage selected here is a famous one, which occurs in the
Chnndogya Upanisad. It is in the form of a dialogue between
a father (Uddalaka) and his son (Svetaketu). The following
extract provides the setting:
36
Advaita Vedanta
1. Om! Now, there was Svetaketu Aruneya. To him
his father said: ‘Live the life of a student of sacred
knowledge. Verily, my dear, from our family there
is no one unlearned lin the Vedas] ( an-ucya ), a
Brahman by connection (brahma-bandhu ), as it
were.’
2. He then, having become a pupil at the age of
twelve, having studied all the Vedas, returned at
the age of twenty-four, conceited, thinking himself
learned, proud.
3. Then his father said to him: ‘Svetaketu, my dear,
since now you are conceited, think yourself
learned, and are proud, did you also ask for that
teaching whereby what has not been heard of
becomes heard of, what has not been thought of
becomes thought of, what has not been
understood becomes understood?’
4. ‘How, pray, sir, is that teaching?’
5. ‘Just as, my dear, by one piece of clay everything
made of clay may be known—the modification is
merely a verbal distinction, a name; the reality is
just “clay”.
6. Just as, my dear, by one copper ornament
everything made of copper may be known—the
modification is merely a verbal distinction, a name;
the reality is just “copper”.
7. Just as, my dear, by one nail scissors everything
made of iron may be known—the modification is
merely a verbal distinction, a name; the reality is
just “iron” so, my dear, is that teaching’.
8. ‘Verily, those honored men did not know this;
for, if they had known it, why would they not have
told me? But do you, sir, tell me it.’
So be it, my dear,’ said he. 42
Advaila Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
37
We plug into the ongoing discussion at a point when the
father is explaining the spiritual import of death to his son:
9. On this point, my dear, understand that this
(body) is a sprout which has sprung up. It will not
be without a root.
10. Where else could its root be than in water?
With water, my dear, as a sprout, look for heat as
the root. With heat, my dear, as a sprout, look for
Being as the root. All creatures here, my dear, have
Being as their root, have Being as their abode, have
Being as their support.
But how, verily my dear, each of these three
divinities, upon reaching man, becomes threefold,
as has previously been said.
When a person here is deceasing, my dear, his
voice goes into his mind; his mind, into his breath;
his breath, into heat; the heat, into the highest
divinity.
11. That which is the finest essence— (7) the
whole world has that is its soul. That is Realty ( satya).
That is Atman (Soul). That art thou, Svetaketu.
‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’
‘So be it, my dear,’ said he.
The reader will notice that the mahavakya under
discussion: That art thou has made its appearance in this piece
of dialogue between the father and the son. It will recur
eight more times and the passages in which it forms the
concluding statement are reproduced below. In these
passages, however, the same mahavakya appears in different
contexts. I shall therefore introduce each occurrence with
a brief note, indicating the point to look for. In the next
occurrence, for instance, the metaphor of honey is used. It could
be argued that, among other things, the passage highlights
the bliss that flows from the realization of the identity of
Advaita Vedanta
88
Atman and Brahman , symbolised by honey.""
1. ‘As the bees, my dear, prepare honey by collecting
the essences of different trees and reducing the
essence to a unity,
2. as they are not able to discriminate “1 am the essence
of this tree,” “I am the essence of that tree”—even so,
indeed, my dear, all creatures here, though they reach
Being, know not “We have reached Being.”
3. Whatever they are in this world, whether tiger, or lion,
or wolf, or boar, or worm, or fly, or gnat, or mosquito,
that they become.
4. That which is the finest essence - this whole world
has that as its soul. That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul).
That art thou, Svetaketu.
‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’
‘So be it, my dear,’ said he.
In the following passage the metaphor of the ocean is used. It
has been proposed that the passage hints at the immensity
of the experience of the ultimate reality. The loss of
individuality, yet its persistence as universality is hinted at. 44
The river ceases to be the river, but does not thereby cease
to be.
1. ‘These rivers, my dear, flow, the eastern toward the
east, the western toward the west. They go just from
the ocean to the ocean. They become the ocean itself.
As there they know not “I am this one,” “I am that
one”
2. Even so, indeed, my dear, all creatures here, though
they have come forth from Being, know not “We have
come forth from Being.” Whatever they are in this
world, whether tiger, or lion, or wolf, or boar, or worm,
or fly, or gnat, or mosquito, that they become.
3. That which is the finest essence—this whole world has
that as its soul. That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul).
That art thou, Svetaketu.
Advaita Vedanta; A Scriptural Approach
39
‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’
‘So be it, my dear,’ said he.
In tile following passage the metaphor of the tree has been
employed. It highlights the intrinsic immanence and
interpenetration involved in the identification of atman and
brahman.
This passage is best understood perhaps in the light of
the following comment by Heinrich Zimmer: “According to
this Brahmanical formula, the dialectic of the universe is a
manifestation of a transcendent, non-dual, trans-dual, yet
immanent principle, which both gives forth the world of
names and forms ( namarupa ) and inhabits it as its animating
principle. The dualism of natura naturans (prakrti) and the
transcendent immaterial monad ( purusa) is thus itself
transcended’’. 45
1. ‘Of this great tree, my dear, if some one should strike
at the root, it would bleed but still live. If some one
should strike at its middle, it would bleed, but still
live. If some one should strike at its top, it would
bleed, but still live. Being pervaded By Atman (Soul),
it continues to stand, eagerly drinking in moisture
and rejoicing.
2. If the life leaves one branch of it, then it dries up. It
leaves a second; then that dries up. It leaves a third;
then that dries up. It leaves the whole; the whole
dries up. Even so, indeed, my dear, understand,’ said
he.
3. ‘Verily, indeed, when life has left it, this body dies.
The life does not die.
That which is the finest essence—this whole world has
that as its soul. That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul). That
art thou, Svetaketu.
‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’
‘So be it, my dear,’ said he.
In the following passage the ‘metaphor of the seed’ is
40
Advaila Vedanta
used. It highlights the subtlety of the identity of Brahman
and atman\ among other things. J. Brereton summarizes its
significance as follows:
First, the passage establishes that the tree grows
and lives because of an invisible essence. Then, in
the refrain, it says that everything, the whole world,
exists by means of such an essence. This essence is
the truth, for it is lasting and real. It is the self, for
everything exists with reference to it. Then and
finally, Uddalaka personalizes the teaching.
Svetaketu should look upon himself in the same way.
He, like the tree and the whole world, is pervaded
by this essence, which is his final reality and his
true self. 4 "
There may also be the implication here that “the world
which has name and form arises from pure being which is
subtle and does not possess name and form.” 47 The passage
runs as follows:
1. ‘Bring hither a fig from there.’
‘Here it is, sir.’
‘Divide it.’
‘It is divided, sir.’
‘What do you see there?’
‘These rather ( iva) fine seeds, sir.’
‘Of these, please ( ahga ), divide one.’
‘It is divided, sir.’
‘What do you see there?’
‘Nothing at all, sir.’
2. Then he said to him: ‘Verily, my dear, that finest
essence which you do not perceive—verily, my dear,
from that finest essence this great Nyagrodha (sacred
fig) tree thus arises.
3. Believe me, my dear,’ said he, ‘that soul which is the
finest essence - this whole world has that as its soul.
That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul). That art thou,
Svetaketu.
Advaila Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
41
Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’
'So be it, my dear,’ said he.
The following passage may be read as an answer to the
question: if Pure Being is the essence of all that exists, why
is it not perceived?” The answer proposed is through the
parable of the salt. Just as “we are able to perceive salt in the
.i rd,_ U .1,-^ ..4- U,, A
Wdici LLiiiOLigii Ldatcj Liiuugu n^t uy iiitans ui tuucii aitu
sight even so we will be able to perceive Pure Being by other
means though it is not obvious to our senses”. 4 " The passage
hints at the transcendental yet experienceable nature of
the identity of atman and Brahman.
1. ‘Place this salt in water. In the morning come unto
me.’
Then he did so.
Then he said to him: ‘That salt you placed in the water
last evening—please bring it hither.’
Then he grasped for it, but did not find it, as it was
completely dissolved.
2. ‘Please take a sip of it from this end,’ said he. ‘How is
it?’
‘Salt.’
‘Take a sip from the middle,’ said he. ‘How is it?’
‘Salt.’
‘Take a sip from that end,’ said he. ‘How is it?’
‘Salt.’
‘Set it aside. Then come unto me.’
He did so, saying, ‘It is always the same.’
Then he said to him: ‘Verily, indeed, my dear, you do
not perceive Being here. Verily, indeed, it is here.
3. That which is the finest essence—this whole world has
that as its soul. That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul).
That art thou, Svetaketu.
‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’
‘So be it, my dear,’ said he.
The next passage contains the parable of the blindfolded
42
Advaita Vedanta
person. Since at the moment we are blind to the reality, how
might we reach it? This passage emphasizes the advisability
of having a suitable guide or teacher. As Franklin Edgerton
noted long ago:
This section contains the beautiful simile of the man
brought to a strange land and left blindfolded to wander
about aimlessly, until some one removes his eye-bandage
and tells him in which direction to go: then he finds his
way home. Just so a man in this world who has not received
the true instruction in Upanisadic philosophy wanders
about aimlessly, his mental eyesight dimmed by the eye-
bandages of ignorance, until a teacher removes the
bandage of ignorance and tells him in what direction to
shape his life’s course; then he will arrive at his true goal. 49
1. ‘Just as, my dear, one might lead away from the
Gandharas a person with his eyes bandaged, and then
abandon him in an uninhabited place; as there he
might be blown forth either to the east, to the north,
or to the south, since he has been led off with his eyes
bandaged and deserted with his eyes bandaged;
2. as, if one released his bandages and told him, “In that
direction would be the Gandharas; go in that
direction!” he would, if he were a sensible man, by
asking [his way] from village to village, and being
informed, arrive home at the Gandharas—even so
here on earth one who has a teacher knows: “I shall
remain here only so long as I shall not be released [from
the bonds of ignorance.] Then I shall arrive home.”
3. That which is the finest essence—this whole world has
that as its soul. That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul).
That art thou, Svetaketu.
‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’
‘So be it, my dear,’ said he.
In the following passage the significance of this insight in
the context of the experience of death is explained. The
implication seems to be that in dying a person, who has
Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
43
realized the identity of Atman and Brahman, transcends all
forms of phenomenal existence in a post-mortem state.
1 .
‘Also, my dear, around a [deathly] sick person his
kinsmen gather, and ask, “Do you know me?” So long
as his voice does not go into his mind, his mind into
flic Krpiffi
highest divinity—so long he knows.
2. Then when his voice goes into his mind, his mind into
his breath, his breath into heat, the heat into the
highest divinity—then he knows not.
3. That which is the finest essence—this whole world has
that as its soul. That is Reality. That is Atman (Soul).
That art thou, Svetaketu.
‘Do you, sir, cause me to understand even more.’
‘So be it, my dear,’ said he.
In the following passage ‘the metaphor of the heated axe
of the ordeal’ is proposed. It highlights the invulnerability
conferred by the realization of the identity, through what to
some might seem a measure of overconfidence in the ability
of metaphysical reality to affect empirical reality. 50
1. ‘And also, my dear, they lead up a man seized by the
hand, and call: “He has stolen! He has committed a
theft! Heat the axe for him!” If he is the doer thereof,
thereupon he makes himself ( atmanam ) untrue.
Speaking untruth, covering himself with untruth, he
seizes hold of the heated axe and is burned. Then he
is slain.
2. But if he is not the doer thereof, thereupon he makes
himself true. Speaking truth, covering himself with
truth, he seizes hold of the heated axe and is not
burned. Then he is released.
3. As in this case he would not be burned [because of
i the truth]. So this whole world has that [truth] as its
i soul. That is Reality. That is atman (Soul). That art
r thou, Svetaketu.
44
Advaita Vedanta
Then he understood it from him—yea, he understood. ’ 1
Let us now apply the six-fold criteria to determine the
import of the culled passages. The first criterion pertains to
the unity of the initial and concluding passages. The initial
passage states: “That Art Thou”, and so does the concluding
passage. The second criterion consists of thematic repetition.
The statement “That Art Thou” is repeated “nine times” 52
in the selection. The third criterion consists of novelty. The
claim “That Art Thou” is novel to the point of being
sensational. The fourth criterion pertains to the result. The
acquisition of knowledge, even saving knowledge, is the
result. The fifth criterion is commendation. Quite obviously
this insight is commended throughout, and the fact of it
being dealt with throughout also fulfils the sixth and final
criterion. Note that the purport is that of the non-duality
between “That” and “This.”
Now that the purport has been established, how is it to be
understood - literally or figuratively? 53
Sankara takes it primarily in a literal sense, 54 and the point
is made strongly in Advaita Vedanta that the “sentence
expresses apposition ( samanadhikarana ) between the two,
Brahman and the individual soul.” 55
From the point of view of Advaita Vedanta the fact that
the two are in apposition is important, because it enables
one to point out that how the statement may not be (mis-)
understood. (1) It is not to be understood as a tautology
because “the Upanisadic sentence removes the delusion of
difference between Brahman and the individual soul, even
though their identity is known as soon as the true nature of
both is known. For, Brahman is the self of all, and the ‘Self
is not really the body or the ego, but Being.” 56 2) It is not to
be understood as an identity between two different things as
cause and effect (“The pot is earthen”) or substance and
attribute (“The lotus is blue”) because here the identity.of a
thing with itself is asserted. 3) It is not to be understood as
an injunction to treat them as such, as for instance in
Advaiia Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
45
meditation, because the sentence has no reference to action.
It is a statement of fact, not an exhortation. 57 4) It is not to
be understood as implication. This view “is based on the
presupposition that words refer directly to substantives and
not to attributes of substantives, and that when words have
to refer to attributes they do so by implication.” 58
A. critic msy ask, ‘If it is said tHat Here tHe identity
of the substantives only—Brahman and jlva—is
asserted, how have been they distinguished from
their attributes?’ An Advaitin may answer that
other Hindu schools (e.g. that of Ramanuja) also
accept omniscience etc., as attributes of Brahman
and ignorance etc., as attributes of jlva. Further,
as will be shown later, prior to the hearing of That
Thou art the meanings of Thou and That should
be clarified (tattvam-padartha-sodhana). When a
man, who has clarified for himself the meanings of
these words, hears the sentence That Thou art, he
will obviously understand that the asserted identity
is only between the substantives and not between
the attributes; just as when somebody tells him bring
the jar, he understands by jar not jarhood, but a
particular thing. If, then, the question occurs to
him, what happens to the attributes? scriptural texts,
supplemented by reasoning, will demonstrate to
him that they are products of maya. Thus an
Advaitin can try to rebut this criticism. 59
Brahman is Spirit
(Dne “may now examine the fifth mahavakya, that Brahman
is spirit, i.e., that it is spiritual rather than material in nature.
In order to fully appreciate this mahavakya, three
realizations need to be made available to our consciousness.
The first is that both material objects and immaterial
conspicuousness are equally the components of everyday
46
Advaita Vedanta
existence. This fact is so obvious that it runs the risk of being
overlooked. Each individual is fully aware of material objects,
as well as of the immaterial consciousness which characterizes
the person as an individual subject. In fact every 7 individual
himself or herself possesses a body and a mind—one material,
the other immaterial in nature.
The second point to recognize is that, as pointed out
earlier, this pervasive fact gives rise to three fundamental
philosophical positions. Although both matter and immaterial
consciousness are equally given in human existence, one
could argue that each could be an epiphenomenon of the
other. In other words, although both are experienced as
empirical reality, only one of the two—matter or spirit may
constitute the ultimate reality. Thus one could argue for
materialism on the ground that, in the last analysis,
consciousness is a byproduct of material forces and processes.
