2021/10/11

10] A History of Christian Thought Paul Tillich Ch 4 The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis

 A History of Christian Thought: From its Judaic and Hellenistic Origins to Existentialism by Paul Tillich | Goodreads





A History of Christian Thought: From its Judaic and Hellenistic Origins to Existentialism

by
Paul Tillich,
Carl E. Braaten (Editor)
4.17 · Rating details · 245 ratings · 14 reviews
Previously published in two separate volumes entitled 
A history of Christian thought and Perspectives on 19th and 20th century Protestant theology.

Paperback, 550 pages
Published November 15th 1972 by Touchstone 
(first published January 1st 1968)
====
URL  http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Paul_Tillich

====

 The Concept of Dogma xxxvi

I]The Preparation for Christianity 1
A. The Kairos 1
B. The Universalism of the Roman Empire 2
C. Hellenistic Philosophy 3
1. Skepticism 3
2. The Platonic Tradition 6
3. The Stoics 7
4. Eclecticism 9
D. The Inter-Testamental Period 9
E. The Mystery Religions 13
F. The Method of the New Testament 14

II Theological Developments in the Ancient Church 17
A. The Apostolic Fathers 17
B. The Apologetic Movement 24
1. The Christian Philosophy 27
2. God and the Logos 29
C. Gnosticism 33
D. The Anti-Gnostic Fathers 37
1. The System of Authorities 38
2. The Montanist Reaction 40
3. God the Creator 41
4. The History of Salvation 43
5. Trinity and Cliristology 46
6. The Sacrament of Baptism 48
E. Neo-Platonism 50
F. Clement and Origen of Alexandria 55
1. Christianity and Philosophy 55
2. The Allegorical Method 57
3. The Doctrine of God 59
vi Contents
4. Christology 61
5. Eschatology 63
G. Dynamic and Modalistic Monarchianism 64
1. Paul of Samosata 65
2. Sabellius 66
H. The Trinitarian Controversy 68
1. Arianism 69
2. The Council of Nicaea 71
3. Athanasius and Marcellus 73
4. The Cappadocian Theologians 76
I. The Christological Problem 79
1. The Antiochean Theology 80
2. The Alexandrian Theology 84
3. The Council of Chalcedon 86
4. Leontius of Byzantium 88
J. Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite 90
K. Tertullian and Cyprian 98
'L. The Life and Thought of Augustine 103
1. The Development of Augustine 104
2. Augustine's Epistemology 111
3. The Idea of God 115
4. The Doctrine of Man 119
5. Philosophy of History 121
6. The Pelagian Controversy 122
7. The Doctrine of the Church 131

III Trends in the Middle Ages 134
A. Scholasticism, Mysticism, Biblicism 135
B. The Scholastic Method 137
C. Trends in Scholasticism 140
1. Dialectics and Tradition 140
2. Augustinianism and Aristotelianism 141
3. Thomism and Sootism 141
4. Nominalism and Realism 142
5. Pantheism and Church Doctrine 144
D. The Religious Forces 145
E. The Medieval Church 149
F. The Sacraments 154
G. Anselm of Canterbury 158
H. Abelard of Paris 167
I. Bernard of Clairvaux 172
J. Joachim of Floris 175

K. The Thirteenth Century 180
L. The Doctrines of Thomas Aquinas 192
M. William of Ockham 198
N. German Mysticism 201
0. The Pre-Reformers 203

IV Roman Catholicism from Trent to the Present 210
A. The Meaning of Counter-Reformation 210
B. The Doctrine of Authorities 211
C. The Doctrine of Sin 212
D. The Doctrine of Justification 213
E. The Sacraments 215
F. Papal Infallibility 218
C. Jansenism 221
II. Probahilism 223
1 11ccent Developments 224

V Ilir Iiiiiiigy iI Ihi Protestant Reformers 227
/\ Niiiiiiii I .iitIiii 227
I. Tho Itrukt Iiroiigii 227
2. I ,iiIlii'i ( iilirisrn of the Church 234
:i. I lh ( oiilIlit vlIIi iiiis,niis 237
I. Ilk Coidlicl wit ii tile Ivangelical Radicals 239
5. liii liii N I )O(t rules 242
a. iiie iihiical Principle 242
b. Sin and Faith 245
c. The Idea of God 247
d. The Doctrine of Christ 249
e. Church and State 251
B. Huldreich Zwingli 256
C. John Calvin 262
1. The Majesty of God 262
2. Providence and Predestination 264
3. The Christian Life 270
4. Church and State 272
5. The Authority of Scripture 274

VI The Development of Protestant Theology 276
A. The Period of Orthodoxy 276
1. Reason and Revelation 278
2. The Formal and Material Principles 280
B. Pietism 283
C. The Enlightenment 287

PART II
Introduction: Problem and Method 297

I Oscillating Emphases in Orthodoxy, Pietism,
and Rationalism 305
A. The Period of Orthodoxy 305
B. The Reaction of Pietism against Orthodoxy 311
C. The Rise of Rationalism 313

II The Enlightenment and its Problems 320
A. The Nature of Enlightenment 320
1. The Kantian Definition of Autonomy 320
2. Concepts of Reason 325
a. Universal Reason 326
b. Critical Reason 327
c. Intuitive Reason 328
d. Technical Reason 329
3. The Concept of Nature 330
4. The Concept of Harmony 332
B. The Attitude of the Enlightened Man 341
1. His Bourgeois Character 341
2. His Ideal of a Reasonable Religion 342
3. His Common-sense Morality 344
4. his Subjective Feeling 348
C. Intrinsic Conflicts of Enlightenment 349
1. Cosmic Pessimism 350
2. Cultural Vices 352
3. Personal Vices 353
4. Progress Based on Immorality 355
D. The Fulfillers and Critics of Enlightenment 356
1. Rousseau, The French Revolution, and Romanticism 356
1. Hume, The History of Religion, and Positivism 357
1. Kant, Moral Religion, and Radical Evil 360

III The Classic-Romantic Reaction against the
Enlightenment 367
A. Lessing, Historical Criticism, and the Rediscovery of Spinoza 367
B. The Synthesis of Spinoza and Kant 370

C. The Nature of Romanticism 372
1. The Infinite and Finite 372
2. The Emotional and the Aesthetic Elements in Romanticism 378
3. The Turn to the Past and the Valuation of Tradition 379
4. The Quest of Unity and Authority 382
5. The Negative and the Demonic in Romanticism 383

D. The Classical Theological Synthesis: Friedrich Schleiermacher 386
1. The Background of Schleicrmacher's Thought 388
2. His Concept of Religion as Feeling 391
3. His Positivistic Definition of Theology 398
4. His Interpretation of Christianity 405

E. The Universal Synthesis: Georg W. F. Hegel 410
1. The Greatness and the Tragic Hybris of Ilegels System 411
2. The Synthesis of God and Man (Mind and Person) 414
3. The Synthesis of Religion and Culture (Thought and  Imagination) 419
1. The Synthesis of State and Church 424
Providence, History, and Theodicy 426
The Christ as Reality and Symbol 430
Eternity against Immortality 431


IV The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis 432

A. The Split in the Hegelian School 432
1. The Historical Problem: Strauss and Baur 423
1. The Anthropological Problem: Ludwig Feuerbach 435

B. Schelling's Criticism of Hegel 437

C. The Religious Revival and Its Theological Consequences 448
1. The Nature of the European Revival 449
2. The Theology of Repristination 453
1. Natural Science and the Fight over Darwinism 454

D. Kierkegaard's Existential Theology 458
1. Kierkegaard's Criticism of Hegel 460
2. Ethical Existence and the Human Situation (Anxiety, Despair) 462
3. The Nature of Faith (The Leap and Existential Truth) 464
4.  Criticism of Theology and Church 472

E. Political Radicalism and its Theological Significance 476
1. The Bourgeois Radicals 477
2. Marx's Relation to Hegel and Feuerbach 478
3. Marx's View of the Human Situation (Alienation) 480
4. Marx's Doctrine of Ideology and His Attack on Religion 481
5. Marx's Political Existentialism 484
6.    The Prophetic Element in Marx 485

F. Voluntarism and the Philosophy of Life 487
1. Schopenhatier's Idea of the Will 488
2. Nietzsche's Idea of Will-To-Power 493
3. Nietzsche's Doctrine of Resentment 494
1. The "Death of God" and the New Ideal of Man 497

V New Ways of Mediation 504
A. Experience and the Biblical Message 506
1. The Erlangen School 506
2. Martin Kähler 509
B. The "Back to Kant" Movement 511
C. Adolf von Harnack 515
D. Miscellaneous Movements in Theology 520
1. The Luther-Renaissance 520
2. Biblical Realism 520
3. Radical Criticism 521
4. Rudolf Bultmann 523
5. The History-of-Religions Approach 524
6. Ernst Troeltsch 526
7. Religious Socialism 530
8. Karl Barth 535
9. Existentialism 539
Index of Names 543
Index of Subjects 547
===

CHAPTER IV The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis

have shown you the parts which were brought into Hegel's great synthesis. I did not go into the several philosophical elements, how much of Kantianism, how much of Spinozism, how much of the Goethe-Schelling dynamic transformation of Spinoza, how much of Romanticism, etc., are to be found in Hegel. They are all there. But for the purposes of this course I dealt predominantly with the synthesis so far as it had a bearing on the Christian tradition. I have tried to stress how important it was for him to try to create this synthesis. It is a ques­tion which is still with us. Can we be schizophrenic forever, living with a split consciousness? Can we be split between the Christian tradition, on the one hand, and the creative concepts and symbols of the modern mind, on the other hand? If that is impossible, how is a genuine syn­thesis possible? After the breakdown of Hegel's synthesis numerous new attempts were made to reconstruct a synthesis, all of them dependent on Hegel, but none possessing the universality and historical power of Hegel's system.

A. THE SPLIT IN THE HEGELIAN SCHOOL

How did the split in Hegel's school take place? Hegel's interpretation of Christ took for granted the historical reality of the biblical image of the Christ. He did not doubt it. His interpretation also stressed the symbolic meaning of the universal essential unity between God and

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   433

man. So his interpretation included both reality and symbol. Something happened, however, which seemed to undercut the historical side of that interpretation. The question arose: Can we rely on the historical reports concerning the Christ? Such historical criticism was much older than the period in which Hegel lived. Historical criticism existed since the deistic movement in England, and since the eighteenth-century conflict between rationalism and supernaturalism. But now a new element was introduced by Hegel.

1. The Historical Problem: Strauss and Baur

In the eighteenth century the question was whether the reports about the life of Jesus were true or false. The Christian theologians were bent on showing that much of the historical material could be vindicated in face of historical criticism. Some of the critics tried to show that almost nothing remains as historically reliable. Others argued on the basis of Hegel's point of view that even though the reports are not historically reliable, they do not for that reason lose their religious value. It does not matter if there is so much uncertainty regarding the biblical records of the life of Jesus, they may nevertheless have symbolic value. The concept of symbol came from Schelling and Hegel, and was not intended to prejudice the historical question. It was simply a different kind of language from ordinary empirical language.

David Friedrich Strauss (1808-1874) drew out all the consequences from previous historical criticism when he wrote his Life of Jesus (1835).' It came like lightning and thunder striking the great synthesis ad all those who felt safe in it. Strauss showed that the authors of the Gospels were not those traditionally thought to be the authors. But more, he tried to show that the stories of the birth and the resurrection of Jesus are symbols expressing the eternal identity of what is essential in Jesus and God. This was felt as a tremendous shock. For decades later scholars tried to refute Strauss's Life of Jesus, and, of course, there were many points in it that proved to be invalid in the light of more research.

1 The Life of Jesus, Critically Examined, translated from the 4th German edi­tion by George Eliot (London: Chapman Brothers, 1846).

434            A History of Christian Thought

But the problem which Strauss raised to the fore in the life of the church could never be removed.

A footnote on Strauss's later development: It contains something tragic. Later he wrote another Life of Jesus,2 this one for the German people, as he said. Here he developed the typical world view of the victorious bourgeoisie, not of the great aggressive bourgeoisie of the eighteenth century, but of the positivistic materialistic bourgeoisie which had become victorious in the nineteenth century, and which he represented. This is characterized by a calculating attitude toward the world, a basic materialistic interpretation of reality, and moral rules derived from the bourgeois Conventions. I mention this because of the tremendous attack which Friedrich Nietzsche made against Strauss in the name of the forces of creative life. He attacked this bourgeoisie resting undisturbed in its own finitude.

This has a lot to do with Gospel criticism, for from his bourgeois point of view Strauss eliminated the in-breaking of the divine into the human, of the infinite into the finite. The infinite was adapted to the finite. The image of Christ which Strauss and many later biographers produced was that of a domesticated divinity, domesticated for the sake of the untroubled life of the bourgeois society in calculating and con­trolling the finite reality. Here Nietzsche was the prophetic victor over Struss, even more than any theologian.

But this was not the end of the story. The development was furthered by a pupil of Hegel, Ferdinand Christian Baur (1792-1860), who founded the Tubingen school which dealt especially with New Testa­ment research. He tried to apply the Hegelian concepts of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis to the early development of Christianity. The thesis was the early Jewish-Christian communities; the antithesis the pagan, Christian, Pauline line of thought (he emphasized very much the struggle between Peter and Paul over the necessity of circumcision, in which Paul prevailed, opening the way for Christianity to conquer the pagan world); the synthesis of the Petrine and the Pauline types of Christianity was the Johannine. In this point Baur was very much in

2Das Leben Jesu für des deutsche Volk bearbeitet (Leipzig: 1864). The English translation is The Life of Jesus for the People (London: Williams and Norgate, 1879).

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis    435

the tradition of classical German philosophy. All of these philosophers, Kant, Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, were great lovers of the fourth Gospel, because of the gnostic terminology in this Gospel, especially the logos term. Baur's interpretation of Christianity was very important and influential, however justifiable or unjustifiable his theory may be from a historical point of view. In the face of the orthodox view of a literally inspired Bible, Baur showed how these biblical writings were created in an historical way. The idea of a creative development which was going on in the church and which produced the Scriptures has changed our whole relation to the Bible. The whole development of historical criticism was later to maintain some form of Baur's sense of the histori­cal emergence of the biblical writings over against the view of a mechanically dictated and inspired Word of God, as if God were dictat­ing to a stenographer at a typewriter.

2. The Anthropological Problem: Ludwig Feuerbach (1804-1872)

It was Feuerbach who launched an anthropological criticism against Hegel's philosophy of religion. He himself was very much influenced by Hegel before turning against him. Hegel had said that man is that being in whom God recognizes himself. In man's knowledge of God, God comes to know himself. There is thus no knowledge of God apart fiom that knowledge of him which is in man. Now Feuerbach, under the influence of Western naturalism,. materialism, and psychologism, said that Hegel must be turned around. God is nothing else than a projection of man's awareness of his own infinity. You see that this is simply turning Hegel upside down. For Hegel God comes to himself in man; for Feuerbach man creates God in himself. These are two quite different views. Here we have Feuerbach's theory of projection. The word "projection" is widely used today. All education deals with methods of projection; Freudian thought interprets God as a human projection, as a father image, etc. But Feuerbach was much profounder. I recommend to all of you who have just discovered Freud's theory of projection to go back to Feuerbach; he had a real theory of projection.

What does projection mean in a technical sense? It means putting an image on a screen. In order to do this, you need a screen. But I always

436            A History of Christian Thought

miss the screen in modern thinking about projection. Granted, God is the projection of the father experience in us; he is the image of it. But why is this image itself God? Who is the screen onto which this image is projected? To this Feuerbach has an answer. He says that man's ex­perience of his infinity, the infinite will to live, the infinite intensity of love, etc., makes it possible for him to have a screen upon which to project images. This, of course, makes sense, and from the point of view of the philosophy of religion one can agree with all projection theories which are as old as Xenophanes, almost six hundred years before Christ. This means that the concrete image, the concrete symbolism applied to the infinite, is determined by our situation and by our relation to our own infinity. This is meaningful. Of course, it is not sufficient, but in any case Fcuerbach saw much better than so many seemingly educated people of today that if you have a theory of projection, you must explain why the images are projected on just this screen, and why the result is something infinite, that is, the divine, the unconditional, the absolute. Where does that come from? The father is not absolute. Nothing that we have in ourselves, in our finite structure, is absolute. Only if there is an awareness of something unconditional or infinite within us can we understand why the projected images have to be divine figures or symbols. So in the terms of the greatest theoreticians of projection, I ci*ticize the modern theories of projection which circulate in popular unreflective thought. Here you have a weapon with which to face this popular talk about projection.

Feuerbach did something here which Marx acknowledged as the final and definitive criticism of religion. We cannot understand Karl Marx without understanding his relation to Feuexbach. He said that Feuer-bach solved the problem of religion once for all. Religion is a projection. It is something subjective in us which we put into the sky of the absolute. But then he went one step beyond Feuerbach. He said that Feuerbach did a great job, but he did not go far enough. He did not explain why projection was done at all, and this, Marx said, cannot be explained in terms of the individual man. This can only be explained in terms of the social existence of men, and more particularly in the class situation of men. Religion is the escape of those who are oppressed by the upper classes into an imaginary fulfillment in the realm of the

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   437

absolute. Marx's negation of religion is a result of his understanding of the social condition of man.

Here you see the great influence these ideas have had. The anti-religious attitude of almost half of present-day mankind is rooted in this seemingly professorial struggle between Hegel, Feuerbach, and Marx, with both of the latter coming from Hegel. Feuerbach turned Hegel upside down, and then Marx introduced the sociological element. The projection of the transcendent world is the projection of the disinherited in this world. This was such a powerful argument that it convinced the masses of people. It took more than one hundred years before the labor movements in Europe were able to overcome this Feuerbach-Marxian argument against Hegel's attempt to unite Christianity and the modern mind.

These people whom I have mentioned are called the Hegelian left wing. Against them stood theologians who belonged to the Hegelian right wing: Marheineke, Biedermann, Pileiderer. They tried to show that it is possible under Hegelian presuppositions to have a tenable and justifiable Christian theology.