Just as wetness is a quality possessed by none of the two gases
which compose water, consciousness could emerge as a
property out of material bases. It could also be argued, from
the other end of the spectrum, that consciousness is the
only ultimate reality, and that matter is its product.
Consciousness could produce matter just as the living body
produces lifeless nails or hair. A third position, which refuses
to reduce each to either is also possible —and may be
described as that of fundamental dualism. It was noted
earlier that the various schools of Indian Philosophy can be
arranged on an axis of:
Materialism. Dualism. Idealism.
In the usual order of enumeration of these systems one
starts with the Carvaka school, regularly characterized as
materialists, and one concludes with the discussion of schools
of Vedanta which are prevailingly idealistic. This also holds
true of Advaita Vedanta even more so.
A third point now requires to be considered: that it is
difficult to refute the claims of materialism or idealism on
Advaita Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach
47
purely logical grounds.™ In other words, we seem to run here
into the limits of reason, so that the significance to be
attached to scriptural authority in general, and Advaita
Vedanta in particular, takes on a new charge.
With this in mind one may now approach the Advaitic
position which aligns itself clearly with the ultimate reality
of the spirit. The following passage provides a remarkably
clear statement of the Advaitic position on this point:
The Advaita definitely denies that there can be
any relation at all between two such disparate
entities as spirit and matter. But at the same time,
it cannot be forgotten that our investigation of
experience leads us to the conclusion that they
are not only together but are often identified with
each other as implied, for example, when a person
says “I am walking.” Here the act of walking is
obviously a feature characterizing the physical
body; and yet it is predicated of the person’s self
which is spiritual. The only explanation conceivable
is that their association must be a mere appearance
or, in other words, that the relation between them
is ultimately false. Sarhkara treats of this point in
his celebrated preamble to the commentary on
the Vedanta Sutra, which is very brief and is written
in what may be described as his “shorthand style.”
“The self or the I-element," he says there, “is so
opposed to the not-self or the Thou-element that
they can never be predicated of each other.” A
necessary corollary to this conclusion is that one of
the relata is unreal. Both, of course, cannot be
regarded as unreal, for in that case, since all the
three elements—the two relata and the relation—
become false, and since the idea of falsehood
necessarily points to a standard of truth, we shall
have to postulate another reality from the
viewpoint of which we declare them to be false.
48
Advaila Vedanta
The advaitin therefore takes for granted that it is
matter which is false. The other alternative would
Jesuit in materialism, whose untcnability we have
already seen . 61
Advaita as pointed out in the passage, also argues against
materialism. As M. Hiriyanna notes:
But even at its best the materialistic theory carries
no conviction with it, since it tries to account for
the higher principle of mind by the lower one of
matter. Starting with the existence of matter, it
explains mind as only a function of it. But in thus
starting, the theory has already taken for granted
that there is no mind, although it is as much an
implication of experience as matter. In fact, we
have no conception at all of matter, except as it
appears to an observing mind. Believing in the
existence of the one thus amounts to believing in
the existence of the other. The truth that may
underlie the theory is that all the things of the
world can finally be brought under a single head,
but it is wrong to conclude from this that that
unitary source is necessarily physical. 62
The statement is not just negative. It can also be argued
that the spiritual premise about the ultimate reality as
Brahman is implied in its description as saccidananda. Thus,
M. Hiriyanna writes:
The spiritual and unitary character of this absolute
reality is very well expressed by the classical phrase
saccidananda. As a single term defining its nature,
it is met with only in the later Upanishads; but its
three elements— sat, cit and ananda —are used of
Brahman, singly and in pairs, even in the earliest
of them. Sat, which means “being,” points to the
positive character of Brahman distinguishing it
from all non-being. But positive entities, to judge
from our experience, may be spiritual or not. The
Advailu Vedanta: A Scriptural Approach 49
next epithet tit, which means “sentience,” show's
that it is spiritual. The last epithet ananda, which
stands for “peace,” indicates its unitary and all-
embracing character, inasmuch as variety is the
source of all trouble and restlessness. “Fear arises
from the other,” as a famous Upanishadic saying
has it. Thus the three epithets together signify that
Brahman is the sole spiritual reality of the
Absolute, which comprehends not only all being
(sat) but also all thought (tit) so that whatever
partakes of the character of either must eventually
be traced to it. In other words, it is the source of
the whole universe, while it is self-existent and self-
revealing, there being no other entity from which
it could be derived or by which it might be made
known. (i:!
PART II
Advaita Vedanta:
A Rational Approach
i
We may begin our rational analysis with any object found in
the universe, even something as simple, as say, bracelet of
silver, in order to illustrate the rational approach to Advaita
Vedanta.
The examination of the bracelet might begin with the
recognition of the fact that the bracelet is made of silver. It
has its origin in silver, and as without silver the “bracelet of
silver” would not exist, silver is the material cause of the
bracelet. The “bracelet of silver”, in this way of looking at it, is
thus an effect, with silver as its material cause.
The next step would now consist of examining the
relationship of this bracelet, as effect, to silver which is its
material cause. When the relationship between the two is
closely examined, some points seem to emerge in clearer view
as a result of this inquiry. It turns out that the effect is nothing
more than the cause—that is to say, the bracelet is made of
nothing other than silver. Note that one is not claiming that
the bracelet is nothing more than the silver, in the sense that
it is silver cast in a particular form and can be worn on the
wrist, in a way plain silver cannot be worn. In this sense the
bracelet of silver could be taken to mean to be “more” than
silver. However, one can make bracelets of different shapes
and sizes out of the same piece of silver but even in the new
forms the material of which the form is made is nothing other
than silver. In this sense the effect does not exceed the cause;
“the effect is nothing more than the cause.”
54
Advaita Vedanta
Moreover, although we might draw a distinction, when
we speak, between a “bracelet of silver” and silver, as it were,
the two are really inseparable. Or to put it another way, just
as an effect is nothing more than the material cause, it is
also nothing less than it, in the sense that it cannot be
removed or divorced from it. That is to say, the effect cannot
exist without the cause; we can separate the idea of the
bracelet from the bracelet, but we cannot separate the
bracelet of silver from silver. The bracelet of silver is shot
through with silver, through and through.
So the first realization is that the effect is nothing more
than the material cause, and the second is that the effect is
inseparable from the material cause. These points are more
or less obvious but no less significant is a third point—that
the effect must pre-exist in the material cause. The ‘idea’
of a bracelet can exist apart from the material cause, but
the actual bracelet, as effect, must pre-exist in the material
cause. If this were not the case,
then it would in principle be possible to produce
any effect from any material cause. In fact, we
cannot even think of a non-[pre]-existent entity
coming into existence. We can only think of a
substance changing from one form into another. If
something non-existent could ever be brought into
existence, there would be no reason why we could
not press oil out of sand (where it is non-existent),
and why we should have to select only a particular
material, namely oilseed, to produce the particular
effect oil.” 64
It might be helpful to locate the discussion somewhat, at
this stage, both in terms of Indian and Western philosophy. It
should be clarified, in terms of Western philosophy, that the
discussion is proceeding by way of material cause in terms of
Aristotle’s four-fold formulation of material, efficient, formal
and final causes. From this perspective, for instance, “the
activity of the efficient cause, the oilman, the potter or the
Advaita Vedanta: /I Rational Approach
55
goldsmith [or the silversmith in the case of the silver bracelet]
cannot produce any new substance, it only manifests the
form of the substance concealed in its previous state.” 65
In terms of Indian philosophy, the context is provided by
the doctrines of Asatkaryavada and Satkarayavada. According
to the former view the effect is something “new” and doesn’t
pre-exist in th
e material cause. According to the lattei the
effect pre-exists in the material cause. It should be obvious
from the trend of the arguments made earlier that Advaita
Vedanta inclines towards the second view.
Hindu thinking further diverges in relation to the latter
view on the point as to whether such effect represents an actual
or apparent transformation of the material cause. According
to the Sahkhya school, the effect represents an actual
transformation of the material cause, as when a piece of silver
is transformed into bracelet of silver, which it was not before.
The Advaitin joins issue with the Sahkhya school here
because to claim that silver has been changed into a “new”
form in the process implies that what was not has come into
being—for that is what “new” must mean here; or the claim
that silver has been transformed into what it was not earlier.
From this point of view it can be said that according to Advaita,
Sahkhya fails to realize the full significance of Satkaryavada:
For, it holds that though the effect exists previously
in its material cause, there is real change (parinama)
of the material into the effect, since the material
assumes a new form. Now this view amounts to the
confession that this form, which did not exist
previously, comes into existence. The doctrine of
Satkarya-vada, that nothing, which didn’t exist
previously, can come into existence, thus breaks
down. If the grounds on which that doctrine stands
are sound, then we must be prepared to accept all
that logically follows from it, and cannot hold any
view which implies any violation of this doctrine,
rationally established. 66
56
Advaita Vedanta
Some have even suggested that the Advaita doctrine
should, by contrast, be called Satkaranavada, because
according to the Advaita doctrine that effects can never
overreach or outreach the cause.
At stake here is the question : What is the logical, ‘as
distinguished from the perceptual’, status of change of form
? Or, m other words, dues change of form amount to change
of reality ? The reality, which underlies all changes of forms,
is the substance itself. Change of form doesn’t amount to
change of substance and if the substance remains the same
through the various forms it assumes, can the changes be
said to be real ? As there is no real change in this sense, can
change be said to be real ? Thus :
We have no reason, therefore, to interpret the
perception of a change in form as a change of
reality. On the contrary, it is found that in spite of
changes in form a substance is recognized by us as
the identical entity. Devadatta, sitting, standing or
lying is recognized as the identical person. How can
this be, if change in form implied change in
reality? 67
In this analysis the rational status of anything characterized
by a quality, or any form characterized by change, is
challenged. To go back to the silver bracelet. Thus the silver
bracelet possesses this quality of having curved. Let us now
pose the question: what is the relationship of the curve of the
bracelet to the bracelet ? The curve does not consist of
anything other than the bracelet itself, i.e.; it characterizes
nothing else than the bracelet. Nor is the curve separable
from it materially. Nor could the curve have come into being
if it had not existed in the bracelet of silver as a potential.
Thus the quality of the curvature of the silver bracelet has no
existence apart from the silver bracelet.
Similarly, the silver bracelet has no existence apart from
silver, as established earlier.
Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach
57
At the heart of the issue lies the question of the
relationship of the quality to object (curvature to bracelet )
or of object to substance ( silver bracelet to silver ). If the
identity of effect to cause is rejected, although argued for
by Advaita, then one is left with the following logical options:
1 ) that the effect is distinct from the cause; or that 2) the
effect constitutes an identity-cum-difference with the cause.
Let us now examine these two options.
We begin by assuming that the effect is distinct from the
cause. This means that there is one thing called cause and
another called effect and the two are distinct. If the two are
distinct, but the cause produces the effect, then they must be
linked in some way; that is to say, there must be a third entity,
which links these two entities. But if such be the case then
We would fail to explain the relation between the
quality and its substance. For, two distinct realities
cannot be conceived to be related without the help
of a third entity to connect them. Now, as soon as
we think of this third entity (which must be distinct
from the two terms it attempts to relate) we have to
think of a fourth relating entity, and also a fifth,
which would relate the third with each of the first
two terms respectively. Similarly, these fourth and
fifth entities would require other similar media for
relating them to the terms they themselves want to
relate, and so on. There would then be an infinite
regress (anavastha). We can thus never come to the
end of our supposition and there will never be a
complete explanation of the relation between the
quality and its substance. In other words, the
supposition of any distinction in reality between any
quality and its substance would be logically
indefensible. So a form cannot be treated as a
distinct reality, and no change in form can be
logically accepted as a real change, unless there is
change in substance. 68
58
Advaita Vedanta
Entity A
Entity B
Entity C
Entity D
(Connecting A and C)
Entity E
(Connecting A to D)
Entity F
(Connecting A and E)
But perhaps treating them as two distinct entities involves
ontological violence and the relationship is more properly
conceived of as identity-in-difference. Thus both silver and
silver-bracelet are after all identical as silver, but the silver-
bracelet is also different in also being a bracelet. Advaitins
claim that this is no more logically helpful in solving the issue
of the relationship between silver-bracelet and silver, than
treating the two as distinct, although on the face of it seems
to resolve the problem. If two objects are related by identity-
cum-difference then it must mean that in some respect they
are identical and in some respect different. However
“neither of them can as such be both identical with and
different from the other. It would mean that M is both N
and not-N and that N is similarly both M and not-M, which is
a violation of the law of contradiction. When two things are
distinct in fact, they cannot be the same.” 69 In other words
they do not constitute identity-in-difference directly. But as
M. Hiriyanna points out further:
Thus we may say that M and N possess one or more
common feature which may be represented by a
and, at the same time exhibit differences
represented by x and y respectively. According to
this explanation, what is identical is quite distinct
Advaila Vedanta: A Rational Approach
59
from what is different; yet the entities, viz. M and
N, by virtue of such features, it may be said, are
identical with and, at the same thing different from
each other. Such an explanation may seem to solve
the difficulty, but the solution is only apparent, for
it merely shifts the difficulty to another set of things.
It assumes that M and N are characterized by a x
and a y respectively, and the assumption leaves us
where we were, for we cannot satisfactorily explain
the relation between a thing and its so-called
characteristics. Now the relation between M and a
x, to take only one of the entities, cannot be identity,
for then the distinction between a and x would
vanish, both being identical with the same M; and
with it also the relation of idendty-in-difference
between M and N. Nor can a and x be different
from M, for then their character, whatever it may
be, will cease to affect M, and therefore also its
relation to N. So we are driven to think of identity-
in-difference as the only possible relation between
these. That is, in explaining the relation in question
between M and N, we presuppose the same relation
within each of them; and pursuing the inquiry
further will only lead to an infinite process. 70
To illustrate: Let us propose that the color of silver is the
common property (a) shared by the silver bracelet and silver
but the differences between them consist of (x) in the form
of undetermined form of silver as a mere lump and (y) in the
form of the special shape of the bracelet.
Now, in the case of silver (M), what is the relationship of
silver to (a) its color and (x) its indeterminate shape? The
difference between (a) color and (x) indeterminate shape
would vanish, if both are identical with the same M (silver).
Nor can (a) and (x) be different from M, for then they would
have no connection with M. Hence this relationship too would
have to be described as identity-cum-difference.
60
Advaita Vedanta
Thus:
M N
Silver Silver-bracelet
Identity-cum-difference
Color Indeterminate Color Bracelet
(a) Shape (x) (a) Shape (y)
Identity-cum-difference Identity-cum-difference
The characterization (of identity-cum-difference) between
M and N merely shifts within them, and so down the pike.
Thus, no logically satisfactory resolution in terms of other
logical options seems possible. Nevertheless, the change is
perceived, although it is rationally unexplained and,
therefore, logically unacceptable. Hence the need to
characterize it as appearance. The point may be elaborated
as follows:
...we have seen that no causation involves any
change in substance. Hence causation does not
imply any real change. Moreover, as every change
is a process of causation; there cannot be any
change in reality. This amounts to the position that
though we perceive changes we cannot rationally
accept them as real. We have therefore to
understand them in the same way as we do, when
we perceive an illusory object. We do perceive a
rainbow, a blue sky, movement of the sun and many
other things which we cannot believe as real
because reasoning proves them to be unreal. Such
a perceived but unreal phenomenon is called an
appearance and distinguished from reality. On the
same ground we must call change also an
appearance and distinguish it from reality. We can
thus reach, on purely logical grounds supported
by common observation, the theory of vivarta or
apparent change, as a rational doctrine required
for the explanation of the world. 71
Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach
61
One might be tempted to argue here in rebuttal, in terms
of practical rather than pure reason, that the silver-bracelet
is surely different from plain silver in that it can be worn on
the wrist in a way one cannot wear plain silver. The Advaitin
would counter argue that the fact that the bracelet is
serviceable doesn’t affect the truth of the proposition, no
more than the apparent movement of the sun across the sky
can be accepted as real just because it is helpful in organizing
our daily activities. It is of service too but that doesn’t make
it true.