B. SCHELLING'S CBITICISM oF HEGEL

We have been discussing some of Hegel's critics, people like Feuer-bach and Marx. I come now to that critic whom I consider to be the most fundamental philosophically and theologically, and perhaps most important for our intellectual life today. The first great existentialist critic of essentialist thinking since Blaise Pascal (1623-1662), who was in a way the predecessor of all existentialists, was Friedrich Schelling (1775-1854). We have to remember that he was prior to Kierkegaard. In fact Kierkegaard attended Schelling's Berlin lectures in the middle of the nineteenth century, and used many of Schelling's categories in his fight against Hegel.

I know that the name of this man Schelling is almost unknown in this country. There are several reasons for this. One of the reasons is that Schelling, together with Fichte, is a bridge between Kant and Hegel. After you have reached the other side of the bridge, you tend

438            A History of Christian Thought

often to forget the bridge itself. Kant is the one who began German classical philosophy, and Hegel is the end. All this happened in no more than half a century. But during this half century Fichte and Schelling were working, first continuing Kant, and then giving basic thoughts to Hegel. Of course, they were not mere bridges between Kant and Hegel. They were independent philosophers having an influence reaching beyond Hegel up to our time. I recall the unforgettable moment when by chance I came into possession of the very rare first edition of the collected works of Schelling in a bookstore on my way to the University of Berlin. I had no money, but I bought it anyway, and this spending of nonexistent money was probably more important than all the other nonexistent or sometimes existing money that I have spent. For what I learned from Schelling became determinative of my own philosophical and theological development.

I have told you already how Schelling synthesized or combined Kant's critical epistemology and Spinoza's mystical ontology. But Schelling as more than this synthess. In some way Goethe did that too. But Schelling became the philosopher of Romanticism. He represented not only the beginning of romantic thinking in the philosophy of nature. There were elements of this already in Fichte and even in Kant's third Critique where he introduced the Gestalt theory of biological under­standing of life. But Schelling kept pace with the different changing periods of Romanticism, and the decisive turning point was when Romanticism started to become existentialism. In this sense Schelling is far more than a bridge between Kant and Hegel. Long after Hegel's death, he was the greatest critic of Hegel. In Schelling the second phase of Romanticism became existentialist. He arrived finally at an under­standing of reality which radically contradicted his former period. This happened through philosophical experiences, understanding of religion, and profound participation in life within himself and around him. He did not, however, abolish what Hegel and he had done before. He preserved a philosophy of essence. Against this he put the philosophy of existence. Existentialism is not a philosophy which can stand on its own legs. Actually it has no legs. It is always based on a vision of the essential structure of reality. In this sense it is based on essentialism, and cannot live without it. If you say that man is evil, you must have a, concept of

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   439

man in his essential goodness, otherwise the word "evil" would not make any sense. Without the distinction between good and evil the words themselves lose their meaning. And if you say that man's structure is distorted in time and space, or that it is "fallen," then you must have something from which he is fallen. You must have some structure which is distorted in time and space. So mere existentialism does not exist. But it can be the main emphasis of a philosophical work and even of a whole period in philosophy. In Schelling's later years it was the main em­phasis, although essentialism was presupposed, but not developed. This is also true of our philosophers and poets. I can best illustrate this in terms of the present-day saint of existentialism, the novelist Kafka. In him you will not find that essentialism is explained, but you will always find that it is implicit and presupposed. For without this he could not even describe the futile search for meaning in the novel, The Castle, or the horrible experience of a guilt of which he is not conscious in his other novel, The Trial. The essentialist understanding of the human situation is behind it, behind the existentialist description. You find this everywhere. If in T. S. Eliot you have the age of anxiety described, this presupposes the possibility of not having anxiety in the radical sense in which he describes it. Thus all existentialism presupposes that from which it breaks away, namely, essentialism. You have it wonderfully expressed in Pascal who relates the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob to both man's greatness and his misery.

Now in his earlier periods, Schelling developed to the extreme the Spinozistic principle, the principle of the ontological unity of every­thing in the eternal substance. This principle of identity is very hard to understand by people educated in nominalistic thinking, as you all are, Whether you know it or not. The nominalistic mind is a mind which sees particulars and relations of particulars, and which uses exclusively logical and scientific methods to get at particulars. The very question of an ultimate identity is very difficult to comprehend. But at least one historical fact should be realized, namely, that by far the greatest part of mankind is not nominalistic, that all Asian religions are based on the principle of identity, and that Greek philosophy from the very be­ginning started with it when Parmenides said, "Where there is being, there is also the logos of being." This means that the word can grasp

440           A History of Christian Thought

being, that the rational structure makes it possible for us to speak about being, and we can use words meaningfully.

Now this fundamental principle underlies the whole history of Christian thought. All the church fathers presupposed this Parmenidean idea, only enriching it by trinitarian symbolism. Where God is, there is his Logos, and they are one in the dynamic creativity of the Spirit. It is a necessary idea because it explains something which all thinking pre­supposes. The presupposition is that there is truth and that truth can be reached by us. In order to have truth, in order to make a true judgment; the subject who makes the judgment and the thing about which the judgment is made must, so to speak, be at one and the same place. They must come together. We use the word "grasp" for this. You must "grasp" the structure of reality. But in order to reach the object, there must be a fundamental belongingness of the subject to the object. This is the one side of the principle of identity, namely, that subject and object are not absolutely separated, that although they are separated in our finite existence, they belong essentially together. There is an eternal unity between them.

The other side of the concept of identity is the problem of the one and the many. This is the great Platonic problem. How is it possible that the many are diverse, but nevertheless form the unity of a cosmos, of a world, of a universe? Even in the word "universe" the word "one" is contained. How is that possible? Again the answer is that there must be an original unity of the one and the many. The principle of identity says that the one substance—Spinoza calls it substance, a very power­ful and originally Aristotelian and Scholastic term—makes togetherness possible in the same time and the same space. Without the one sub­stance there could not be causal connections between things, and there couldn't be substantial union and separation of different substances. This latter point is emphasized especially in the Asian religions. I remember a really Spinozistic argument used by a high priest in a Buddhist monastery. In discussing the question of how community is

possible between human beings, he said that if every human being has his own substance, then community is impossible. They are eternally

separated. I answered that human community is possible only if indi­viduals have their independent substance—substance means, of course, standing upon oneself—otherwise there is no community, but only

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   441

identity. 'Where there is no separation, there is no community either. It was with this argument that I left Japan, in the last important discus­sion I had there.

The philosophers of identity argued that there must be an underlying identity. I would never deny this, for if we were absolute strangers to each other, if there were no element of identity in the common sub­stance of our being human, we could not speak to each other. We would not be able to have any form of community. It is the emphasis on diversity which separates the Western from the Eastern world. It was of the greatest importance that Christianity came from Judaism. In Juda­ism the individual personality has personal responsibility before the eternal God, and is not dissolved into the identity of everything as in Asia.

These problems in the history of religion are also the problems which preoccupied a philosopher like Schelling. Under the influence of Spinoza he was grasped by the one substance, by that which is beyond subject and object, beyond spirit and matter. His whole philosophy of nature was an attempt to show the indwelling of the potential spirit in all natural objects and how it comes to its fulfillment in man. The romantic philosophy of nature is nothing else than a carrying out of the program of Nicholas of Cusa, the presence of the infinite in the finite, and the program of Spinoza, the one substance in all its modifications, and Schelling's own program, the presence of the spiritual in the material. Thus the philosophy of nature becomes in Schelling a system of intuitions, in a half-philosophical, half-aesthetic way, of the power of being in nature, a power which is beyond the separation of the spiritual and the material.

Now a modem scientist might say that this is all imagination or aesthetic fancy and has nothing to do with his work. But not all modern scientists would say this. I know scientists in biology and psychology of the Gestalt school who follow in the line of Schelling, although they have to reject his concrete results. In any case Schelling is the initiator of this romantic philosophy of nature, and because of it he became famous in his mid-twenties. At that time he was the most famous of the German philosophers, with the exception of Fichte, and was better known than Hegel who started much later and developed quite slowly.

In Schelling's philosophy nature is construed dynamically and thus

442           A History of Christian Thought

also anti-Spinozistically. In Spinoza nature is presented geometrically whereas in Schelling it is presented partly biologically and partly psychologically. In this construction the process of nature proceeds from the lowest to the highest forms of nature, and finally to man in terms of a contrast of two principles. He called the one principle the unconscious and the other the conscious. He tried to show how slowly in all different forms of nature consciousness develops until it comes to man where it becomes self-consciousness. Then a new development starts, the development of culture and history. Schelling's discovery of the un­conscious was, however, a rediscovery, because the philosophers of nature in the Renaissance, Paraclsus and Boehme, around A.D. 1600 already knew about the unconscious element in man and even applied it to both God and nature.

Many of you probably believe that the unconscious is the discovery of Freud. Freud's merit is not the discovery of this concept, but the application of it in terms of a scientific method derived from medical psychology. The concept itself goes back to Schelling, not directly, but by way of Schopenhauer, the voluntaristic philosopher and critic of Hegel, and by way of Eduard von Hartmann who wrote a whole book on the philosophy of the unconscious. And it is possible to show that this book was known to Freud. This is then one element in Schelling's philosophy of nature which has survived and is still valid. In Kant and Fichte you find the predominance of practical reason, of the moral imperative. Religion is only an appendix to the moral imperative. It is at best a tool to express the unconditional character of the moral impera­tive. The philosophy of Fichte is concerned with the morally deciding self, the ego, the "ich" as he called it, which is completely separate from nature. Nature is only the material which man must use in himself, in his body which is nature, and outside of himself in his surroundings, in order to actualize the moral imperative. Nature has no meaning in itself. So here with a kind of holy wrath Schelling turned against Fichte and said, "It is a blasphemy of the Creator to think that nature is only there in order to be the material for our moral glory; nature has the divine glory in itself." In this way he was brought to the philosophy of nature.

But there is an even deeper consequence of this term. This is the turn toward the concept of grace over against the concept of law. If nature,

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis    443

which makes no conscious decision and has no moral imperative, has within itself the divine presence, then the divine presence is not only dependent on our moral action. It is prior in the development of reality, and it is also subsequent to our moral action. It is below and above the moral imperative. Schelling's philosophy or theology was very much a doctrine of grace, stressing the given divine reality before our merits and before our moral acts. So natural philosophy was a way of rediscovering grace over against the moralism of the Enlightenment. This was one of the great achievements of Romanticism for theology. Here I would say that because American Protestantism has never had a romantic period, aside from a few individuals, it has preserved up to today a religion in which the enlightened moralistic attitude is predominant, and the concept of grace is quite strange. The teachings of Jesus are moral or doctrinal laws. You will not hear very much in sermons in this country about the presence of the divine preceding all that we do. Another consequence of this is the disappearance of sacramental feeling. Sacra­mental thinking is meaningful only if the infinite is present in the finite, if the finite is not only subject to the commands of the infinite but has in itself saving powers, powers of the presence of the divine. This is a rediscovery of Romanticism. Of course, it was present in the whole sac­ramental experience of the early church, but to a great extent it was lost in the Reformation criticism, and then finally lost in the Enlightenment which based itself only on the imperative.

So now we have a whole new vision based on the principle of identity. Later Schelling went beyond the philosophy of nature to a philosophical understanding of reality through the arts. The aesthetic element broke through in full power. During his period of aesthetic idealism he made the arts the substitute for religion. Artistic intuition is the way in which we see God. The divine comes to us through the arts. Neither the biblical miracles nor any other are the manifestation of God, but every work of art is the great miracle of the full revelation of the divine substance.

After Schelling had become famous for his philosophy of nature, then developed his philosophy of aesthetic intuition, he finished this period by something which he called the philosophy of identity. Here the principle which was underlying all his periods was expressed, not in

444           A History of Christian Thought

a geometrical but in a logical way, and in a way which was the extreme fulfillment of what Spinoza intended. This represented the end of essentialism in Schelling's development. For Schelling 1809 was an important year because of the death of Caroline Schlegel, the wife of his friend Schlegel, the famous translator of Shakespeare. Schelling married her. She was one of the great women of Romanticism. Her letters are a classical document of that period. Her premature death was a tremendous catastrophe for Schelling. Shortly after this two things came out. One was the dialogue Clara in which he used the Platonic form of the dialogue to develop the idea that eternal life means the essentialization of what we are in our essential being as seen by God. It is not a continuation of existence in time and space but participation in eternity with what we are essentially. But more important for the history of man's spiritual life was his writing on human freedom.3 This is probably his most important work because here the concept of freedom breaks into the concept of identity. Freedom, of course, presupposes the possibility of choice. Identity as such is eternally fulfilled. So David Friedrich Strauss could say of Schelling that the principle of freedom drove him out of the restfulness of the principle of identity, which was spelled out in his System of Philosophy, as he called it. Here he had spoken like Spinoza of the eternal restfulness, not running for a purpose, but receiving the power of being directly by contemplation.

But then something happened. If you read the two books, The System of Philosophy, which is his philosophy of identity, and then Of Human Freedom, you feel that you have entered a new world. What had happened was his personal experience of the death of Caroline. But the logic of thought also played a part, the necessity of explaining manifoldness and diversity, and life itself which goes out of identity into alteration and wants to return to itself. How could this be explained? How can we explain that we are living here in time and space in continuous action, as we do, if there is an eternal ground in which the substance which is in all of us lies in eternal rest. The explanation was given in terms of freedom. Freedom breaks gut of identity. Here he used

Friedrich W. J. Schelling, Of Human Freedom, translated by James Gutman (Chicago The Open Court Publishing Co., 1936).

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis    445

the imagery of his philosophy of nature. He construed two or three principles in the ground of the divine, the unconscious or dark princi­ple, the principle of will which is able to contradict itself, on the one hand, and the principle of logos, or the principle of light, on the other hand. There is here the possibility that the unconscious will, the drive in the depths of the divine life, might break away from the identity. But it cannot do so in the divine life itself. The spiritual unity of the two principles keeps them always together. But in man, in the creature, it can break away. In the creature freedom can turn against its own divine substance, its own divine ground. So the myth of the fall is interpreted by him, following the line of Plato, through Origen and Boehme, as the transcendent fall. The fall is not something which happened once upon a time, but something which happens all the time, in all creatures. This fall is the breaking away from the creative ground from which we come in the power of freedom.

This was expressed by Schelling in terms of the problem of good and evil. He showed that the possibility of good and evil is given in God. Evil is possible because the will in the divine ground is able to contra­dict itself. But in God it never comes to a disruption. Only the free decision of the creature to turn against its created ground accounts for evil. The principles are eternally in union in God, the abysmal depth in the divine life, the prerational development of the will, the principle of the logos or light or reason or structure or meaning, and their unity which he calls the spirit. These three principles are in the divine life, but in the divine life the finite which is present is unable to break away. The unity of the principles can be disrupted only in creatures. This is something which you can find in empirical terminology in Freud and in every modern psychotherapeutic book of profound formulations. You can find it most openly expressed in Jung's writings, and more hiddenly in Freud when he speaks of eros and thanatos, love and death. In Schelling it appeared in the highest abstraction in the fundamental vision of the nature of the will in relation to the nature of the structure. If you run ahead into the nineteenth century, you will discover the influence of these ideas everywhere. The whole of French voluntarism up to Bergson was dependent on these ideas; in Germany Schopen-hauer and Nietzsche were equally dependent on them, and they have

446            A History of Christian Thought

had a great effect on the philosophy of Whitehead up to the present time, especially in Charles Hartshorne, the main representative of the Whiteheadian school. So these ideas have had a great influence on history-making personalities.

The influence on theology was not less decisive. Some of the great theologians in the nineteenth century worked in the line of Schelling. But Schelling never rested. After this breakthrough he became silent for many years. In his old age he was called to Berlin in order to fight against the left-wing Hegelians. Many important people attended these lectures in the middle of the nineteenth century. The most important was Soren Kierkegaard, a transcription of whose notes on Schelling's Berlin lectures is to be found in the Copenhagen library in Denmark. This latest period reflected in Schelling's Berlin lectures is a tragic period. These lectures were prematurely published by an enemy of his and, of course, poorly published, which made him many critics, some of them even contemptuous of his work. But what he did is nevertheless worthy of careful study because there is hardly one category in twentieth-century existentialist poetry, literature, philosophy, and in­directly the visual arts, which you cannot find in these lectures. They are to be found in the last four volumes of his collected works. And when people like Friedrich Trendelenburg (1802-1872) and Kierke-gaard criticized Hegel's logic, and his confusion of dialectics and history, they were doing what Schelling had done more fully in his latest works.

In these latest writings you will find a distinction between two types of philosophy, negative and positive philosophy. Negative philosophy is philosophy of identity or essentialism. He called it negative because it abstracts from the concrete situation as all science has to do. it does not imply a negative evaluation of this philosophy, but refers to the method of abstraction. You abstract from the concrete situation until you come to the essential structures of reality, the essence of man, the essence of animals, the essence of mind, of body, etc. Negative philosophy deals with the realm of ideas, as Plato called it. But negative philosophy does not say anything about what is positively given. The essence of man does not say anything about the fact that man does exist in time and space. The term "positive philosophy" expresses the same thing that we call existentialism today. It deals with the positive, the actual situation

The Breakdown of the tlniversa! Synthesis   447

in time and space. This is not possible without the negative side, the essential structure of reality. There could not be a tree if there were not the structure of treehood eternally even before trees existed, and even after trees go out of existence on earth altogether. The same is true of man. The essence of man is eternally given before any man appeared on earth. It is potentially or essentially given, but it is not actually or existentially given. So here we are at a great turning point of philo­sophical thinking. Now Schelling as a philosopher described man's existential situation. We are then in the second period of Romanticism. The unconscious has pushed toward the surface. The demonic elements in the underground of life and of human existence have become manifest. This can even be called a kind of empiricism. Schelling some­times called it higher empiricism, higher because it takes things not simply in terms of their scientific laboratory appearances, but in correla­tion with their essential nature. Thus he arrives at all these categories now current in existentialist literature. We have the problem of anxiety dealt with, the problem of the relation between the unconscious and the conscious, the problem of guilt, the problem of the demonic, etc. Here the observation of things, and not the development of their rational structure, becomes decisive.