II
So we started with the examination of the relationship of
the curve of the silver bracelet to the silver bracelet,
preceded to an examination of the relationship of silver-
bracelet to silver and found that the new relationship
reincarnates the old problem. One might, however, at this
point raise the following objection—what you say seems to
hold for the objects in the universe, but does this also hold
for the universe itself treated as an object, as it were. In
other words, does what holds for the parts also hold for the
whole?
Even this objection can be logically nuanced as follows:
why speak of the universe, you speak of forms and substance
but does what you say of forms apply to the substance also?
Both of these issues may now be dealt with in this section.
One must begin by recognizing that silver was chosen as a
substance because, in relation to it, bracelets and other
ornaments could be viewed as its modifications (vikara) into
form.
From a broader perspective, however, even silver is subject
to modification (vikara). That is, it too is the form of some
other substance X. Just as the bracelet arose out of silver, was
in silver in some way before it so arose and dissolved into it
again, so also silver itself is apparently the form of some
substance X in which it pre-exists, from which it arises as silver
and into which it disappears. Or to ring a metaphorical change,
and talk of a pot of clay rather than a bracelet of silver:
62
Advaita Vedanta
The qualities of a pot have no reality apart from
the pot, and also that the pot itself has no reality
apart from its cause, the clay, which is the real
substance of which the pot is only one form of
manifestation. But as clay itself is liable to
modification and may cease to be clay, even it
cannot be called a real substance; it is only a form
of manifestation, though more abiding than a pot,
of some other substance which persists through all
the modifications of clay, and is also present in what
clay itself comes from and in what it is changed into,
after its destruction. If all so-called substances are
thus liable to modification (vikara), then the
substance underlying all objects of the world would
be that which persists through all forms of objects.
Existence is revealed in the perception of every
object, whatever be its nature. It can, therefore, be
called the substance, the material cause, or the
underlying reality behind the world of objects. 72
And now when we move to the level of the universe we do
see a shift and a change in quantity does lead to change in
quality in a quirky Marxian manner:
If all so-called substances are liable to modification
vikara then the substance underlying all the objects
of the world would be that which persists through
all forms of objects. And we observe that existence
(not in any specific form but existence pure and
simple) is what is common to all forms of objects.
Existence is revealed in the perception of every
object, whatever be its nature. It can, therefore,
be called the substance, the material cause of the
underlying reality behind the world of objects.”
The qualitative change in the general conclusion should
not go unnoticed. The attempt to analyze the nature of
specific objects in the universe has led to the identification
Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach
63
of non-specific existence as the material cause. The material
cause has turned out to be immaterial existence! But this
should not be considered unduly abstract. It is the neutral
or unengaged gear in the car, which allows all specific gears
to be engaged.
Ill
The next logical question to arise in the context is the
following: this logical analysis pertains to the objective world.
Does it also apply to the subjective world of the individual?
Does Advaita Vedanta offer a different rational analysis for
the internal world of being as opposed to the external?
This conclusion, that the material cause of the universe is
immaterial existence, is also applied to the internal states in
Advaita Vedanta, for these states also exist.
...when we examine the changing states within our
minds what we also find there is that every state,
every idea, whatever its object, exists. Even an
illusory idea, which lacks an external object, exists
as an idea ( avagati). A state of deep dreamless sleep
or of swoon also exists, although no objective
consciousness is present there. Existence is thus
found to be the one undeniable reality persisting
through all states, internal and external. It can,
therefore, be accepted as the substance, and
material cause of which all determinate objects and
mental states are the diverse manifestations.
We find then that pure existence which is the
common cause of the entire world is itself formless,
though appearing in various forms; partless, though
divisible in different forms; it is infinite though it
appears in all finite forms. Sankara thus reaches
the conception of an infinite, indeterminate
nirvisesa existence as the essence or material cause
of the world. He calls this Absolute or Brahman. 74
64
Advaita Vedanta
IV
This is how the rational investigation of everyday reality by
Advaita leads it to question and then reconfigure the
conceptual framework with which we operate in everyday life.
In the course of ordinary living, we draw a sharp distinction
between our experience of the external universe and our
own inner life. Advaita Vedanta, however, pools our
experiences of the external world and the internal world as
data to be explained in common and is thus counter-intuitive
in terms of our quotidian philosophical framework.
It questions this framework at an even deeper level, when
it raises the question of the relationship of consciousness to
existence. In terms of our quotidian or even commonsensical
philosophy of life, we associate “existence” with our experience
of the external world, and “consciousness” with our experience
of the internal world. Thus for us external objects “exist” and
we are “conscious” of our internal states.
In this context Advaitic rationality raises the question: What
is the criterion of consciousness? Note the Advaitin answer to
the parallel question: What is the criterion of existence? is
the following: that which is perceived. The totally non-existent
—the barren woman’s son and the horns of a hare—cannot
be perceived. Let a similar question now be posed in relation
to consciousness.
But what is the criterion of consciousness? A mental
state is conscious, because its existence is self-
revealing. But when we perceive the external world
its existence also reveals itself. The power of
appearing bhati is common to both internal and
external forms of existence; and it can, therefore,
be argued that existence which is common to the
internal and external world must posses the power
of revealing itself. Therefore, it is more reasonable
to hold that Absolute existence is of the nature of
self-revealing consciousness. In fact, a little
reflection shows that self-revelation may even be
Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach
65
taken as the differential that distinguishes
existence from non-existence. What is non¬
existent (e.g. the son of a barren woman) cannot
even appear or reveal itself for a moment . 75
The gulf we tend to sense between existence and
consciousness is bridged in Advaita Vedanta by arguing that
when we speak of the existence of the silver-bracelet it boils
down to the consciousness of the existence of the silver-
bracelet and that we would not be able to speak of the
existence of silver apart from the consciousness of its existence.
In terms of another metaphor:
Wherever there is appearance of existence there
is awareness invariably present. Even an external
object, say clay, which appears to us is presented by
an awareness of clay (mrt-buddhi). When we
perceive clay becoming a pot, our clay-consciousness
turns into pot-consciousness (ghata buddhi). An
imaginary object is just the idea of the object, and
so also is an illusory object. So we find that awareness
pervades all forms of existence known to us.
By a series of arguments like these Sankara reaches
logically what he accepts on the authority of the
revealed texts, namely that the world originates
from Brahman, which is Absolute Existence and
Consciousness and that Brahman has the power of
manifesting itself in diverse apparent form, without
really undergoing any modification . 76
V
The tenor of our analysis of the world, however, has so far
taken the smooth and easy route. We started out with the
curve of the silver-bracelet, and moved through on to silver
and to that substance of which the silver might only be one
form, and ended up by identifying general existence as the
material cause of the universe.
66
Advaila Vedanta
But the course of the universe is not that smooth. For one
thing we find one experience of existence contradicted by
another. What we thought was a snake turns out to be a rope.
Similarly, the universe doesn’t consist of just silver-bracelets
or silver. It contains many other objects. In other words, our
analysis of the universe needs to be made more complex by
incorporating two new features of our experience into it: (1)
the contradictability of objects and 2) the immense variety of
objects. The question we must now answer is : how do these
twin considerations affect the logic of the arguments advanced
so far ?
We argued earlier from form to substance in a seamless
way—but forms can contradict or replace one another over
time and they vary in space. What bearing then do these factors
have on the logical outcome of our discussion?
When experiences contradict one another, then the
contradicting form takes precedence over or is considered
more real than the contradicted form. Thus normal waking
state is considered more real than dream state and within
waking state, as when a piece of shell is experienced as silver,
the contradicting experience (here shell) is considered more
real than the contradicted experience (here silver).
But in spite of such contradictions among the
different forms, existence or (consciousness) as
such remains uncontradicted. When we disbelieve
an illusory serpent we only deny that the existence
there is of a form of a serpent, but we do not deny
that there is some existence. Again, even when we
deny a dream object, we don’t deny that the
experience or idea existed. And when we think of a
time or place where nothing exists, we are thinking
of the existence of at least that time or place. So
existence, in some form or another, is as wide as
thought and we cannot conceive of the absence
or denial of existence. This universal, pure
existence (or consciousness ) is thus the only thing
Aavaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach
67
whose contradiction is unthinkable. Sankara calls
it, therefore, supreme reality (Paramarthika satta.)
He thus logically arrives also at his conception of
reality as that which persists uncontradicted through
all forms of existence in all place and times. 77
Rut on what logical basis, we might wish .to ask, was the
contradicting experience considered superior to the
contradicted, experience? A little reflection leads to the
conclusion that the contradicting experience is considered
more real than the contradicted experience, because it
endures longer than the contradicted experience. Thus
waking state outlasts the dreaming state, and the experience
of the rope lasts longer than that of the serpent.
This provides a clue to the Advaitic concept of reality
namely, that that which persists is real. One is led in this
direction by an examination of both the original argument
and the complications introduced into it in this section. Thus,
to revert to the original argument, the silver in a sense is more
real since the bracelet was a form of it and the substance X, of
which silver might be the form, is more real than silver because
each respectively endures longer, and existence itself—pure
indeterminate existence—was identified as the material cause
of the universe because it was the most enduring of all.
This thrust is confirmed when one takes the fact that forms
might contradict one another into account—as when the
experience of a snake is contradicted by it turning out to a
rope, or dream experience by waking experience. Existence
as such persists through them also.
As for the diversity of objects exhibited by the universe, it
needs to be noted that they are all undergoing modification,
although at different rates. Even more important than the
difference in the rate at which they are undergoing
modification is the fact that they are all undergoing
modification. Now
This theoretical possibility of change in perception,
and of consequent contradiction, then makes the
68
Advaita Vedanta
status of every particular object precarious, in
respect of its reality. We can never be absolutely
certain that what appears now as pot will not appear
otherwise later. We see, therefore, how different
particular forms of existence, like pot and cloth,
weaken and undermine each other’s claim to
indubitable reality. If, however, these claimed only
pure existence, and not existence of particular
forms, their claims would not have been mutually
exclusive. The rival claims of particulars as
particular existents thus prevent them from having
the position of indubitable reality such as pure
existence enjoys. 78
VI
The upshot of such a rational analysis of the objective universe
along Advaitic lines leads one to the following conclusion:
On such rational grounds Sankara grades and
classifies common experience. As we saw, he first
of all, distinguishes all objects of possible and actual
experience from utter unreality, like the child of
the barren mother. The former again are classed
under there heads : 1) those that only appear
momentarily in illusions and dreams, but are
contradicted by waking experience, 2) those that
appear in normal waking experience—the
particular and changing objects, which form the
basis of our ordinary life and practice, but which
are still not acceptable to reason as completely real
(because they exhibit contradiction or are open to
future contradiction), and 3) pure existence which
reveals itself through all experience, and is neither
contradicted nor contradictable. 79
How is such a world, the world not only of common
experience, but one in which common experience is rationally
described?
Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach
69
The world is thus not a homogeneous conception,
and if, in spite of this, one insists on being told
what such a world, as a whole is, the fairest reply
can only be, what Sankara gives, namely that is
indescribable ( anirvacaniya ) either as real or as
unreal. But if the word world is confined only to
the second aspect, it would be again fair to say,
that the world is real only for practical purpose,
more real than the first and less real than the third
kind of existence. But if the world is taken in the
third sense, Sankara would emphatically assert that
the world is eternally real. As he puts it : “As the
cause, Brahman, doesn’t lack existence at any time,
past, present or future, so does the world not lack
existence in any of the three periods of time.”
Again, “ All particular modes of existence with
different names and forms as real as existence,
but unreal as particulars.” st>
VII
So much of the objective world—what now of the individual
subject?
The rational analysis of the individual subject in Advaita
seems to follow three routes: 1) an analysis of the subject’s
experience of itself; 2) an analysis of the subject’s experience
of the states in which it exists in the world and 3) and analysis
of the subject in the light of its relation to the external world.
The subject’s experience of itself is usually described
through the use of the personal pronoun “I”. One way in which
Advaita arrives at its concept of the individual is through a
rational analysis of this linguistic phenomenon.
The word “I” can be employed in various ways and if the
common denominator underlying these various uses could
be identified, then one might have here the key by turning
which the secrets of the self may be unlocked. Some of such
uses of the “I” may be listed as follows:
70
Advaita Vedanta
1. I am tall
2. I see you
3. I walk home
4. I think of it
’5. I feel he is wrong
6. I will do it
7. I know, I just know
The first use refers to the body. So the “I” possesses a body.
Thus people say: ‘I am tali’, ‘I am short’, ‘I am fat;, T am
thin’ and so on.
The second use refers to an organ of perception—the eye.
One also says: I hear, I touch, I taste, and I smell. Thus the
organs of perception located in the body and their function
are some of the things the “I” identifies with. It does the same
when it says: I balance myself on a beam.
The third use refers to an organ of action, that of
locomotion. One also says: I talk, I grasp, I empty my bladder,
and I have sex. Thus the organs of ac tion located in the body
and their function are some of the other things the “I”
identifies with.
The fourth, fifth, and sixth uses point to the psyche in its
three dimensions of thinking, feeling and willing. The “I”
identifies itself with each of these.
The seventh use points to the sense of intuition possessed
by us—a sense of knowing somewhat different from our usual
way of knowing things. The I identifies with it too.
Now what persists through all these states as a common
denominator? One might be tempted to say the body, but
the body could not identify with any of the descriptions offered
earlier, were it not conscious. Neither would the mind be able
to identify with any were it not conscious. In fact, the
identification of the / with any of the descriptions offered
earlier presuppose consciousness. Thus
Consciousness is, therefore, the essence of the self
in whichever form it may appear. But it is not
consciousness of any particular form, but simple
Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach
71
consciousness common to all its forms. Such
consciousness is also pure existence since existence
persists throughout all forms of consciousness. The
different particular and changing forms of
consciousness can be shown, from their
contradictory natures, to be mere appearance, in
the same way as the different forms of existence
were shown to be so before. 81
There arc ostensibly moments, however, when
consciousness is not present, as when we swoon or are asleep.
At these moments, however, our sense of / also disappears.
Thus the correlation between / and /-consciousness in terms
of our conscious self is obvious. But what when we are
dreaming? We are not conscious of our body when we are
dreaming, although consciousness in some form is present.
In deep sleep it seems to be absent at first sight.
This brings us to the second approach adopted in Advaita
for identifying the nature of the self. All of us assert that I am
awake, I dreamt, and I slept. Thus the / clearly persists
through these three states of waking, dreaming and deep
sleep. But does consciousness persist through these three
states? According to Advaita an analysis of these three states
reveals that consciousness does persist through them.