What is said against much of twentieth-century existentialism can be said of his philosophy. It is pessimistic. But the term "pessimism" should be avoided because that refers to an emotional reaction. Philosophy cannot be pessimistic. Only a perscin can be pessimistic in his psycho-logical

sychological attitude. This philosophy describes the situation, the conflict between essence and existence, and this conflict is expressed in the concepts of existentialist literature.

But Schelling not only asks the existentialist questions; he also tries to give religious answers to them. This he does in terms of the classical Christian tradition. He is much nearer to Orthodoxy, whereas Kierke-gaard is nearer to Pietism and the theology of revivalism, if we can use that term. In any case, for Schelling it is Lutheran Orthodoxy which offers the answers to the existentialist questions. This answer is given in a powerful vision of the history of religion. Here he has given a key, to me and many others, to the meaning of the history of religion. The history of religion cannot simply be explained in psychological terms. It

448            A History of Christian Thought

has to do with powers of reality which grasp the unconscious, or which come out of the unconscious and grasp the consciousness of men and produce the symbolism in the history of religion. Of course, he had to use the limited knowledge available to him at that time about the history of religion. He knew much more of this than Hegel, and was himself responsible for the later intensive development in the religious-historical studies of Friedrich Muller (1823-1900), But what Schelling did know was interpreted by him not in terms of meaningless imagina­tion or in terms of subjective psychological projection, but in terms of powers of being which grasp the human mind itself. These go through man's psyche, his soul, through his conscious and unconscious mind, but they do not derive from it. They come from the roots men have in the depths of reality itself.

So the different types of religions express the different powers of being by which men are grasped. The terrible sacrifices in religion, the tremendous seriousness in the history of religions, the fact that religion is the most glorious and the most cruel part of man's history, all this is understandable only if religion is not a matter of wishful thinking, but is a matter of powers of being which men encounter. In this light he explains the inner struggle, the terrible struggles in the history of religion.

This brings my consideration of Schelling to an end. You see that he can be considered the main and the most powerful critic of Hegel, not a critic who breaks out into a merely naturalistic or secularistic opposition to the great synthesis, but one who offers motives for a new synthesis on the basis of his criticism.

C. THE RELIGIOUS REVIVAL AND ITS THEOLOGICAL CONSEQUENCES

Most of the theological movements in the nineteenth century began as critical theology, critical of the great synthesis. Theologies and philos­ophies do not fall like hailstones from heaven, but are prepared in the movement of history, and in all the realms of this movement, sociologi­cal, political, as well as religious. Now I come to the religious back­ground of the conservative criticism of Hegel.

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis    449

1. The Nature of the European Revival

There was around 1830 a movement called the "awakening move-ment"4 which swept throughout Europe like a storm. It was not confined to Europe, for at about the same time there was the revivalist movement in America. It touched Fiance, Germany, and Switzerland. In England it was somehow connected with the revival of the Catholic element in the Church of England. Everywhere individuals and small groups were grasped by a new understanding of the problem of human existence and the meaning of the Christian message for them. Usually they would gather around the Bible in small groups. This movement was not restricted to any special sociological groups, although by this time the labor movement was heading in a different direction. It was very strongly represented among the landed aristocracy in East Germany and in Europe generally, among the small peasants in southwestern Germany, and among bourgeois people in other European countries; it was often connected with romantic reactions against the Enlightenment; it was rooted in what I would call the law of nature, valid in both physical and spiritual dimensions, the law, namely, that there can be no vacuum, no void. Where there is an empty space, it will be filled. The Enlightenment with its consequences, especially its materialistic trends in France and later in Germany, created a feeling of a vacuum in the spiritual life. The preaching of the Enlightenment was a kind of lectur­ing on all possible subjects, agricultural, technical, political, or psycho­logical, but the dimension of the ultimate was lacking. So into this empty space an intense pietistic movement stressing conversion entered and filled it with a warm spirit of vital piety. When I began my studies in the University of Halle in 1904, now in the East Zone of Germany, I was a pupil of the greatest personality of this faculty, Martin Kähler. He was an unusual personality, standing within the classic-romantic tradition. He told us that when he was a young man he knew his Goethe by heart. He was filled with the traditions of German classical poetry, literature, and philosophy. Then this movement of revivalism grasped him, and he was converted in the literal sense of "being turned

In German, die Er-weckungsbewegung.

450            A History of Christian Thought

around." He became a biblical theologian with the highest spiritual power over us. There in Halle one could see the influence of this movement. In the student corporations at the University—what are called fraternities here—the leading activities centered around dueling and drinking. Revivalism changed all this. Some fraternities were set up on definitely Christian principles, forbidding excessive drinking and dueling between students. This was the great side in the revivalist movement. This was still visible in the fraternity of which I became a member in 1904. The Christian principles were taken in utter serious­ness. One of the most common topics of discussion was: Can you be a member of such a group if you are in doubt? In one of the meetings of all the Christian fraternities all over Germany and Switzerland I formulated the statement that the foundation is not dependent on us, but on the Christian principle. The individual person doubts, or he does not doubt, and his doubt might even be very radical, but if he takes very seriously the problem of his doubt and his faith, and struggles with the problem of the loss of faith in him, then he is a member of our frater­nity. Ever since as a professor of theology I have told my students that faith embraces itself and the doubt about itself. Younger and older ministers have had to be told the same thing. When Martin Kahler was in his seventies and lecturing on the principle of justification by grace through faith, he told us: Do not think that at my age one becomes a fully serene, mature, believing, and regenerated human being. The inner struggle is going on to the last day no matter how old one becomes. This means that his pietism was not a perfectionist pietism, as it often became on Calvinist soil. Rather it was a typically Lutheran type of pietism in which the paradox of justification by grace through faith, Cod's acceptance of the unacceptable ones, is a fundamental principle.

So here is a motive for theology which looks a bit different from others we have discussed. Out of this some interesting things came. In this second wave of pietism, as in the first one (cf. Zinzendorf and the Moravians, the Wesley brothers and the Methodists) the missionary interest became important. It is interesting that in both the original pietist reaction against Orthodoxy and the second pietist reaction against the Enlightenment there arose a renewed missionary zeal. In the power

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   451

of their experience those grasped by the revivalist movements wanted to communicate that power to paganism all over the world. So in the thirties a new theology of missions arose. It was a limited one. The main idea was still as in early pietism to save souls out of all nations. Just as the conversion experience was an individual one, so the missionary activity was individualistic in character. It had the idea of converting as many pagans as possible to rescue them from eternal damnation. There was, however, one new element in the nineteenth-century missionary zeal. It was directed not only to the pagans outside of Christendom, to non-Christians and Jews, but also to those at home. This was home missions or "inner missions," as it was called in Germany. This was particularly interesting because it was connected with a strong feeling of social responsibility for the disinherited people.

The way in which this idea of social responsibility developed was interesting. On Lutheran soil it was impossible to have revolutionary movements as could happen on Calvinist or radical-evangelical soil. Yet, this Lutheran pietism was very much interested in the social conditions of the masses in the beginning of the industrial revolution. But it did not have the revolutionary idea of changing the structure of society. It only worked to help the victims of the social conditions. The revolu­tionary idea was taken over by the socialists, and later in the twentieth century, by the communists. We find the germ of this revolutionary idea already in Thomas Münzer, the leader of the peasant revolt in the Reformation period. Thomas Münzer is a very interesting phenome­non. He did not say that we must change society as such, but that we must give the poor people who are enslaved in work, day and night without interruption, the possibility of reading the Bible, and of having spiritual experiences, experiences of the Spirit. He had observed in the small towns of Saxony where some early capitalist forms of production were used in the factories that these people had no Sunday, insufficient hours of rest and sleep, no chance for an education, no schools, no reading or writing. His socialist ideas came out of this observation of the spiritual situation of the urban working classes, and of the peasant classes.

The reasoning of the nineteenth-century revivalist movement was the same. The healthy part of society should give help to the sick part. The

452            A History of Christian Thought

sick part is composed of the laboring people who were exploited in those victorious days of a ruthless capitalism. But home mission was still basi­cally conceived of as conversion of those who were estranged from the church. Indeed the laboring masses were completely estranged from the churches. There was no call for revolution. Revolution was out of the question on Lutheran soil. But there was the call to assume the responsibility of helping the other classes to understand spiritual values of which they were being deprived by their life situation. I cannot develop here all the sociological background—the conditions of the agricultural workers, out of which all the city workers originally came, because there was no industry, and when the industry started, they came from the villages, but in the villages the lowest classes were already estranged from the churches, because the churches were always on the side of the upper classes.

This sense of social responsibility was certainly important, but it was not enough. The members of the church were given the feeling that it was enough to exercise personal charity toward unfortunate individuals. This in itself, however, served to estrange church people from a real understanding of the new sociological situation created by the industrial revolution. Therefore, in spite of the feeling of revivalism and social responsibility for the disinherited people, the rise of socialism and communism could not be prevented in Europe, because it was not seen that individual help was entirely fruitless in relation to the masses of industrial workers who soon numbered in the millions. No individual help could possibly cope with this situation.

To anticipate what happened much later, I would like to say a few words about the religious socialist movement of the twentieth century. This movement tried to combine two elements: on the one hand, a sense of social responsibility for the laboring, disinherited masses, which characterized the theology and piety of the awakening movement, and on the other hand, taking seriously the transformed sociological situa­tion, by not thinking only in terms of individual relations, but accepting the analyses of the social situation of the French and German socialists, especially the profoundest of them made by Karl Marx. So the religious socialist movement combined the heritage of nineteenth-century revival­ism and the rise of socialism. When we founded this movement in

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis    453

Germany after the first World War, we were deeply aware that the social attitudes of the revivalist people and of the Ritschlians, who thought on an individualistic basis, were inadequate to the new situation described by the socialist writers as a complete dehumanization, a Verdinglichung, a thingification, an objectification of the masses of people. They were transformed from being persons into being objects of working power which could be bought. They had to sell themselves in order to survive. The quarters in which they lived were not slums in the modem sense, but they were bare of anything human. I remember my horror when I went into the living quarters of the working people in Cities like Berlin or in the Ruhr country where the largest industry is concentrated, and saw the kind of dehumanized existence these people endured. Our response to this situation came in the form of combining the revivalist tradition of social responsibility and the sociological analy­sis of the socialist writers, especially Marx and Engels.

2. The Theology of Repristination

There were still other consequences of the awakening movement, especially a revival of traditional theology. The pupils of Schleier-macher, Hegel, and Schelling had produced a theology of mediation, which combined the rediscovered biblical reality with the concerns of the modern mind. But alongside of this theology of mediation there arose a theology of restoration or of repristination, or as we would call it today, a conservative theology as over against a liberal theology. This repristination theology was a radical return to and rediscovery of the orthodox tradition. The theologians in this movement did not produce many new theological thoughts, but they did one valuable thing for us. They opened up the treasures of classical Orthodoxy. I say this even though I am completely opposed to a theology of repristination, for I wish that every student would learn in Latin the classical formulations of Protestant Orthodox theology. Then he would be as educated as the Roman Catholic theologians who know their Thomas Aquinas or their Suarez or some other classical theologian. Then, of course, one can go beyond that. But to go beyond without having been within Orthodoxy is not a wholesome attitude. But this is what has happened more and

454            A History of Christian Thought

more. So I say now that the one good thing that the theology of re-pristination did for us was to show forth the treasures of the past as matters which still concern us. It still concerns me what Johann Gerhard or other great Protestant scholastics said about a given doctrine. They knew many of our problems and offered solutions which we should not simply forget. Besides, they were not unlearned as our present-day fundamentalists who are direct products of revivalism, but without theological education. It is a fundamentalism based simply on piety and on biblical interpretation which is ignorant of the way in which the Bible was written and came into existence. So you cannot compare classical Orthodoxy with fundamentalism. But in any case, a repristination theology could not last, because history does not run backward but forward.

This restoration theology was an expression of the dissolution of the great synthesis. These forms of Orthodoxy despised what had happened since the Enlightenment. They went back to classical Orthodoxy. They did not accept the historical criticism of the biblical literature. They took the Bible literally. They even believed that the Pentateuch was written by Moses, even though one of the books tells about his death. Such absurdities are always the consequence of the doctrine of literal inspiration. This view could not and did not last. The real bearers of the development in theology were the theologians of mediation, people like Martin Kähler and the theologians of the Ritschlian school.

3. Natural Science and the Fight over Darwinism

Another attack against the great synthesis came from the direction of modern science. Schelling's philosophy of nature and Hegel's mechani­cal application of the categories of man's spirit to nature produced the great reaction of empirical science. Empirical science followed the method of analysis and synthesis, as we have it in the physical sciences, the mathematical structure of nature as a presupposition, the mechani­cal movement as the metaphysical background, the Newtonian ideas about natural laws, in short, a mechanical naturalism in all realms, especially in physics and medicine. This movement came to its direct

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   455

expression in Darwinism, which is worth considering from the point of view of Christian theology.

This mechanical or mechanistic naturalism threatened Christian the­ology and so Christian theology had to do the work of defense.—There are other kinds of naturalism, the vitalistic naturalism of Nietzsche, the dynamic naturalism of Bergson and Whitehead. This mechanistic natu­ralism we sometimes call materialistic, but the term "materialism" itself has three different meanings, so I do not use it here.—In any case, Christian theology became a theology of retreat and defense in the face of this mechanistic naturalism. This was true of the Ritschlian theology, the theology of mediation or apologetic theology, and of most of the theological books that were written in the second half of the nineteenth century. Christian theology was like an army retreating in face of an advancing army. With every new breakthrough of the advancing army, in this case modern science, Christian theology would attempt to protect the Christian tradition which still remained intact. Then a new breakthrough would make the previous defense untenable, and so another retreat and setting up a new defense would be necessary. This went on and on.

This whole spectacle, this fight between science and religion, has brought contempt upon the term "apologetic." It was a poor form of apologetic. The first great shock which had to be accepted was the Copernican world view. Galileo, the greatest representative of this idea, was forced by the Inquisition to recant, but his recanting did not help the church at all. Soon the theologians had to accept the Copernican world view. Then there was Newton's mechanics of bodies moving according to eternal natural laws; the concept of natural law was established and philosophically formulated by Kant. This prevented thinking about interferences of a divine being; God was placed along­side the world, and not permitted to interfere with it. Then theology came to the defense of miracles, the idea of the possibility of divine interferences, which of course presupposes a miserable concept of God who would have to destroy his creation in order to do his work of salvation. But this was the apologetic situation. Then another retreat was required because the defense of miracles in this way was untenable. A further shock came with the idea of evolution. Then a six-day

456            A History of Christian Thought

creation was defended, then abandoned. Evolution said that life has developed out of the inorganic realm. Then where is God? According to the traditional idea of creation God has created the organic forms; they have not developed out of the inorganic forms. Therefore, a particular work of God's creation must be postulated and on this thin thread the whole apologetic position was suspended. There was the lacuna in scientific knowledge, for science was not able to show how the organic developed out of the inorganic. Theologians enjoyed this lacuna, for they could place God in this gap left by science. Where science could not work any more, God was put to work, so to speak. God filled the gaps left by science.

That was an unworthy idea of God. The position was indefensible so theologians had to withdraw again. But one last point was kcpt. That is the creation of man. Here the Roman Church still sticks to the idea that even if the evolutionary process is as presupposed by biology today, there is still one point that cannot be explained biologically, namely, the immortal soul which God has given man, the higher animal, at some moment in the process of evolution. This was and still is a last defense against science, but this last defense is not tenable either, for it pre­supposes a substance, the soul, which is a separate form from the form of the body. But in the Aristotelian sense, the soul is the form of the body and you cannot separate them. Moreover, the concept of eternal life has nothing to do with such a dualistic construction of an immortal soul put at one moment into man's body. When this last defense is given up, science has conquered all apologetic positions. And this is a good thing. Then the situation must be seen in an absolutely new way. Science lives and works in another dimension and therefore cannot interfere with the religious symbols of creation, fulfillment, forgiveness, and incarnation, nor can religion interfere with scientific statements. No scientific statement about the way in which living beings have come into existence or how the first cell developed out of large molecules can have direct bearing on theology. Indirectly, of course, everything is a concern of theology. For when science describes the way in which life is construed and is developed, then indirectly it says something about God, the creative ground of life, but not in terms of an interference of a highest being in the processes of nature.

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   457

This whole struggle between science and religion is no doubt in the past for you. But it was not so when I began the study of theology. At that time apologetic theology was full of confidence that science would never find a way of showing the development from, let us say, the original mud to the first cell. But science can show this to a great extent, perhaps not fully, but this is a matter of experiment. Theology does not need to put God to work to fill an empty space in our scientific knowledge.

The struggle over Darwin dealt not only with this general evolution­ary idea, but more concretely with the genesis of man. The "monkey trial" was a last remnant of this struggle which was so prominent in the nineteenth century. It was a great shock which the church had to absorb after the initial shocks of the Copernican revolution and the Newtonian idea of natural law. I may be wrong, but I believe that aside from some literalists in the South or in the Bible belt no one in the younger generation or among theologians is involved in this conflict any longer. People presuppose that science has to go its way, and that the religious dimension is different from the scientific. But in the nineteenth century this affair disrupted the faith of millions of people. The laborers who read the socialist literature decided negatively against religion; they looked at religion as always interfering in the arena of scientific discus­sions. And when religion did this, it was a lost cause. It has taken over a half a century to overcome the antireligious attitude among the scientists and the antiscientific attitude among the religious people. If we are out of this situation now, I hope we never return to it. And we should avoid remnants of this kind of apologetics today. For instance, we should not try to base our doctrine of freedom on Heisenberg's principle of indeterminacy, as if to say that since there is some element of indeter­minacy in nature, we can speak of freedom. Perhaps tomorrow this principle will be replaced by another, and then your whole wonderful apologetic collapses, and you join the retreating army of apologists. The theologians of the twentieth century should learn this lesson from the nineteenth century. You cannot apologetically establish symbols which belong to the dimension of the ultimate upon a description of finite relations.