Moreover, as a bonus, this analysis also enables us to identify
the nature of this consciousness more clearly, if we argue as
follows:
The essence of the self must remain in all these or
the self would cease to be. But what do we find
common to all these states ? In the first state there
is consciousness of external objects; in the second
also there is consciousness, but of internal objects
present only to the dreamer. In the third state no
objects appear, but here is no cessation of
consciousness, for otherwise the subsequent
memory of that state , as one of peace and freedom
from worries, would not be possible. The persistent
72
Advaita Vedanta
factor then is consciousness, but not necessarily of
any object. This shows again that the essence of
self is pure consciousness without necessary
relation to objects. 82
The identification of objectless consciousness through the
rational analysis of deep sleep is very important from the point
of view of Advaita. Normally, we always associate consciousness
with an object but the phenomenon of deep sleep reveals
that although consciousness need not always be associated
with an object, it must always be associated with the subject.
The third approach to the individual subject identified in
Advaita enables one to say more about the nature of pure
consciousness. In this approach that fact that the individual
subject stands face-to-face with a world of objects is subjected
to radical rational scrutiny. The first result of such an
investigation is the reconfiguration of the concept of subject
and object as commonly understood in philosophy as follows:
The cognitive situation is usually taken to involve a
subject and object. The Advaitin substitutes for them
drk and drsya, the former meaning the self or what
reveals and the latter, what is revealed. The reason
for this substitution is that the other division is not
logically quite satisfactory. The subject includes not
only drk but also drsya. It is really a complex of the
self and the not self. This is clear from statements
like I know myself-,, where myself refers to some
thought or feeling or, as Hume said, ‘some
particular perception or other, of heat or cold, light
or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure.’ These
perceptions, being observable, are drsya and
necessarily point to some center of consciousness
beyond them. 85
The drk or the individual subject, as the center of pure
consciousness, upon analysis, displays certain striking
properties.
Advaila Vedanta: /I Rational Approach
73
It is impossible to think of the absence of drk —as
having ceased to be or as not having yet come to
be, for that thought itself would imply the presence
of drk. Hence drk, in some sense, should be regarded
as having neither beginning nor end, and therefore
as eternal or timeless.
...We have seen that ark cannot have internal parts.
It cannot be externally related to other drks, for a
similar reason, viz., that it is not possible to think of
any dividing line between them. The only way in
which we can distinguish between one drk and
another is by reference to their content or the
objects they reveal. In themselves, they are
indistinguishable. That is, drk is one or, more strictly,
not many. 84
In this way the pure subject is not only external and one, it
can also be considered all-comprehensive, if the drsya is
considered dependent on the drk and therefore accounted
for by drk, for then drk becomes “all-comprehensive, in the
sense that there is nothing outside it”, directly or indirectly.
VIII
The concept of contradiction plays a special role in logical
analysis. We would do well, therefore, to analyze its role in
Advaitic rationality.
In terms of pragmatic reason, Advaitic thinking would
distinguish between contradiction between one thought and
another, and between thought and practice. One could
think of a situation, for instance, in which an individual is
constantly changing his pattern of thought, so that what one
says today may contradict what one said fifteen days ago.
However, one might yet, in both these phases, be consistent
in terms of thought and practice. Suppose, for instance, that
fifteen days ago a person believed in violence and also behaved
violently. Now, fifteen days later, the same person comes to
74
Advaita Vedanta
believe in non-violence and also behaves non-violently. Then
over this fifteen-day period he would have exhibited
contradiction at the level of thought and also at the level of
practice, but not at the level of the relationship between
thought and practice. In terms of practical reason, as it were,
one could display a pattern of four possibilities. 1)
contradiction between thought and thought ; 2)
contradiction between practice and practice; 3) thought
contradicted by practice (when one thinks oneself to be
detached and may not be) and 4) practice contradicted by
thought (one may actually be modest and not think of
oneself as such, as part of being modest!) . Then there is
the case of th ejivanmukta, a case in which such contradictions
might be considered unthinkable. This is then how the
discussion of contradiction might well proceed in terms of
Advaitic ethics and soteriology.
In the realm of Advaitic epistemology and ontology,
however, the discussion of contradiction must be set on a
different course. The referents of contradiction here are
thought and experience. In terms of these referents one can
again came up with a four-fold pattern; 1) the contradiction
of one experience by another; 2) the contradiction of one
thought by another; 3) the contradiction of thought by
experience and 4) the contradiction of experience by thought.
An example of the contradiction of one experience by
another is provided by the experience of what was thought to
be snake turning out to be a rope. The experience of the
rope contradicts the experience of the snake. Similarly, the
experience of waking contradicts the experience of sleep.
Note, however, that while in the first case the contradicting
experience of the rope falsified the contradicted
experience; this cannot be said of the contradiction involved
in the waking and sleeping states. One can either accept
both on their face value, or claim that each falsifies the other.
This is possible because they belong to two different kinds
of consciousness, unlike the case of the rope-snake example.
Advaita Vedanta: A Rational Approach
75
An example of the contradiction of one thought by
another is provided when it is argued that the effect and
(material) cause may be two distinct entities. This is
contradicted by the thought that the two distinct entities
require a third entity to relate them, but then this third
entity will have to be related by a fourth and fifth entity to
the first and so forth, leading to infinite regress.
The example of the contradiction of thought by experience
will be provided by the case in which one might think it
unthinkable that one could experience a state in which one
is neither aware of oneself nor of the world. Yet the experience
of dreamless sleep provides precisely an example of such a
state, and so might samadhi.
The example of the contradiction of experience by thought
is provided by the apparent movement of the sun across the
sky. It is given by experience but contradicted by astronomical
knowledge.
For the rational presentation of Advaitic ontology, however,
this grid has to be ratched up a notch to another level: to the
contradiction between the non-contradictable and the
contradictable.
It was mentioned earlier how “universal, pure existence
(or consciousness) is the only thing whose contradiction is
unthinkable. Sankara calls it, therefore, Supreme reality
(Paramarthika Satta). He thus logically arrives also at this
conception of reality as that which persists uncontradicted
through all forms of existence in all places and times.” 22 As
distinguished from such existence in general, existence in
the particular suffers from a liability. “About any definite or
particular form of existence, which may appear in our
experience, we can never be certain that it may not be
supplanted by a contradictory experience arising in future.
So the theoretical or logical possibility of it being contradicted
is always there.” 86
The distinction between the contradiction of snake by
rope; and of sleep by waking become relevant when it is
Advaita Vedanta
claimed that rationally speaking, even two objects like pot
ghata and cloth pata falsify each other.
Rope and snake experienced in the same waking state as
distinct objects do not falsify each other; when the same object
which was perceived as a snake turns out to be a rope, one
(snake) is falsified by the other (rope); waking and dreaming
may be credibly said to falsify' each other but they belong to
two different orders of experience. It is true that both pot
and cloth may be falsified, as particulars, in relation to
universal existence but they can be said to mutually falsify
each other only from the perspective of universal existence,
as the uncontadictable reality in the light of which not only
are both contradicted but also mutually so, even though they
are at the same ontological level. In other works, change
involves the possibility of contradiction, possible change
therefore involves the possibility of contradiction but note
that experientially the pot can never change into cloth because
of acceptance of satkaryavada. From the point of view of
satkaryavada both effects are false and doubly so but only
mutually in relation to the highest level.
The paradox is that although logically the pot and cloth
falsify each other on account of changeability, experientially
they cannot change into each other. Logic from the highest
level delimits experience of particulars, while logic at the same
level limits experience to particulars. The rope can apparently
turn into a snake but can the pot turn into cloth? No, but
what they do is “weaken and undermine each other’s claim
to indubitable reality” by reinforcing each other’s
particularity.
PART III
Advaita Vedanta:
An Experiential Approach
The experiential approach to the study of Advaita Vedanta
provides a third possible way of approaching the subject. An
initial validation for such an approach is provided by an
attempt to answer the following question : Why should not a
rational approach suffice either by itself, or in combination
with the scriptural approach, to provide an introduction to
Advaita Vedanta? Of course from a certain point of view it
can. In fact, either the scriptural or the rational could suffice
by itself for that matter. However, a more comprehensive
perspective might lead one to conclude otherwise. Our
experience of life reveals that life is characterized by three
states of consciousness—waking, dreaming and deep sleep.
A philosophy of life must take all three into account and
account for all three. Rationality, however, is a characteristic
of human mind only during the waking state, although
mental activity in some form is common to both the waking
state and the dreaming state. In the state of deep sleep,
even mental activity, or at least conscious mental activity,
also ceases. Thus rationality only characterizes a part of life;
can it be used to account for the whole of life? The same
argument can be given another form in terms of conscious
mental activity, even during the waking state. Mental activity,
in the waking state, also includes aesthetic and emotional
experience. Thus rationality is only one, if privileged, aspect
of this manifold mental activity. We give premium to
rationality because we associate it with the philosophical
enterprise in which we are engaged. Thus, its role gives it a
certain status in view of the nature of the task we are engaged
in but it is useful to be reminded of the fact that there is
80
Advaita Vedanta
more to life than logic. What an electrifying insight this must
have been before it became a cliche.
How then might Advaita Vedanta be presented, if it took
all the states of existence and not just one (of which the
experience of rationality is so striking a feature) into account?
II
One important feature of the experiential exposition of
Advaita Vedanta is to question the finality of the distinction
between waking and dreaming and deep sleep. In our
everyday approach to life, if we were asked to pair out any
two of them and separate the one left out as an indication
in our judgement of their relative importance, then nine
times out of ten we will be inclined to pair dreaming and
deep sleep as one unit, and separate the waking state as the
one in which we are really alive. The waking state lies at the
center of our life. After all, we live from day-to-day, not night-
to-night. The night is spent in repose and in experiencing
the states of dreaming and deep sleep.
The Advaita approach to the matter, however, is more
inclined to pair the states of waking and dreaming, and
prefers to separate deep sleep from them for reasons which
will now be explained. Advaita Vedanta is inclined to pair
the waking and dreaming states together, notwithstanding
their differences, because both of them are equally
characterized by mental activity. According to the Advaitic
view our concepts of space, time and causality differ in the
waking and dreaming states, in contrast to the common view
that these concepts are present in the waking state and absent
in the dreaming state. According to Advaitins the only real
difference between the two is duration—waking is a longer
stretch of dreaming and that is why in the waking state we
can recall we slept but not vice versa.
Many thinkers—both Eastern and Western—have felt that
drawing a firm distinction between waking and dreaming
presents difficulties. Among Western thinkers Descartes and
Pascal may be specially mentioned. Descartes wrote:
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
81
When I consider the matter carefully, I do not find
a single characteristic by means of which I can
certainly determine whether I am awake or
whether I am dreaming. The vision of a dream
and the experience of my waking state are so much
alike that I am completely puzzled and I don’t
reallv know if I am not dreaming at this moment. 87
And Pascal said :
If a dream comes to us every night we should be as
much occupied with it as by the thing we see every
day, and if an artisan were certain that he would
dream every night for twelve hours that he was a
king, then he would be just as happy who dreams
every night for twelve hours that he is an artisan. 88
In the East, the Indian king Janaka and the Chinese
philosopher Chuang Tzu were baffled, it seems, by similar
experiences. There was once a famous Indian king called
Janaka. “King Janaka had a dream that he was a beggar. On
his waking up he asked his guru ‘Am I a king dreaming of
being a beggar or a beggar dreaming of being a king?” 89
Chuang Tzu (c. 369-286 B.C ), second in importance only
to Lao Tzu as a representative of Taoism, raises for “epistemo¬
logy... the ultimately unanswerable question”: 90
Once upon a time, Chuang Chou [ i.e. Chuang
Tzu] dreamed that he was a butterfly, a butterfly
fluttering about, enjoying it. It did not know that
it was Chuang Chou again. But he didn’t know
whether he was Chuang Chou who had dreamed
that he was a butterfly, or whether he was a
butterfly dreaming that he was Chuang Chou.
Between Chuang Chou and the butterfly there
must he some distinction. This is what is called
the transformation of things. 91
In a less celebrated and more elaborate passage Chuang
Tzu further considers the plausibility of the dream-like nature
of life.
82
Advaila Vedanta
Those who dream of a merry drinking party may
the next morning wail and weep. Those who
dream of wailing and weeping may in the morning
go off gaily to hunt. While they dream they do not
know that they are dreaming. In their dream, they
may even try to interpret their dream. Only when
they have awakened do they begin to know that
they have dreamed. By and by comes a great
awakening, and then we shall know that it has all
been a great dream. Yet all the while the fools
think that they are awake; this they are sure of.
With minute nicety, they discriminate between
princes and grooms. How stupid! Confucius and
you are both in a dream. And when I say that you
are in a dream, this is also a dream. This way of
talking may be called paradoxical. If after ten
thousand generations we could once meet a great
sage who knew how to explain the paradox, it
would be as though we met him after only one
morning or one evening. 92
A similar tendency to treat the waking state as analogous
to dreaming also appears in Buddhist thought, as the
following passage indicates:
‘The senses are as though illusions and their objects
as dreams. For instance a sleeping man might
dream that he had made love to a beautiful
country girl, and he might remember her when
he awoke. WTiat do you think ...does the beautiful
girl he dreamed of really exist?”
“No, Lord.”
“And would the man be wise to remember the
girl of his dreams, or to believe that he had really
made love to her ?”
“No, Lord, because she doesn’t really exist at all,
how could he have made love to her—though of
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
83
course he might think he did under the influence
of weakness or fatigue.”
“In just the same way a foolish and ignorant man
of the world sees pleasant forms and believes in
their existence. Hence he is pleased, and so he
feels passion and acts accordingly 91 ’
Mystics even more than philosophers are inclined to
disregard the distinction, at some level, between waking and
dreaming, as in the following story narrated by Sri Ramakrsna
Paramhamsa (1836-1886):
A son was born to a king. He was the only child
and was therefore the apple of the eye of both the
king and queen. The prince became a favorite with
all and as he grew older he was taught all the arts
and the sciences. One day, all of a sudden, the
prince fell ill. The malady went on getting worse
and even the best physician of the kingdom found
that all treatments were of no avail. Both the king
and the queen never left his side day and night
and the most competent physician and nurses
continuously attended him. The king was
exhausted by his constant vigil and one night he
could not resist falling asleep. He was awakened
by the sound of crying and weeping and learnt
that prince had passed away while he was asleep.
The king sat as if he was stupefied, without
speaking a single word. The queen asked him how
it was that on the passing away of the only a child
whom he loved so much there was not a single
drop of tears in his eyes. The king said, ‘Oh queen,
when I fell asleep I dreamt that I had become a
monarch of a large kingdom, much larger than
mine, and the father of seven worthy and ideal
princes, each of whom was well trained in the art
of administration. I handed over the charge of my
kingdom to them and thereafter I was spending
Advaita Vedanta
8'i
my days in peace and happiness with you. And now
this tragedy has taken place and I am unable to
make up my mind whether I should lament for
the child that has left us today or whether I should
mourn the loss of the seven sons and a vast
kingdom: I see no difference in the two bereave¬
ments and to me the world has become nothing
but a dream’. 94
Ramana Maharsi (d. 1950) asserts even more directly the
elusiveness of the distinction.
All that we see is a dream, whether we see it in the
dream state or waking state. On account of some
arbitrary standards about the duration of the
experience and so on, we call one experience a
dream and another waking experience. With
reference to reality both the experiences are
unreal. A man might have such an experience as
getting anugrah (grace) in his dream and the
effects and influence of it on his entire subsequent
life may be so profound and so abiding that one
cannot call it unreal, while calling real some trifling
incident in the waking life that just flits by is causal
and of no moment and is soon forgotten. Once I
had an experience, a vision or a dream whatever
you may call it. I and some others including
Chadwick who had a walk on the hill. Returning
we were walking along a huge street with great
buildings on either side. Showing the street and
the buildings, I asked Chadwick and others
whether anybody could say that what we were
seeing was dream and they all replied, What fool
■will say so ? and we walked along and entered the
hall and the vision or dream ceased, or [we] woke
up. What are we to call this? 95
A story told about the fifth Sikh Guru, Guru Arjun (1563-
1606) also makes a similar point. It is said that a king came
to visit him but
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
85
when he heard the musicians hymning the Guru’s
composition saying “O friend, the Writ thy God
has written out for thee can be obliterated not”,
he became anxious in the mind. On being
questioned, the Guru explained to the visitor that
the Writ that God writes is based upon one’s own
deeds. This gravely disappointed the King who
asked:—“If such be the case what is the need of
the Guru’s Grace or even of doing or being good,
if what has to happen must come to pass.” The
Guru replied:—-“Of this we would talk tomorrow.”