You can speak of the structure of nature, as I have done in the third

458             A History of Christian Thought

volume of Systematic Theology, through all the realms of the natural. But this is not done for apologetic purposes, but is in line with Thomas Aquinas' statement that he who knows anything, knows something about Cod. Whatever we know in any realm bears witness to the creative ground of it. In this sense we must deal with statements of science. But we must do so also in another sense. For the work of the scientists is of the highest theological interest insofar as it reveals the logos of being, the inner structure of reality, which is not in opposition to the Logos which has appeared in the Christ, but is the same Logos. Therefore, in this sense the witness of science is the witness to God. This is the right relationship and is not one of fighting against each other in terms of unjustified interferences.

D. KJERXEGAABD'S EXISTENTIAL THEOLOGY

Soren Kierkegaard must also be dealt with as a contributor to the breakdown of the universal synthesis, although his greatest influence has been exercised in our time rather than in his own. He made a new start based on a combination of an existentialist philosophy and a pietistic, revivalistic theological criticism of the great synthesis. More specifically, he combined Lutheran pietism of the revivalist type, including the orthodox content of revivalism, with the categories of Schelling's exis­tentialism. Although he denied Schelling's solution, he took over the categories. His criticism, together with that of Marx and Nietzsche, is historically most important. But none of these three became influential in world-historical terms in the nineteenth century. Kierkegaard was largely a forgotten individual in his century. I recall with pride how as students of theology in Halle we came into contact with Kierkegaard's thought through translations made by an isolated individual in Würt-temberg. In the years 1905-1907 we were grasped by Kierkegaard. It was a very great experience. We could not accept the theological orthodoxy of repristination. We could not accept especially those "posi-tive"—in the special sense of "conservative"—theologians who disre­garded the historical-critical school. For this was valid science which was carried on by this school. It cannot be denied if honest research is conducted into the historical foundations of the New Testament.

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   459

But on the other hand we had a feeling of moralistic distortion and amystical emptiness, an emptiness in which the warmth of the mystical presence of the divine, was missing, as in the whole Ritschlian school. We were not grasped by this moralism. We did not find in it the depths of the consciousness of guilt as classical theology had always had. So we were extremely happy when we encountered Kierkegaard. It was this combination of intense piety which went into the depths of human existence and the philosophical greatness which he had received from Hegel that made him so important for us. The real critical point would be the denial that Hegel's idea of reconciliation is a genuine reconcilia­tion. Man is not reconciled by the reconciliation in the philosopher's head. We will hear the same thing from Marx later on.

We could discuss Kierkegaard in connection with the existentialist movement of the twentieth century, because he became effective only in our own century. Nevertheless, in the structure of this course I prefer to Place him in his own historical place where he represents one of the decisive criticisms of Hegel's great synthesis. We will discuss him fairly thoroughly, and you can take this discussion not only as a treatment of nineteenth-century theological thought, but also of twentieth-century theology, for while he wrote in the nineteenth century, his real influence has been significant in the twentieth century. Later we will see similar situations with regard to two other thinkers who were not inner-ecclesiastical representatives of theology, but anti-ecclesiastical representatives. They are Marx, especially in his earlier existentialist protest against Hegel, and then Friedrich Nietzsche, who followed Schopenhaner.

You may be a little surprised that I do not deal more with the theological movements within the church of this period. The reason I do not is that they are not as important as the great critics of Hegel for our own situation. These critics are more fundamental for our theological situation today than are the theologians of mediation. There are some rare exceptions, as for example my own teacher Martin Kahler in Halle. The real impact came from people outside. Of course, Kierkegaard was religiously inside, but as a critic of the church he was perhaps even more radical than Marx and Nietzsche put together.

Kierkegaard has become the fashion in three respects: (a) Reli‑

460            A History of Christian Thought

giously, which is most justified, because his religious writings are as valid today as they were when they were written. (b) As the inspiration for the dialectical theology, called neo-orthodoxy in this country. In Europe it is usually called dialectical, which shows its relation to Hegel, for this term is the main principle of Hegel's thinking. (c) As the inspiration for Heidegger, the philosopher who has given the name existentialism to the whole movement which derives from Kierkegaard.

I. Kierkegaard's Criticism of Hegel

As in the case of most of the anti-Hegelians, Kierkegaard's criticism is based on the concept of reconciliation. For Hegel the world is reconciled in the mind of the philosopher of religion who has gone through the different forms of man's spiritual life the subjective spirit (which is the psychological side), the objective spirit (the social-ethical and political side), and the absolute spirit (art, religion, and philosophy). The philosopher lives in all of them. He is deeply in the religious realm; he lives in the aesthetic realm; and on the basis of the religious realm he conceptualizes what is myth and symbol in religion. Out of all this he develops his philosophy of religion. In this way he mirrors in his mind the final synthesis after the whole world process has gone through thesis, antithesis, and synthesis. The divine mind, the absolute mind, comes to its rest on the basis of religion within the mind of the philosopher who achieves his highest power when he becomes a philosopher of religion, conceptualizing the symbols of the religious life. This is for Hegel reconciliation. This reconciliation in the mind of the philosopher was the point attacked by all those whom I have mentioned—Schelling, Feuerbach, pietists, and natural scientists. They all said the world is unreconciled. The theologians went back to Immanuel Kant and said the prison of finitude is not pierced, not even by Hegel's great attempt. The reconciliation of the finite and the infinite has not yet happened.

Kierkegaard did the same thing in a particular way. In the system of essences reconciliation might be possible, he argued, but the system of essences is not the reality in which we are living. We are living in the realm of existence, and in the realm of existence reconciliation has not yet happened. Existence is the place of decision between good and evil.

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   461

Man is in the tragic situation, in the tragic unavoidability of evil. This contradiction in existence means that Hegel is seen as confusing essentialist fulfillment with existential unfulflilment or estrangement. I told you that estrangement or alienation is one of the terms which Hegel created, but which is then turned against him. Nature is estranged spirit for Hegel; the material reality is self-estranged spirit. Now Kierkegaard said that mankind is in this state of estrangement, and Hegel's construction of a continuous series of syntheses in which the negativity of antithesis is overcome in the world process is true only with respect to the essential realm. Symbolically we could perhaps say that it goes on only in the inner life of Cod. But Kierkegaard empha­sized that estrangement is our situation. Only in the inner divine life is there reconciliation, but not in our situation.

Hegel had described the inner divine life in his great logic. The logic is the science of essences in their highest abstraction and their inner dialectical relationship. Then the logicians came along. The man who is very important for the criticism of all essentialism is Trendelenburg. Kierkegaard was dependent on him for his logical criticism of Hegel. His criticism was that the logical process is not a real process; it is not a process in time; it is only a description of logical relations. What Hegel did was to confuse the dialectical process of logic with the actual movement in history. While reconciliation is always a reality in the dialectical process of divine life, it is not a reality in the external process of human existence. So from the logical point of view Hegel was criticized for his fundamental confusion of essence and existence.

Hegel was not able to understand the human situation in terms of anxiety and despair. Kierkegaard could not follow Hegel; all his life he possessed a melancholic disposition. This melancholy of which he often spoke was associated with a curse which his father made against God, and he felt that the reaction to this blasphemy of his father was upon him and never left him free. The point is that such a personality was able to discover things which were not so deeply felt by a character as Hegel, who existed in a bourgeois situation, who felt psychologically more safe and was able to conquer the negative and tragic elements of life which he saw.

462            A History of Christian Thought

2. Ethical Existence and the Human Situation (Anxiety, Despair)

One of the main points connected with Kierkegaard's melancholic personal condition and his feeling of unreconciled reality was his experience of the lonely individual. Here again we have an anticipation of present-day existentialism. The individual stands in solitude before God and the process of the world cannot liberate him from the tremendous responsibility by which he lives in the situation. Again and again he said that the last reality is the deciding individual, the individual who in freedom must decide for good or evil. We find nothing of this in Hegel. It is very interesting that Hegel who was so universal in his thinking and all-embracing never developed personal ethics. His ethics are objectivist; he subsumed ethics under philosophy of history and philosophy of law. Ethics of family, ethics of state, of comj-nunity, of culture, all that is in Hegel, but not ethics which has to do with the personal decision of the individual. This was already an element in Schelling's attack against Hegel, but it was stressed more by Kierkegaard than by anybody else.

What is the reason for this experience of solitude? It is due to human finitude in estrangement. It is not the finitude which is identical with the infinite, but it is separated finitude, finitude standing upon itself in the individual person. As long as the identity principle was decisive, it was possible to overcome the anxiety of finitude, of having to die, by the experience of being united with the infinite. But this answer was not possible for Kierkegaard. So he tried to show why we are in anxiety because of being finite and in despair because of being in separated finitude. The first is his description of anxiety and the second is his description of despair. There are two writings which every theologian must read. Both are comparatively short: The Concept of Dread and The Sickness Unto Death.5 I have always criticized the title of the English translation of The Concept of Dread, because dread is different from anxiety. Dread has in it the connotation of something sudden,

5 Soren Kierkegaard, The Concert of Dread, translated by Walter Lowrie (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1944); and The Sickness Unto Death, translated by Walter Lowrie (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1941).

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   463

whereas what Kierkegaard describes is an ontological state of man. But now in English the term "anxiety" has generally replaced "dread" to describe this state which Kierkegaard has in mind. The Concept of Dread, in any case, is a fundamental book on the theory of anxiety. It has been more fully developed by others, so that now there is a vast literature on the subject, including the works of people like Freud, Rollo May, et al.