In the night, the King dreamt that he had become
a sweeper, clothed in tatters, dealing with filth all
the time and living the life of a miserable wretch.
He woke up, disturbed, in the morning and told
the Guru so. The Guru replied: “O devotee, you
slept as a King and in the dream became a poor
wretch. Your dream-state was as valid at the time
of your dreaming, as is your kingly state which you
really possess. Such is the nature of the Guru’s
Grace that no matter what your past or present,
you pass through, and are affected by it, only as
one passes through a dream, till one’s self awakens
to realise the essential kingly nature of one’s
soul”. 96
The state of deep sleep presents a radical contrast to the
states of waking and dreaming. The most striking features
of this contrast are two-fold: (1) that in deep sleep one loses
awareness of both oneself and of the world—outer as well as
inner. In the waking state, one is aware of the world of
external objects; in the dream state, one is aware of a world
of external objects also (which upon waking are discovered
to have been inner); but this crucial distinction disappears
in deep sleep. (2) Although one thus undergoes loss of
individuality in deep sleep yet upon waking one identifies
oneself with the same person who went to sleep. This
establishes that identity can survive loss of individuality. These
86
Advaila Vedanta
two facts—that in deep sleep one loses all sense of
individuality (as well as of the world) and further that despite
this lapse in individuality one doesn’t suffer loss of identity—
are considered such sensational features of deep sleep that
they—for the Advaitin—place deep sleep in a category by
itself, in comparison with waking and dreaming taken
together.
III
We revert now to the discussion of three states as separate
ones, after noticing that the analysis of deep sleep leads us
to the conclusion that there must be some entity which
survives discontinuity as sharp as the one involved in the state
of deep sleep* wherein even our sense of individuality is
lost. We are now led to a larger question: what constitutes
the underlying link even between the two different senses
of individualities experienced by us in the waking and
dreaming state respectively? Thus there is something which
underlies and sustains both the changing individualities in
waking and dreaming states, and the loss of individuality as
such in the state of deep sleep.
One, thus, arrives at the concept of the pure subject, in
the absence of which the three separate states couldn’t
possibly constitute the experience of a single person.
This is the experiential counterpart to the scriptural saksi
and the rational drk.
IV
Another way of approaching Advaita Vedanta experientially
is to view the hierarchy of the three states—listed in that
order as waking, dreaming and deep sleep—in two different
but complementary ways.
One can employ the analysis of the three states in order
to indicate both the nature of this pure subject, and how it
might be discovered. This dual thrust of the fresh analysis of
the three states is the clear implication, for instance, of some
of the remarks by Ramana Mahar?i. On the one hand, he
Advaila Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
87
admits that, in a sense, the state of deep sleep is closer to
the state of the pure subject as “the sleep state is free from
thoughts and their impression on the individual.” 97 Yet, at
the same time, he warns that one should not “therefore desire
to be always in sleep” because the “incentive to realize” the
self “can arise only in the waking state and efforts can only
be made when one is awake.” 98
This distinction between what is to be realized and how it
is to be realized is crucial to an understanding of the way
these three states of waking, dreaming and deep sleep are
approached in experiential Advaita. In effect, Ramana, and
earlier thinkers of Advaita, set up these three states in a
pattern of opposing hierarchies (somewhat like structure
and anti-structure). One may designate them as a theoretical
and the practical approaches to the issue. “The theoretical
approach shows us where we want to go, i.e., to the
interiorisation and the unification of consciousness, while
the practical approach indicates the means to achieve that
end, i.e., through Advaitic knowledge or yogic will.” 99
The theoretical approach may be elaborated first. It could
be argued that as one moves from the waking states
progressively to dreaming and deep sleep in the world of
ordinary experience, consciousness becomes increasingly
rarefied in the empirical subject. In the waking state, objects
are experienced in the external world. In the dreaming
state, objects become a product of the person’s interior
consciousness. In deep sleep, the distinction between the
subject and the object dissolves—even the internal division
within a dream between the experiencing subject and the
experienced object vanishes. All that is left is the sleeping
person. But as on waking up the person remembers having
slept, there must have been some conscious subject that
witnessed the unconsciousness of sleep. This pure subject
has to be realized. Its realization is said to put an end to all
unhappiness. Such is the Advaitin claim, that except for one
who experientially comes to “know” this pure subject, which
is known solely by means of itself “on account of its self-
88
Advaita Vedanta
luminosity”, according to Ramana “every man, from king to
peasant has a certain account of sorrow. Even in cases where
it seems absent it is only a time factor that makes you think
so —sooner or later it comes.’’ 1 " That is, until Self-realization
is achieved.
This analysis is suggestive in several ways. First, it suggests
that a radical discontinuity is involved in realizing the pure
subject, on account of its purity: its total absence of any
relationship with any object as in deep sleep, as distinguished
from its interiorised relationship as in dreams or an external
relation as in the waking state. Thus the knowledge of the
pure subject is categorically different from the knowledge
or absence of it which arises in a subject-object context, even
though this latter type of knowledge is itself qualitatively
different in waking, dreaming and deep sleep. Second, as
the realization of pure subjectivity entails the total elimination
of any form of object-contextuality, the realization of the
pure subject is a purely negative enterprise, in the sense
that all objects have to be eliminated at all levels—including
the possibility of a subject in a state of relation to no objects.
The subject must be just that. “When non-self disappears,
the self alone remains. To make room it is enough that
cramping is removed. Space is not brought in afresh. Say
more space is there even in cramping.” 101 This passage serves
to explain the comment that while in ordinary experience
the “true self-cannot be known, it doesn’t therefore remain
unrealized, for it is self-revealing. In fact it can never be
wholly suppressed.” 102 It is in this sense perhaps that one
must understand Ramana’s remark: “The feeling that I have
not realized is the obstruction to realization. In fact, it is
already realized...”” 103
The practical approach toward the realization of the self
and its relation to the three states of waking, dreaming and
deep sleep may now be examined. Any effort at realization
involves volition, so from a practical point of view the
hierarchy must now be reversed: no volition is possible in
deep sleep, perhaps more in dreaming but most in the
waking state.
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
89
The overall point may be graphically presented as follows:
Deep Sleep
Dreaming
Waking
The three states in terms
of unification of
consciousness
Waking
Dreaming
Deep Sleep
The three states in
terms of degrees of
volition in Consciousness
The special point to note is that one cannot just jump
from one pyramid to the other. It is somewhat like the
experience in mountaineering, when we may be standing
on a cliff atop one mountain and within close reach of
another mountain. It would be foolhardy, however, to just
try to jump from the top of a cliff on to the other mountain.
One must come down all the way and then climb to the top
of the other.
V
What, it might be asked, is the exact nature of the problem
towards solving which efforts must be directed in the waking
state?
The problem is best illustrated with the help of an
example. Let us take the case of a young lady who is in love
with her beau and goes out to buy a nice dress to please him.
She brings that dress home and places it on the table. She
then reclines on the chair and begins to speculate on the
romantic possibilities this addition to her wardrobe could
set in motion.
She imagines how she will wear the dress in the evening
and go out for a candle-lit dinner with her friend. She will
iron the dress with particular care and wear a perfume with
it. She imagines the possibility of spilling wine on it and
spoiling the dress (God forbid), and how she will preserve it
and after years of marriage still keep it though it may be
worn out by then, and how she will show it to her daughter
as the dress she wore on the evening her husband proposed
to her. While she is thus thinking, the phone rings and she
90
Advaila Vedanta
talks to her friend about this fabulous dress she bought in
the morning, describing in great detail the way it came to
be purchased.
Throughout this series of events the actual dress has simply
been lying on the table. So all her experiences don’t really
pertain to the dress but to the dress-thought. When she
thinks of wearing the dress it is really the dress-thought she
is concerned with—the dress as such is merely lying on the
table. The web of romantic associations she has woven are
also woven not around the dress itself, which just lies as an
item on the table, but around the dress-thought, in her mind.
When she talks with her friend on the phone she really talks
of the dress-thought, not the dress itself, which lies on the
table and is indifferent to the vicissitudes of fortune the
dress-thought is undergoing. The moment the lady stops
thinking or talking of the dress-thought—which is what is
really involved in the thinking or talking about it rather than
the dress itself—the dress-thought may be said to go back
into the dress.
This example serves to illustrate several aspects of the
problem at hand. It is the Advaitin contention that what we
are concerned with in the process of ordinary living is not
the real /but the I-thought, just as what the lady was concerned
with in exploring her romantic situation was the dress-
thought and not the dress, even though she may find it
difficult to draw this distinction. Although the dress as dress-
thought was the object of so much activity, the dress as such
just lay passively on the table. It is the Advaitin contention
that just as it was not the dress but the dress-thought which
ran the young lady’s life for a while, it is not pure subject—
the pure I —but the /- thought which runs our lives, divorced
from the real I but deriving its existence from it, just as the
dress-thought is divorced from the dress and yet derives its
existence from it! This I-thought is also called the ego and it
is said that “those alone who have found out the real nature
of the ego have seen reality. They will have no more doubts
or anxiety. ” 104 Even this point can be clarified analogically:
Advaila Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
91
just as once one has discovered the nature of the dress-
thought—which one constantly confused with the dress
itself—one would also discover the real nature of the dress
as such, unclouded by the dress-thought.
In Advaita, it is said that realization of one’s true nature
entails realizing how the I-thought rises from the real /. ‘To
say / am this or I am ihat there must be the I. This / is only
the ego or the I-thought is therefore the root-thought ...find
out its source. Then all these [other thoughts] will vanish
and the pure self will remain over .”" 15 Similarly one is told
that the ego proceeds from the self as a spark from fire.
“The spark is called the ego. In the case of the ignorant
man it identifies itself with an object simultaneously with its
rise. It cannot remain independent of such association with
objects If its objectifying tendency is killed it remains pure
and also merges into the source .”" 1 ' 1 This point can also be
made in relation to the analogy of the dress-thought and
the dress. When we perceive the dress qua dress without
dress-thoughts, one can describe the process as either tracing
dress-thoughts back to their source, the dress, or making
dress-thoughts merge into the dress.
Just as one needed to distinguish between the dress and
the dress-thought, one needs to distinguish between the I
and the I-thought. “You must distinguish between the I, pure
in itself, and the I- thought .” 107 “If you stay as the /, your
being alone, without thought, the /-thought will disappear
and the delusion will vanish forever .” 108
This raises the interesting question: are there two Is ? The
parallel question in terms of the analogy would be—are there
two dresses ? There is only one dress. Similarly, there is only
one I. But just as the dress gives rise to the dress-thought,
the I-thought emerges from the I. Or, one can even say that
once the dress-thought has arisen, several dress-thoughts in
various phases arise based on the original dress-thought.
Thus the sequence runs as follows: dress > dress-thought >
dress thoughts. This helps explain the following: “The I of
the dream has vanished. Another I speaks of the dream.
92
Advaita Vedanta
This / was not in the dream. Both the r s are unreal. There
is the substratum of the mind which continues all along,
giving rise to so many scenes. With every thought rises /, and
with its disappearance the I disappears too. So the Is are
born, and die every moment ,’’" 11 like dress-thoughts
emerging from moment to moment. Once one knows that
the dress is lying safely on the table the vicissitudes of the
dress-thoughts cease to be a cause for concern.
There are other ways as well in which the analogy of the
dress and dress-thought is illuminating. For instance, it is
said in Advaita : “That which makes the enquiry is the ego.
The / about which the inquiry is made is also the ego. As a
result of the enquiry the ego ceases to exist .”" 0 Parallel:
starting as we do from the realm of the dress-thought, it is
the dress-thought, which inquires into itself. Then it realizes
it is just the dress-thought and disappears, yielding place to
the actual dress lying on the table. Again, in Advaita one is
encouraged to enquire who undergoes the vicissitudes of
life and discover that only the ego is affected by them, not
the self, and that “the ego is non-existent.” Parallel: the dress-
thoughts undergo all the vicissitudes, they do not bind the
dress itself and the dress-thoughts are non-existent in the
sense that what really exists is only the dress. Again it is said:
“Reality is simply the loss of ego.”"' Parallel: the recognition
of the reality of the dress is simply the loss of dress-thoughts.
Thus the analogy is helpful in many ways. Let me close by
poindng out two more instances in which it is helpful in a
much more dynamic sense—in shedding light on the actual
pursuit of the spiritual goal.
It is sometimes said that the realization could be sudden
or gradual, that is, taking time to steady itself. At times
Ramana said that “there are no degrees of liberation ,”" 2
and at other times that “realization takes time to steady
itself .”" 3 This could also be understood in terms of our
analogy. Let us imagine that the young lady in the parable is
suddenly told that her beau has run off with someone else! If
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
93
the lady is shocked to her sense by this revelation the dress
would immediately become a piece of cloth for her—the
dress-thoughts would disappear. If, however, she still retained
affection for the heel who left her, dress-thoughts might
still occasionally arise from the dress and may only gradually
subside till the dress become just a piece of cloth (that is, till
she finds another beau).
It is also sometimes said that realization is not possible so
long as one is “aware of an /”; it is only possible upon “being
the /’. So long as one has thoughts of the dress, one is in a
sense in a state of alienation from the dress and still in the
realm of dress-thoughts. But when the dress becomes the
dress —that is, when all dress-thought disappear, then alone
it is in its natural and primal state.
The process of realization may be said to consist of three
stages. In the first stage one is aware of only the I-thought to
begin with. One is so carried away by this identification with
the I-thought to begin with that one doesn’t know there is an
underlying real / which is quite different from the I-thought,
although the source of it. In other words, the pure subject,
though ever present, is never known because of one’s
identification of existence with the three states of
consciousness which conceal the pure witness. One must, in
the second stage, lose sight of the world to experience the
pure subject. As Ramana explains in this catechetical series:
When will the realization of the self be gained ?
When the world, which is what is seen as, has been
removed, there will be realization of the self which
is the seer.
Will there not be the realization of the self—even while
the world is there (taken as real)? There will not be . 114
In the third stage, once the pure subject is realized, the
world is again seen but now as part of the self and not apart
from it as was the case in the beginning. In terms of our
analogy one begins with the young lady with her mind full
94
Advuiia Vedanta
of dress-thoughts. In stage two she experiences the actual
dress to be worn. She cannot see it unless the dress-thoughts
depart from the mind, so that she can see and experience
the actual dress. While actually experiencing it ever, the
thought “this is the dress” is a distraction from it. Finally,
emerging from the absorption in the dress she can again
lose herself in dress-thoughts going down the aisle but she is
aware of the relationship of these dress thoughts to the real
dress, which was not the case the first time.
The relation between the dress and the dress-thought
continues to possess considerable illustrative and therefore
explanatory power. This becomes apparent, when we explore
the nature of the /-thought as analyzed in Advaita Vedanta a
little further. When the “I” thought arises in the context of
person, it is worth noting that it often takes the form “I-am-
the-body ”. 113 That is to say—it is not a vague free-floating “I”
thought and it has a definite if fully undetermined referent.
Similarly, the dress-thought, in relation to the dress, is not a
dress thought in general, but assumes the form of “a dress-
thought” rather than “dress thought” in general, or a
collection of dresses as it were. “Is there not a name for the
body? It is that which we take as the name of that particular
person. When asked who you are, one says, I am Rama. If
someone calls Rama, that person alone looks back. While
other bodies have other names, this particular body becomes
Rama ”" 6 Similarly, other chains of dress thoughts may have
their own identities, and may arise in different contexts,
but this chain of dress-thought possesses its own identity—
and destiny.
The metaphor on hand can even be developed to indicate
the relation between the various sheaths mentioned in the
Upanisads, and its relation to the I and the I-thought. In
accordance with the doctrine of the various kosas or sheaths,
an individual is presented as “sheathed” in five of them—
and at their core lies the true atman or I. But empirically,
the person exists as an entity covered in these sheaths and
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
95
generated by an “I-thought”. The person is like the young
lady wrapped up in the dress, but still carried away by the
“dress-thought” into the reverie she is in. In fact one can
come to point even more directly here, by undertaking a
simple exercise. Please sit down at a desk quietly and just
think of yourself as someone sitting down by the desk quietly.
What you have in your mind is an 1-thought of yourself sitting
down by the desk. Similarly, the young lady sitting by herselt
thinking of doing all kinds of things with the dress on, is
trafficking in the dress-thought just as we traffic in I-thought.
Experiential Advaita also draws a distinction between what
is called manolaya and manonasa. The first term stands for
the temporary suspension of mental activity and the second
term for final elimination of mental activity as an obstacle to
self-realization. The distinction is important in experiential
Advaita because it is on the basis of this distinction that it
distinguishes its own samadhi from that which results from
the practice of Yoga. Ramana Maharsi explains the point as
follows:
In deep sleep the mind is merged and not
destroyed. That which merges reappears. It may
happen in meditation also. But the mind which is
destroyed cannot reappear. The yogi’s aim must
be to destroy it and not to sink into laya. In the
peace of meditation, laya sometimes ensues but it
is not enough. It must be supplemented by other
practices for destroying the mind. Some people
have gone into yogic samadhi with a trifling
thought and after a long time awakened in the
trail of the same thought. In the meantime
generations have passed in the world. Such a yogi
has not destroyed his mind. The true destruction
of the mind is the non- recognition of it as being
apart from the Self. 117
The metaphor of the dress is useful here. So long as the
idea of the wedding persists, the dress-thoughts will continue
96
Advaila Vedanta
to reappear even if they disappear for a while, but once the
idea of wedding is abandoned altogether, the dress-thoughts
will cease and stop interfering with one’s perception of the
dress as such.
We often talk of the mind. It is one of the claims of
experiential Advaita that the concept the mind doesn’t bear
scrutiny.
What is the mind? The reply which Bhagavan
[Ramana Maharsi] gives us is thaL mind is nothing
but (a bundle of) thoughts. If one investigates what
this mind is, keeping off all thoughts, he will find
that there is no such thing as mind. 118
The link between the I and the 1-thought is the mind. When
it is claimed that there is no mind what is meant is that there
is no mind apart from the thoughts, just as there is no river
apart from its flow. Similarly, then, there is no dress-thought
apart from the bundle of thoughts which have arisen from
the dress or flow from it. And further: just as if one probed
these “dress-thoughts” uninterruptedly one will be led back
to the dress, so also the uninterrupted interrogation of I-
thoughts will jolt one back to the true /.
At another level the whole metaphor of the dress and
dress-thought in a way helps elaborate the way the subtle
body is said to operate in the psychology of Advaita Vedanta.
The following account is self-explanatory in this respect.
Let it not be considered that the mind takes a subtle
body only in dreams. The same phenomenon takes
place even in the waking state during flights of
the mind, for instance in a revery. Suppose we sit
and imagine in the waking state that we travel to
far off countries, meet a friend there, talk with
him or undergo all the vicissitudes of life. The
mentally projected body in which we seem to
undergo all these experiences is also our subtle
body. We know that these subtle bodies we take
up now and then are transient. When one wakes
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
97
up from a dream, the dream body is gone. In the
same way the body assumed in day-dreams
(reveries) is also found to be false, i.e. these bodies
are the false forms that come to and go away from
us. Because we exist even in the absence of these
bodies, they are not WE." 9
In the course of developing this illustration so far we have
focused on the emergence of the dress-thought (and then
even dress-thoughts) from the dress as an example of how
the I-thought (and then even the many I-thoughts) can arise
from the real “I”. With a little shift in focus, however, the
application of this I metaphor to our existential situation
can also be enlarged. In order to see how this might be
possible let’s go back to the young lady who imagines wearing
the dress she has bought when she goes out with her beau
for the candle-light dinner.
Let us now visualize her imagining this scene while relaxing
in her room—that she is sitting next to her beau on a table in
the restaurant in the dress she has bought. Now note that
not only is she wearing a dress-thought as she imagines herself
in the restaurant, she herself, as she imagines herself in the
restaurant, is not she herself but a thought of herself. For
she, as she really is, is sitting right there in the room! So it is
a she-thought (and not she, although the she-thought
proceeds from her) who is wearing the dress-thought! Now
note that the dress-thought is an object and she-thought is a
subject, and the sAe-thought is also wearing the dress-thought—
that is—the object and subject are interacting but in a world
of thought —so that their interaction also partakes of the same
character. The ontological status of all of them, though
derivative, is the same! This is how Advaita Vedanta is able
to combine an empirical realism with a transcendental
idealism.
Or to put the matter more philosophically: a major issue this
school of thought has to contend with is not an unexpected
one: how to reconcile its claim of a metaphysical non-dual reality
with the apparent plurality of our empirical existence.
98
Advaita Vedanta
Here is a glimpse of the ways in which such a reconciliation
might be proposed. The range of our experience in the
empirical world is vertiginously diverse, but a little reflection
suggests that all of it occurs in one of three states of
consciousness: when one is awake, when one is dreaming
and while one is in deep sleep. These three states of
experience provide a useful handle for talking of our
empirical world because all the varied experiences we have
in this world can be slotted as falling within one of these
three states of consciousness. Now in the waking state physical
objects are real (at the empirical level). It can thus be
described as sat or real. Compared to them objects and persons
encountered in a dream are merely mental in nature and it
can thus be described as tit, or characterized by immaterial
conscious-ness. Finally, the experience of deep sleep is
universally considered restful, blissful and happy. Thus this state
of consciousness qualifies as dnanda or bliss. Thus the empirical
reality we experience can be described as follows:
Waking Sat
Dreaming Cit
Deep Sleep Ananda
Readers will recall, however, that the ultimate reality, at
the transcendental level, was also described in part I of this
book as saccidananda Brahman, where Brahman denoted the
ultimate reality to which the words sat (reality), cit
(consciousness) and dnanda (bliss) are applied as ways of
orienting ourselves towards it.
In other words, the question we are dealing with may be
rephrased as follows: what is the relationship of the ultimate
reality as sat, cit and dnanda and our experience of the
empirical world, which is also capable of being so described.
The question may be answered with the help of a chart.
Sat, Cit, Ananda,
Brahman
Sat
Waking
Git
Dreaming
World
Ananda
Deep Sleep
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
99
How could the horizontal line become the vertical, in other
words? Just as a straight rod appears bent when placed in a
tub full of water, say Advaita Vedanta. That is to say, there is
something in the nature of the empirical world which
apparently distorts the ultimate reality when viewed in
relation with it. The word used to denote this something in
Advaita Vedanta is maya or avidya.
But matters get straightened out when one achieves
enlightenment. One way of moving towards such
enlightenment or Realisation is to ask the question: if I
undergo the experience of waking, dreaming and deep
sleep which as states of consciousness differ so radically from
one another, then how do I retain my sense of identity
despite undergoing these different states of experience, and
the different experiences I have within these states of
waking, dreaming and deep sleep. There must be some
unchanging consciousness in me which undergirds my
consciousness of change of these states of consciousness and
the changes within them. Such unchanging consciousness
is called dtman in Advaita Vedanta—which constitutes the
unchanging core of our being.
According to Advaita Vedanta this dtman is identical with
Brahman. They are not two. It is this understanding of non¬
dualism—that the dtman and Brahman are not two distinct
entities but identically one—which represents experientially
the most resonant dimension of Advaitic non-dualism. This is
the truth but somehow it has become warped and it is the
goal of Advaita Vedanta to help us straighten it out.
VI
In analysing the experiential approach so far we have stuck
to the experience of ordinary human beings. It may not be
out of place now at least to refer to the experiences of an
extraordinary kind which have a bearing on Advaita Vedanta.
We have some accounts of mystical experiences of the
Advaitic variety from the accounts of the lives of mystics of
the twentieth century, which bear on the present discussion.
100
Advaita Vedanta
They are such as are best shared rather than explained.
The first of these is from the life of Swami Vivekananda
(1863-1902) who bore the name Narendra Nath Dutt, or
Naren for short, before he became a monk. He ultimately
came to acknowledge Sri Ramakrsna Paramhamsa(1836-
1886) as his master. The relevance of the following account
of a spiritual incident between the two will not be lost on
students of Advaita Vedanta.
Thus one day the Master told Narendranath many
things indicating the oneness ofjlva and Brahman
of the non-dual philosophy. He heard those words,
undoubtedly with attention, but he could not
comprehend them and went to Hazra at the end
of the Master’s talk. Smoking and discussing those
things again with Hazra, he said, ‘Can it ever be
possible that the waterpot is God, the cup is God,
whatever we see and all of us are God?’ Shri Hazra
also joined Narendra in thus ridiculing the idea
and both of them burst into laughter. The Master
was till then in the state of partial external
consciousness. Hearing Narendra laugh, he came
out of his room like a boy with his wearing cloth in
his armpit and, coming to them smiling, said
affectionately, ‘What are you both talking about?’
He then touched Narendra and went into
samadhi.
Narendra said to us afterwards, ‘There was a
complete revolution in the state of my mind in a
moment at the wonderful touch of the Master. I
was aghast to see actually that there was nothing
in the whole universe except God. But I remained
silent in spite of seeing it, wondering how long
that state would last. But that inebriation did not
at all diminish that day. I returned home; it was all
the same there; it seemed to me that all that I saw
was He. I sat far my meal when I saw that all -food,
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
101
plate, the one who was serving as well as myself—
were nothing but He. I took a mouthful or two
and sat quiet. My mother’s affectionate words—
“why do you sit quiet; why don’t you eat?”—
brought me to consciousness and I began eating
again. Thus, I had that experience at the time of
eating or drinking, sitting or lying, going to the
college or taking a stroll. I was always overwhelmed
with a sort of indescribable intoxication. When I
walked along the streets and saw a carriage coming
along before me I did not feel inclined, as at other
times, to move away, lest it should collide with me.
For, I thought, “I am also that and nothing but
that”. My hands and feet always remained
insensible at that time. I felt no satisfaction
whatever when I took my food. It seemed to me as
if some one else was eating the meal... When that
overwhelming intoxication diminished a little, the
world appeared to me to be a dream. Going for a
walk on the bank of the Hedua tank, I knocked
my head against the iron railings round it to see
whether what I saw were dream-rails or actual ones.
On account of the insensibility of my hands and
feet I was afraid whether I was not going to have
paralysis. I could not escape that terrible
intoxicating mood and overwhelming condition
for some time. When I came to the normal state, I
thought that that was indication of non-dual
knowledge. So what is written in the Sastras about
it is by no means untrue. Since then I could never
doubt the truth of non-duality. 120
The second account is drawn from the life of Ramana
Maharsi (1879-1950) who is regarded as one of the great
Advaitins of our age. He underwent the following precocious
experience in 1896.
It was about six weeks before I left Madurai for good
102
Advaita Vedanta
that the great change in my life took place. It was
so sudden. One day I sat alone on the first floor of
my uncle’s house. I was in my usual health. I seldom
had any illness. I was a heavy sleeper. When I was at
Dindigul in 1891 a huge crowd had gathered close
to the room where I slept and tried to rouse me by
shouting and knocking at uie door, all in vain, and
it was only by their getting into my room and giving
me a violent shake that I was roused from my torpor.
This heavy sleep was rather a proof of good health.
I was also subject to fits of half-awake sleep at night.
My wily playmates, afraid to trifle with me when I
was awake, would go to me when I was asleep, rouse
me, take me all round the playground, beat me,
cuff me, sport with me, and bring me back to my
bed—and all the while I would put up with
everything with a meekness, humility, forgiveness,
and passivity unknown to my waking state. When
the morning broke I had no remembrance of the
night’s experiences. But these fits did not render
me weaker or less fit for life and were hardly to be
considered a disease. So, on that day as I sat alone
there was nothing wrong with my health. But
sudden and unmistakable fear of death seized me.
I felt I was going to die. Why I should have so felt
cannot now be explained by anything felt in my
body. Nor could 1 explain it to myself then. I did
not however trouble myself to discover if the fear
was well grounded. I felt I was going to die, and at
once set about thinking out what I should do. I did
not care to consult doctors or elders or even friends.
I felt I had to solve the problem myself then and
there.
The shock of fear of death made me at once
introspective, or introverted. I said to myself mentally,
i.e., without uttering the words—‘Now, death has
come. What does it mean? What is it that is dying?
Advaila Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
103
This body dies.’ I at once dramatised the scene of
death. I extended my limbs and held them rigid
as though rigor-mortis had set in. I imitated a corpse
to lend an air of reality to my further investigation,
I held my breath and kept my mouth closed,
pressing the lips together so that no sound might
escape. Let not the word I or any other word be
uttered! Well then, said I to myself, ‘this body is
dead. It will be carried stiff to the burning ground
and there burnt and reduced to ashes. But with
the death of this body, am “I” dead? Is the body
“I”? This body is silent and inert. But I feel the full
force of my personality and even the sound “I”
within myself,—apart from the body. So “I” am a
spirit, a thing transcending the body. The material
body dies, but the spirit transcending it cannot be
touched by death. I am therefore the deathless
spirit.’ All this was not a mere intellectual process,
but flashed before me vividly as living truth,
something which I perceived immediately, without
any argument almost. 1 was something very real,
the only real thing in that state, and all the
conscious activity that was connected with my body
was centred on that. The / or my self was holding
the focus of attention by a powerful fascination
from that time forwards. Fear of death had
vanished at once and forever. Absorption in the
self has continued from that moment right up to
this time. Other thoughts may come and go like
the various notes of a musician, but the /continues
like the basic or fundamental sruti note which
accompanies and blends with all other notes.
Whether the body was engaged in talking, reading,
or anything else, I was still centred on I. Previous
to that crisis I had no clear perception of myself
and was not consciously attracted to it. I had felt
no direct perceptible interest in it, much less any
104
Advaita Vedanta
permanent disposition to dwell upon it. The
consequences of this new habit were soon noticed
in my life. 121
Paul Brunton offers the following abbreviated account.
Maharsi told once how he got realization. On the
day his father died he felt puzzled by death and
pondered over it, whilst his mother and brothers
wept. He thought for hours and after the corpse
was cremated he got by analysis to the point of
perceiving that it was the / which makes the body
to see, to run, to walk and to eat. “I now know this
/but my father’s / has left the body”. 122
The third account is the report of a talk byj. Krishnamurti
(1895-1986). Whether Krishnamurti should be installed in
the Advaitic pantheon is a matter of debate, therefore a
word of explanation might be required by way justifying the
inclusion of the excerpt. One of the chief tenets of Advaita
Vedanta, as scripturally propounded, is the claim that
realization is achieved not by action {karma) but jnana
(insight); that what transcends action cannot be achieved
by action. The following discourse of Krishnamurti is
potentially illuminating in this respect.
Krishnamurti : For most of us, our whole life is based
on effort, some kind of volition. And we cannot
conceive of an action that is not based on it. Our
social, economic, and so-called spiritual life, is a
series of efforts, always culminating in a certain
result. We think effort is essential. So we are now
going to find out if it is possible to live differently,
without this constant battle.
Why do we make effort? Put simply, it is in order
to achieve a result, to become something, to reach
a goal, isn’t it? If we do not make an effort, we
think we shall stagnate. We have an idea about
the goal towards which we are constantly striving;
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
105
and this striving has become part of our life. If we
want to alter, to bring about a radical change in
ourselves, we make a tremendous effort to
eliminate old habits, to resist the habitual
environmental influences, and so on. So we are
used to this series of efforts in order to find or
achieve something, in order to live at all.
Now, is not all such effort the activity of the self? Is
not effort self-centred activity? And, if we make
an effort from the centre of the self, it must
inevitably produce more conflict, more confusion,
more misery. Yet we keep on making effort after
effort; and very few of us realize that the self-
centred activity of effort does not clear up any of
our problems. On the contrary, it increases our
confusion and our misery and our sorrow. Or we
know this, and yet continue hoping somehow to
break through this self-centred activity of effort,
the action of the will.
This is our problem—Is it possible to understand
anything without effort? Is it possible to see what
is real, what is true, without introducing the action
of the will, which is essentially based on the self,
the me? And if we do not make an effort, is there
not a danger of deterioration, of going to sleep,
of stagnation? Perhaps, as I am talking, we can
experiment with this individually, and see how far
we can go through this question. For I feel that
what brings happiness, quietness, tranquillity of the
mind, does not come through any effort. A truth
is not perceived through any volition, through any
action of will. And if we can go into it very carefully
and diligently, perhaps we shall find the answer.
How do we react when a truth is presented? Take,
for example, the problem of fear. We realize that
our activity and our being and our whole existence
106
Advaita Vedanta
would be fundamentally altered if there was no fear
of any kind in us. We may see that, we may see the
truth of it; and thereby there is freedom from fear.
But for most of us, when a fact, a truth, is put before
us, what is our immediate response? Please,
experiment with what I am saying; please do not
merely listen. Watch your own reactions; and find
out what happens when a truth, a fact, is out before
you—such as ‘any dependence in relationship
destroys relationship’. Now, when a statement of
that kind is made, what is your response? Do you
see, are you aware of, the truth of it, and does
dependency thereby cease? Or have you an idea
about the fact? Here is a statement of truth. Do we
experience the truth of it, or do we create an idea
about it?
If we can understand this process of the creation
of idea, then we shall perhaps understand the
whole process of effort. Because once we have
created the idea, then effort comes into being.
Then the problem arises, what to do, how to act?
That is, we see that psychological dependence on
another is a form of self-fulfilment; it is not love;
in it there is conflict, fear, the desire to fulfil
oneself through another, jealousy, and so on,
which corrode. We see that psychological
dependence on another embraces all these facts.
Then, we proceed to create the idea, do we not?
We do not directly experience the fact, the truth
of it; but, we look at it, and then create an idea of
how to be free from dependence. We see the
implications of psychological dependence, and
then we create the idea of how to be free from it.
We do not directly experience the truth, which is
the liberating factor. But out of the experience of
looking at that fact we create an idea. We are
incapable of looking at it directly, without ideation.
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
107
Then, having created the idea, we proceed to carry
out that idea into action. Then we try to bridge
the gap between idea and action—in which effort
is involved.
So can we not look at the truth without creating
ideas? It is almost instinctive with most of us: when
ccsm utfiirsrr
jouie l.llllig
iv.uiatv.ij
create an idea about it. And I think if we can
understand why we do this so instinctively, almost
unconsciously, then perhaps we shall understand
if it is possible to be free from effort.
Why then do we create ideas about truth? Surely
that is important to find out, is it not? Either we
see the truth nakedly, as it is, or we do not. But
why do we have a picture about it, a symbol, a word,
an image, which necessitates a postponement, the
hope of an eventual result? So can we hesitantly
and guardedly go into this process of why the mind
creates the image, the idea—that I must be this or
that, that I must be free from dependence, and
so on? We know very well that when we see
something very clearly, experience it directly,
there is a freedom from it. It is that immediacy
that is vital, not the picture or the symbol of the
truth—on which all systems and philosophies and
deteriorating organizations are built. So is it not
important to find out why the mind, instead of
seeing the thing directly and simply, and
experiencing the truth of it immediately, creates
an idea about it?
I do not know if you have thought about this. It
may perhaps be something new. And to find the
truth of it, please do not merely resist. Do not say,
‘What would happen if the mind did not create
the idea? It is its function to create ideas, to
verbalize, to recall memories, to recognize, to
108
Advaila Vedanta
calculate’. We know that. But the mind is not free;
and it is only when the mind is capable of looking
at the truth totally, completely, without any barrier,
that there is freedom.
So our problem is—why does the mind, instead of
seeing the thing immediately and experiencing it
directly, indulge in sll tHese idecis. Is this not one
of the habits of the mind? Something is presented
to us, and immediately there is the old habit of
creating an idea, a theory about it. And the mind
likes to live in habit. Because without habit the
mind is lost. If there is not a routine, a habitual
response to which it has become accustomed, it
feels confused, uncertain.
That is one aspect. Also, does not the mind seek a
result? Because in the result is permanence. And
the mind hates to be uncertain. It is always seeking
security in different forms—through beliefs, through
knowledge, through experience. And when that is
quesdoned there is a disturbance, anxiety. And so
the mind, avoiding uncertainty, seeks security for
itself by making efforts to achieve a result.
I hope you are actually observing your own minds
in operation. If you are not, then you will not
experience, your mind will remain on the verbal
level. But—if I may suggest—if you can observe
your own mind in operation, and watch how it
thinks, how it reacts, when a truth is out before it,
then you will experience step-by-step what I am
talking about. Then there will be an extraordinary
experience. And it is this direct approach, this
direct experience of what truth is that is so
essential for bringing about a creative life.
So why does the mind create these ideas, instead
of directly experiencing? Why does the mind
Advaita Vedanta: An Experiential Approach
109
intervene? As we have said, it is habit. Also, the
mind wants to achieve a result. We all want to
achieve a result. In listening to me, are you looking
for a result? You are, aren’t you? The mind is
seeking a result; it sees that dependence is
destructive, and therefore it wants to be free of it.
Rut the very desire to be free creates the idea.
The mind is not free; but the desire to be free
creates the idea of freedom as the goal towards
which it must work. And thereby effort comes into
being. And that effort is self-centred; it does not
bring freedom. Instead of depending on a person,
you depend on an idea or on an image. So your
effort is only self-enclosing; it is not liberating.
Now, can the mind, realizing that it is caught in
habit, be free from habit—not have an idea that it
should achieve freedom as an eventual goal, but
see the truth that the mind is caught in habit,
directly experience it? And, similarly, can the mind
see that it is pursuing incessantly a permanence
for itself, a goal that it must achieve, a God, a truth,
a virtue, a state of being, or whatever, and is
thereby bringing about this action of will, with all
its complications? And when we see that, is it not
possible to experience the truth of something
directly without all the paraphernalia of
verbalization? You may objectively see a fact, in that
there is no ideation, no creation of idea, symbol,
desire. But subjectively, inwardly, it is entirely
different. Because there we want a result; there is
the craving to be something, to achieve, to
become—in which all effort is born.
I feel that to see what is true from moment to
moment, without any effort, but directly to
experience it, is the only creative existence. Because
it is only in moments of complete tranquillity that
10
Advaita Vedanta
you discover something—not when you are making
an effort, whether it is under the microscope or
inwardly. It is only when the mind is not agitated,
not caught in habit, not trying to achieve a result,
not trying to become something—it is only when it
is not doing these things, when it is really tranquil,
when there is no effort, no movement—that there
is a possibility of discovering something new.
Surely, that is freedom from the self, that is the
abnegation of the me —and not the outward
symbols, whether you possess this or that virtue or
not. But freedom comes into being only when you
understand your own processes, conscious as well
as unconscious. It is possible only when we go fully
into the different processes of the mind. And as
most of us live in a state of tension, in constant
effort, it is essential to understand the complexity
of effort, to see the truth that effort does not bring
virtue, that effort is not love, that effort does not
bring about the freedom that truth alone can
give—which is direct experiencing. For that, one
has to understand the mind, one’s own mind—
not somebody else’s mind, not what somebody else
says about it. You may read all the volumes ever
written but they will be utterly useless. For you
must observe your own mind, and penetrate it
more and more deeply, and experience the thing
directly as you go along. Because there is the living
quality, not in the things of the mind. And the
mind, to find its own processes, must not be
enclosed by its own habits, but must be free
occasionally to look. Therefore, it is important to
understand this whole process of effort. For effort
does not bring about freedom. Effort is only more
and more self-enclosing, more and more
destructive, outwardly as well as inwardly, in
relationship with one or with many. 123
A verse, popular in India, claims to summarize the teachings
of the school of Advaita Vedanta in just half of a verse:
Brahman is real; the world is an illusory appearance;
and the individual soul (jiva) [in its true character]
is Brahman alone, none other. 124
Or to put the matter more formally:
The non-duality of Brahman, the non-reality of the
world, and the non-difference of the soul [Atman]
from Brahman—these constitute the teaching of
Advaita. 125
The reader would have noticed that whether we approach
Advaita Vedanta scripturally, or rationally, or experientially,
in the end one finds oneself face-to-face with the pedagogical
structure which bears a family-resemblance to this statement.
While following the scriptural approach one starts out with
Brahman and Atman and has to confront the issue of their
identity in the face of the apparent plurality which
characterizes our life. In adopting the rational approach one
starts out with the world—or an object of the world—and
finds oneself confronting indeterminate existence. In
adopting the experiential approach one starts out with oneself
only to see one’s self facing experiential dissolution. In all
three cases one finds oneself at an interface between reality
and unreality—but an unreality which cannot be severed from
Reality and vice versa, as it were.
The aim of this book was not much to convey the technical
details of the system of philosophy of Advaita Vedanta, on
112 Advaiia Vedanta
which many books exist, as to convey its spirit, for it is as
much a spirituality as a philosophy. Whether it has succeeded
in this is for the reader to decide.
Notes
1. Andrew O. Fort, fivanmukti in Transformation: Embodied Liberation in
Advaita and Neo-Vedanta (Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York
Press, 1998).
2. Wilhelm Halbfass, India and Europe: An Essay in Understanding (Albany,
N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1988) p. 353.
3. M. Hiriyanna, The Essentials of Indian Philosophy, (London: George Allen
& Unwin, 1949) p. 19.
4. Ibid., p. 152.
5. Ibid., p. 154.
6. For a good discussion of this point see John Grimes, Problems and
Perspectives in Religious Discourse: Advaita Vedanta Implications (Albany,
N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1994).
7. Ibid.,p. 156-157,
8. Ibid, p. 157-158.
9. Ibid, p. 158.
10. Ibid.
11. Ibid., p. 157.
12. Ibid., p. 158.
13. Ibid.
14. Ibid., p. 47-48.
15. Ibid., p. 159-160.
16. K. Satchidananda Murty, Revelation and Reason in Advait a Vedanta. (Delhi:
Motilal Banarsidass, 1974) p. 40.
17. M. Hiriyanna, Indian Philosophical Studies. (Mysore: Kavyalaya Publishers,
1957) p. 89.
18. M. Hiriyanna, The Essentials of Indian Philosophy, p. 21.
19. Ibid.
20. Robert Ernest Hume, tr. The Thirteen Principal Upanishads. (London:
Oxford University Press, 1968) p. 113-114.
21. Thomas J. Hopkins, The Hindu Religious Tradition (Encino, California
and Belmont, California: Dickenson Publishing Company, Inc., 1971)
p. 37.
22. Robert Ernest Hume, tr., op. til., p, 132-133.
114
Advaila Vedanta
23. Ainslie T. Embree, ed., Sources of Indian Tradition (second edition) (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1988) Vol. I, p. 32.
24. Ibid., p. 33
25. Ibid.
26. S. Radhakrishnan, The Principal Upanisads. (Atlantic Heights, NJ:
Humanities Press, 1992) p. 695-705.
27. Ibid., p. 36.
28. Ainslie T. Embree, ed., The Hindu Tradition (New York: Random House,
1972) p. 52.
29. Ibid., p. 55.
30. Ibid., p. 55.
31. Ibid, p. 21.
32. Ibid., p. 22.
33. Ibid., p. 22.
34. Ibid.
35. Troy Wilson Organ, Hinduism: Its Historical Development^ Woodbury,
N.Y.: Barron’s Educational Series, 1974) p. 114.
36. M. Hiriyanna, Outlines of Indian Philosophy, p. 378.
37. Troy Wilson Organ, Hinduism: Its Historical Development, p. 114.
38. Ibid., p.114-115.
39. Chandradhar Sharma, A Critical Survey of Indian Philosophy (London:
Rider, 1960) p. 282-283.
40. I incorporate material here, which also appears in Arvind Sharma, The
Philosophy of Religion and Advaila Vedanta: A Comparative Study of Religion
and Reason (University Park, Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State
University Press, 1995) p. 97-99.
41. Satchidananda Murty, Revelation and Reason in Advaita Vedanta, p. 81.
42. Robert Ernest Hume, op. cit. p. 240-241.
43. See the discussion of the Honey-Doctrine (madhu-vidya), R.E. Hume,
op. cit., p. 102-105.
44. M. Hiriyanna, The Essentials of Indian Philosophy, p. 157.
45. Heinrich Zimmer, Philosophies of India. (Edited by Joseph Campbell.
New York: Princeton University Press, 1969) p. 337-338.
46. Patrick Olivelle, The Early Upanisads (New York: Oxford University Press,
1998) p. 561.
47. S. Radhakrishnan, ed., op. cit., p. 462.
48. Ibid., p. 463.
49. Franklin Edgerton, “Studies in the Veda "Journal of the American Oriental
Society 35:242 (1915).
50. In the case of some ordeals it is possible to propose a psychological
basis for the confidence that the innocent party may get acquitted,
although it is doubtful if it applies here:
Notes
115
Specially interesting is the ordeal of the ploughshare, in which the
accused man had to touch a red-hot iron ploughshare with his tongue;
if it was not burned he was deemed innocent—psychologically a fairly
sound test of his own confidence in the result: since if he had a guilty
conscience his salivary glands would not function properly, and his
tongue would be burnt." (A.L. Basham, The Wonder that was India [New
Delhi; Rupa & Co., 1999] p.l 17.) Curiously enough, a similar claim is
made in a similar context in Islamic mysticism, as in the Upanisadic
passage, see Reynold A. Nicholson, The Mystics of Islam (Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1889 [1914]) p. 182-183.
51. Ibid., p. 245-250, with subheadings removed.
52. Sacchidananda Murty, op. cit., p. 89.
53. Ibid., Chapter VI passim.
54. Ibid., p. 89-90,97.
55. Ibid., p. 92.
56. Ibid., p. 93.
57. Ibid., p. 93.
58. Ibid., p. 96.
59. Ibid., p. 98.
60. See Arvind Sharma, The Philosophy of Religion and Advaila Vedanta: A
Comparative Study in Religion and Reason, p. 46-47.
61. M. Hiriyanna, The Essentials of Indian Philosophy. P. 160-161.
62. Ibid., p. 59.
63. Ibid., p. 22-23.
64. Satischandra Chatterjee and Dhirendramohan Datta, An Introduction
to Indian Philosophy (Calcutta: University of Calcutta, 1950) p. 382.
65. Ibid., p. 382.
66. Ibid.
67. Ibid., p.383.
68. Ibid., p. 383.
69. M. Hiriyanna, Outlines of Indian Philosophy (London; George Allen &
Unwin, 1932) p. 370.
70. M. Hiriyanna, Outlines of Indian Philosophy p. 370-371.
71. Satishchandra Chatterjee and Dhirendramohan Datta, op. cit., p. 383-
384.
72. Ibid., p.384.
73. Ibid.
74. Ibid., p. 385.
75. Ibid.
76. Ibid., diacritics supplied.
77. Ibid., p. 386-387.
78. Ibid., p.388.
116
Advaita Vedanta
79. find., p. 392.
80. Ibid.
81. Ibid., p. 467. “This conclusion is further supported by the linguistic
cxpiessiuu 'my body', ‘my sense', 'my intellect’, 'etc. which show that
the self can alienate itself from there ( body, sense, etc.) and treat them
as external objects distinct from itself. These cannot, therefore, be
regarded as the real essence of the self. It is true, one also sometimes
says, ‘my consciousness.’ But such an expression cannot be taken
literally, as implying a distinction between the self ( as possessor )and
consciousness ( as possessed). For, if the self tries to distinguish itself
from consciousness, it only assumes the form of distinguishing
consciousness. Consciousness thus proves inseparable and
indistinguishable from the self. So ‘my consciousness’ must be taken in
the metaphorical sense. The possessive case here doesn’t really imply
distinction, but rather identity or apposition ( as in ‘The city of
London’). By comparing and analyzing the different meanings of the
self expressed by T and ‘mine’ we discover thus pure consciousness as
the real essence of the self’ ibid., p. 407-408).
82. Ibid., p. 408.
83. M. Hiriyanna, Indian Philosophical Studies ( Mysore : Kavyalaya Publishers,
1957 )p. 135.
84. Ibid.,p. 135-136.
85. Satishchandra Chatterjee and Dhirendramohan Datta, op. til., p. 387.
86. Ibid.
87. Quoted in P. Sankaranarayanan, What is Advaita? (Bombay: Bharatiya
Vidya Bhavan, 1970) p. 46.
88. Ibid., p. 47.
89. Maurice Frydman, tr., I Am That: Conversations With Sri Nisargadatta
Maharaj (Bombay: Chetana, 1973) Part I, p. 263.
90. John A. Hutchinson, Paths of Faith (New York: McGraw-Hill Book
Company, 1969) p. 222.
91. Wm. Theodore de Bary ed., Sources of Chinese Tradition (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1960) Vol. I, p. 73.
92. Ibid., p.72.
93. Ainslie T. Embree, ed.. Sources of Indian Tradition (second edition) (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1988) Vol. I p. 175-176.
94. Swami Sambuddhananda, Vedanta Through Stories (Bombay: Sri
Ramakrishna Ashram, 1959) pp. 44-45.
95. A. Devaraja Mudaliar, compiler, Gems From Bhagavan
(Tiruvannamalai:Sri Ramanasramam, 1985) p. 24-25.
96. Gopal Singh, The Religion of the Sikhs (Bombay: Asia Publishing House,
1971) p.93-94.
97. Talks With Sri Ramana Maharshi (Tiruvannamalai: Sri Ramanasramam,
1984) p. 563.
Notes
117
98 find
99. William M. Indich, Consciousness in Advaita Vedanta (Delhi: Motilal
Banarsidass, 1980) p. 65.
100. Paul Brunton, Conscious Immortality (Tiruvannamaalai: Sri
Ramanasramam, 1984) p. 127.
101. Ibid., p. 184.
102. M. Hiriyanna, Essentials of Indian Philosophy, p. 166.
103. Ibid., p. i 16.
104. A. Devaraja Mudaliar, compiler, op. tit., p. 35.
105. Paul Brunton, op. til., p. 91.
106. David Godman, ed.. The Teachings of Sri Ramana Maharshi (New York:
Arkana, 1985) p. 53.
107. Ibid., p. 52.
108. Ibid.
109. Swami Rajeswarananda, compiler, Erase The Ego (Bombay: Bharatiya
Vidya Bhavan, 1974) p. 39.
110. A. Devaraja Mudaliar, compiler, op. tit., p. 17.
111. Swami Rajeswarananda, compiler, op. tit., p. 55.
112. Arthur Osborne, ed., The Teachings o/Bhagavan Ramana Maharshi in his
Own Words (Tiruvannamalai: T.N. Venkataraman, 1971) p. 249.
113. Ibid., p.228.
114. T.M.P. Mahadevan.tr., WhoAmP (Tiruvannamalai: Sri Ramanasramam,
1976) p. 2.
115. Sadhu Om, The Path of Shri Ramana (Kanpur: The City Book House,
1971) p. 28.
116. Ibid., p. 32.
117. David Godman, ed., op. tit., p. 158.
118. Sadhu Om, op. tit., p. 26.
119. Sadhu Om, op. tit., p. 46.
120. Swami Saradananda, Sri Ramakrishna: The Great Master (Madras:
RamakrishnaMath, 1952) pp. 128-129.
121. B.V. Narsimha Swami, Self-Realization: The Life and Teachings ofSriRamana
Maharishi. (Tiruvannamalai: Sri Ramanasramam, 1985; first published
1931) p. 20.
122. Paul Brunton, op. tit., p. 68.
123. J. Krishnamurd, On Truth. (San Francisco: Harper, 1995) pp. 24-29.
124. T.M.P. Mahadevan, Outlines of Hinduism (Bombay: Chetana Limited,
1971 [1956]) p. 141.
125. Ibid.
Bibliography
Basham, A.L. The Wonder That Was India, Rupa & Co, New Delhi, 1999
[1954],
Brunton, Paul. Conscious Immortality, Sri Ramanasramam, Tiruvannamalai,
1984.
Chatterjee, Satischandra, and Dhirendramohan Datta. An Introduction to
Indian Philosophy, University of Calcutta, Calcutta, 1950.
De Bary., Wm. Theodore, Ed. Sources of Chinese Tradition, Columbia University
Press, New York, 1960.
Edgertion, Franklin. “Studies in Veda”, Journal of the American Oriental Society,
35:242,1915.
Embree, Ainslie T., Ed. Sources of Indian Tradition (second edition), Columbia
University Press, New York, 1988.
Fort, Andrew O.Jtvanmukti in Transformation: Embodied Liberation in Advaita
and neo-Vedanta, Albany, State University of New York Press, N.Y. 1998.
Frydman, Maurice, Tr. I Am That: Conversations urith Sri Nisaragadatta Maharaj,
Part I, Chetana, Bombay, 1973.
Godman, David, Ed. The Teachings of Sri Raman Maharshi, Arkana, New York,
1985.
Halbfass, Wilhelm. India and Europe: An Essay in Understanding, Albany, State
University of New York Press, N. Y., 1988.
Hiriyanna, M. Indian Philosophical Studies, Kavyalaya Publishers, Mysore, 1957.
-. The Essentials of Indian Philosophy, George Allen & Unwin, London, 1949.
-. Outlines of Indian Philosophy, George Allen & Unwin, London, 1932.
Hopkins, Thomas J. The Hindu Religious Tradition, Encino, California and
Belmont, Dickenson Publishing Company, California, 1971.
Hume, Robert Ernest. The Thirteen Principal Upanishads, Oxford University
Press, London, 1968.
120
Advaila Vedanta
Hutchinson, John A. Paths of Faith, McGraw-Hill Book Company, New York,
1969.
Indirh, William M. Consciousness in Advaita Vedanta, Motilal Banarsidass,
Delhi, 1980.
Krishnamurti.J. On Truth, Harper, San Francisco, 1995.
Mahadevan, T. M. P., Tr. Who Am I f Sri Ramanasramam, Tiruvannamalai,
1976.
-. Outlines of Hinduism, Chetana Limited, Bombay, 1971 [1956].
-. Talks With Sri Ramana Maharshi, Sri Ramanasramam, Tiruvannamalai,
1984.
Mudaliar, A. Devaraj (compiler). Gems From Bhagvan, Sri Ramanasramam,
Tiruvannamalai, 1985.
Murty, K_ Satchidananda. Revelation and Reason in Advaita Vedanta, Motilal
Banarsidass, Delhi, 1974.
Nicholson, Reynold A. The Mystics of Islam, Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1914
[1889],
Olivelle, Patrick. The Early Upanisads, Oxford University Press, New York,
1998.
Om, Sadhu. The Path ofShri Ramana, The City Book House, Kanpur, 1971.
Organ, Troy Wilson. Hinduism: Its Historical Development, Woodbury, Barron’s
Educational Series, N. Y., 1974.
Osborne, Arthur, Ed. The Teachings of Bhagavan Ramana Maharshi in His
Own Words, T. N. Venkataraman, Tiruvannamalai, 1071.
Radhakrishnan, S. The Principal Upanisads, N. J.: Humanities Press, Atlantic
Heights, 1992.
Swami Rajeswarananda (compiler). Erase the Ego. Bharatiya Vidya Bhavan,
Bombay, 1974.
Swami Sambuddhananda. Vedanta Through Stories, Sri Ramakrishna Ashram,
Bombay, 1959.
Sankaranarayanan, P. What is Advaita ? Bharatiya Vidya Bhavan, Bombay,
1970.
Swami Saradananda, Tr. Sri Ramakrishna: The Great Master, Ramakrishna
Math, Madras, 1952.
Sharma, Arvind. The Philosophy of Religion and Advaita Vedanta: A Comparative
Study in Religion and Reason, The Pennsylvania State University Press,
University Park, Pennsylvania, 1995.
Bibliography 121
Sharma, Chandradhar. A Critical Survey of Indian Philosophy, Rider, London,
1960.
Singh, Gopal. The Religions of the Sikhs, Asia Publishing House, Bombay, 1971.
Swami, B. V. Narasimha. Self-Realization: The Life and Teachings of Sri Ramana
Maharshi, Sri RamasramamTiruvannamalai, 1985 [1931].
Zimmer, Heinrich. Philosophies of India, (Edited by Joseph Campbell),
Princeton University Press, New York, 1969.
Index
A
Astika&S
Atman9, 24, 28, 30, 33, 43,99
Advaita Vedanta 10-13
Advaita 18
Antahkarana 21
Anadi 22-23
Asatkaryavada 55
Anavastha 57
Aniruacaniya 69
Avidyd 99
B
Brahmasutra 17, 34
Brahman 19
Brhadaranyaka upani$ad 27
Brereton, J. 40
Buddish 83
Brunton, Paul 104
c
Chandogya Upani$ad 29,35
Causation 53 ff,
Consciousness 70,100-101
Chuanglzu 81
Contradiction 67, 74
D
Darsana 6,8
ZM 72-73,86
Drsya 72 - 73
Descartes 80
Dress metaphor 89 - 94
Dreaming 80 ff
Deep sleep 85 - 86
E
Edgerton, Franklin 42
Experience 79 ff
Existence 62
Experential approach 79 ff
Exbree, Ainslie 30
F
Falsification 74,76
Five sheaths 29,94
Father and Son 36
Fire 28
God 31,100
G
Gargi 26 - 27
Guru Arsun 84
Gandharas 42
Gandharvas 26
H
Hiriyanna, M 31, 48, 58
124
Advaita Vedanta
Hume 72
History 10
Hinduism 6
I
I-Th ought 90 - 92
India 3
Islam 4
Identity-cum-Difference 57 - 59
J
Jivanmukti 4 - 5
Jiva 19, 20, 24, 34,45
JIvatman 21
Janaka27, 81
Jivanmukla 74
Jnana 104
K
Karma 22
Kosa 94
Krishnamurti 104
King 81,83
L
Liiiga 35
Life-Its Three States 79 - 80
Logic 79 - 80
Laya 95
Limitations 20
M
Mahavakya 18 ff.
Mandukya Upanisad 29
Mimamsa 35
Materialism 46,48
Maya. 45,99
Mueller, Max 6
N
Nityata24
Nine Schools 6
Niyati 24
Name and Form 36, 39
o
Organ, Troy Wilson 32
Otto, Rudolph 33
Ocean, Mataphor of 38
Origin of Karma 22
P
Pascal 81
Parinama 23, 55
Pramanas 35
Prakrti9
Q
Questioning 26 - 28
Quantity 62
Quality 46,57
Questions in Advaita Vedanta 13
Qur'an 7
R
Religion and Philosophy 3 - 4
Ramakrsna 83,100
Ramana Maharsi 84, 86 - 88, 93, 95,
96,101
Rational Approach 53 ff
Rationality 79
Ramanuja 45
Index
125
s
V
Sankara 18,44,47,63,65,68,69,75
Vedanta 11
.Sal 20
Vedas 12
Samsara 22
Vikdra 61-62
Sadlihga 35
Vivaria 23
Qi'otnl/otn A A
k_» » V- IU1\V- tu »/ X X
T ~ on
V ISlflU
Saccidananda 48
Vivekananda 100
Satkaryavada 55, 76
Sdthkhya 55
w
Sattd 67, 75
West 4-5
Samadhi 75, 95
World 68
Saksi 86
Worlds 26-27
Scriptural Approach 17 ff
Waking State 89 - 80
T
Taittiriya Upani$ad 29
Time and Eternity 24
Truth 43
Text and Interpretation 34 ff
U
Upanisads 12,17,25,28
Upadhi 20-21
Uddalaka 35
Upapatti 35
X
X and Y 59
X substance 67
Y
Yajnavalkya 26 - 28
Yoga 4, 6
z
Zimmer, Heinrich 39
Arvind Sharma is the
Birks Professor of
Comparative Religion in
the faculty of Religious
Studies at McGill
University; and was the
first Infinity Foundation Visiting
Professor of Indie Studies at Harvard
University. His previous works on
Advaita Vedanta include: The
Experiential Dimension of Advaita Vedanta
(1993); The Philosophy of Religion and
Advaita Vedanta (1995); and The Rope
and the Snake: A Metaphorical Exploration
of Advaita Vedanta (1997).
He lives in Montreal, Canada.
The history of the Vedanta school is well-known since the time of
Sankara but its prehistory before Sankara is quite obscure. However,
there is a period of a thousand years between the compilation of
the major Upanisads to Sankara without loss of the tradition of the
Upanisads; there appeared many philosophers and dogmaticians,
although their thoughts are not clearly known.
The author made clear the details of the pre-Sankara Vedanta
philosophy, utilizing not only Sanskrit materials, but also Pali, Prakrit
as well as Tibetan and Chinese sources. In this respect, this epoch-
making work was awarded the Imperial Prize by the Japan Academy.
Parts One and Two will be important literature indispensable
not only to those, who are specialists in the study of Vedanta but
also to those engaged in the study of Indian thought in general.
Part Two is a complete English translation of Vols. Ill and IV of
the Japanese version, with many additions and revisions done by
the author himself.
This is a unique work discussing the teachings of four of the great
Advaita Acaryas: Gaudapada, Sankara, and his two disciples,
Suresvara and Padmapada.
The author combines close textual scholarship with the
perspective of one is a teacher (Acarya) within the tradition of
Advaita. This work will prove useful for the student who wishes to
obtain clear and detailed information about these four Acaryas, and
it will also be of value to one who is seeking to develop their own
spirituality within the Advaita tradition.
E-mail: mlbd@vsnl.com
Website: www.mlbd.com
Rs. 295 Code: 20274
1S BN 81-208-2027-4