Kierkegaard wrote about two kinds of anxiety. The first is con­nected with his theory of the fall. He symbolized this with the biblical myth of Adam and Eve, and found profound psychological insight there. This is the anxiety of actualizing one's own freedom, which is a double anxiety: the anxiety of not actualizing it, of being restricted and of not coming into real existence, and the anxiety of actualizing it, with the knowledge of the possibility of losing one's identity. This is not a description of an original historical Adam, but of the Adam in every one of us, as the word "Adam" means. in this double anxiety of actualizing oneself and of being afraid to actualize oneself, every adolescent finds himself with respect to sex, his relation to his parents, to the political tradition in which he lives, etc. It is always the question of actualizing or not actualizing one's potentialities.

Finally the decision is made for actualizing oneself, and this is simultaneously the fall. But after the fall there is another anxiety, because the fall, like every trespassing of limits, produces guilt. The anxiety of guilt at its extreme point is despair. This despair is described in The Sickness Unto Death. This sickness unto death is present in all human beings. This condition is described with the help of many Hegelian categories, as the conflict between spirit and matter in man, man having finite spirit, man experiencing the conflict in himself, having the desire to get rid of himself, and of being unable to commit suicide because the guilt consciousness makes it clear that suicide cannot help you to escape the situation in which you are. One thing ought to be kept in mind, and that is that the term "guilt" means both the objec­tive state of being guilty for something that is wrong, and the subjective state of feeling guilty. To confuse these two states can be very bad, for example, when many psychoanalysts say that we must abolish guilt. That is very ambiguous, for what they really have to overcome is

464            A History of Christian Thought

misplaced guilt feeling, which is one of the worst mental diseases. But this can be done only if they manage to bring the patient to the point where he faces up to his real state of being guilty, his true guilt in the objective sense. We must make a clear distinction between guilt and guilt feeling. Guilt feelings may be very misleading. In neurotic and psychotic conditions they are always misplaced. One of the defenses of the neurotic is to insist on misplaced guilt feeling because he cannot face reality and his own real guilt. This real guilt is his estrangement from the ultimate that expresses itself in actual acts directed against his own true being.

3. The Nature of Faith (the Leap and Existential Truth)

There is no escape from the sickness unto death; therefore, something must happen which cannot be mediated in logical terms. You cannot derive it from anything in you; it must come to you; it must be given to you. Here the doctrine of the "leap" appears in Kierkegaard. It has already appeared, in fact, in his description of the fall. Anxiety brings man before a decision, for or against actualizing himself. This decision is a leap; it cannot be logically derived. Sin cannot be derived in any way. If it is derived, then it is not sin any more but necessity. Here we can recall what I said about Schleiermacher for whom sin is the necessary result of the inadequacies of our spiritual life in relation to our physical life. That makes sin a necessity, and thus takes the sharpness of guilt away from sin. Kierkegaard repudiates this notion of sin. For him the fall of man is a leap of an irrational kind, of a kind which cannot be derived in terms of logical necessity.

But there is the opposite leap, the leap of faith. You cannot derive this either from your situation. You cannot overcome the sickness unto death, the anxiety of estrangement. This can only be done by faith. Faith therefore has the character of a nonrational jump in Kierkegaard. He speaks of the leap from the point of view of the individual. He is so well nourished on Hegelian dialectics that he builds up a dialectic of spheres. Between these spheres there is a leap. That is non-Hegelian. But the spheres themselves follow each other hierarchically, and that is truly Hegelian. There are three steps or spheres. You can also call them

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis    465

stages, but they are not so much stages following each other in time as levels lying above each other in space, and coexisting all the time in ordinary human beings. These levels or stages are the aesthetic, the ethical, and the religious. Man lives within all of them, but the decisive thing is how they are related to each other and which one is predomi­nant for him.

Kierkegaard's description of the aesthetic stage was perhaps the most brilliant thing he did. His Diary of the Seducer, often abused for other purposes, is the most complete description of the aesthetic stage in its complete actualization. Also his analysis of Mozart's Don Juan is a great work of literary criticism, philosophy, and theology all in one. The characteristic of the aesthetic stage is the lack of involvement, detach­ment from existence. It has nothing to do with aesthetics as such or with the arts. Of course, this attitude of mere detachment and of noninvolve­ment in the situation can take place in relation to music, literature, and the visual arts; but it can also be found in the theoretical or in the cognitive relation to reality. Cognition can have the merely aesthetic attitude of noninvolved detachment. I am afraid this is seen as the ideal even in many humanities courses in the universities. To be sure, there are elements of mere detachment in every scholarly inquiry; detachment will be necessary when dealing with dates, places, and connections, etc., but as soon as you come to interpretation, detachment will be reduced by existential participation. Otherwise you cannot understand reality; you do not "stand under" the reality.

Hegel was regarded somehow as a symbol of the aesthetic attitude, and so were the romantics. Because of their aesthetic detachment they took all the cultural contents on the basis of a nonexistential attitude, a lack of involvement. When I came to this country and first used the word aestheticism in a lecture, a colleague of mine at Columbia Uni­versity told me not to use that word in describing Americans. That is a typical European phenomenon. Americans are activists and not aestheti-cists. Now I do not believe this is true. I think there is quite a lot of this aesthetic detachment even in popular culture. It is present in the buying and selling of cultural goods—I spoke about this on the occasion of Time Magazine's fortieth anniversary—in which you often see a non­participating, nonexistential attitude. Here Kierkegaard's criticism

466            A History of Christian Thought

would be valid. Perhaps on the whole this is not a very great danger among the American intelligentsia. My observation has been that they jump very quickly out of the detached aesthetic attitude—in all lectures and discussions, in philosophy and the arts—to the question, "What shall we do?" This attitude was described by Kierkegaard as the attitude of the ethical stage.

In the ethical stage the attitude of detachment is impossible. Kierke-gaard had a concept of the demonic which means self-seclusion. This belongs to the aesthetic stage, not going out of oneself, but using everyone and everything for one's own aesthetic satisfaction. Opposed to this demonic self-seclusion is love. Love opens up and brings one out of self-seclusion, and in doing so conquers the demonic. This character of love leads to the relations of love. Here Kierkegaard accepted Hegel's objective ethics—the ethics of family, of vocation, of state, etc. In the aesthetic stage sex produces isolation; in the ethical stage love overcomes isolation and generates responsibility. The seducer is the symbol of irresponsibility with respect to the other one, for the other one is manipulated only aesthetically. Only through responsibility can the ethical stage be reached.

It is interesting as a biographical fact that Kierkegaard never reached two of the decisive things that he attributed to this stage, that is, family and vocation. He lived from some income as a writer, but he never had an official vocation, either in the church or outside of it. And he had this tragic experience with his fiancée, Regina Olson, whom he loved dearly. But because of the inablity to transcend his self-seclusion, his melancholic state, he finally dissolved the relationship, and never really overcame the guilt connected with it.

Then Kierkegaard dealt with the religious stage. The religious stage is beyond both the aesthetic and the ethical and is expressed in relation to that which interests us infinitely or which produces infinite passion. You recall that I told you about Hegel's two concepts: interest and passion. Hegel's critics took these terms from him and then used them in their criticism of him. Hegel said that without interest and passion nothing great has ever happened in history. This notion was now taken over by Kierkegaard into the religious situation and by Marx into the quasi-religion of the nineteenth-century revolutionary movement.

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis    467

Religion has within itself two possibilities, identity and contrast. The principle of identity is based on mysticism, the identity of the infinite and the finite; and the principle of distance is based on estrangement, the finitude and the guilt of the human situation. We have discussed this often in these lectures. We saw this especially in the contrast between Spinoza and Kant, Spinoza the representative of the principle of identity and Kant the representative of critical detachment. This duality which permeates all human existence and thought is also present in Kierkegaard's description of the two types of religion. He calls these two types "religiousness A" and "religiousness B," but a more powerful way of expressing the same thing is to use the names of "Socrates" and "Jesus." Both of them have something in common. Both of them are existentialists in their approach to God. Neither is simply a teacher who communicates ideas or contents of knowledge. They are the greatest teachers in human history because they were existential. This means they did not communicate contents, but did something to persons. They did not write anything, but they have produced more disciples than anybody else who has ever written anything. All four Greek schools of philosophy were pupils of Socrates who never wrote a thing, and Christianity is the result of Jesus who never wrote anything.

That alone shows the person-to-person situation, the complete existen­tial involvement of these two types of religiousness. But then there arises the great difference. Religiousness A or the religion of Socrates pre­supposes that truth is present within every human being. The funda­mental truths are in man himself. The dialectical or existential teacher has only to evoke them from man. Socrates does this in two ways. The one is irony. This concept is in the best tradition of Romanticism of which I spoke. This means that every special content of which a person is sure is subjected to radical questioning until its insecurity is revealed. Nothing remains as self-evident. In Plato's dialogues Socrates is the leader of the discussions, and he applies irony to the Sophists who know everything, who are the scholars of their time. The Socratic questioning undercut their scholarly self-consciousness, their belief in their infalli­bility. Socrates did the same thing with the craftsmen, the businessmen, and the aristocratic people who were his followers. The other way is midwifery. This means that the existential teacher brings to birth what

468            A History of Christian Thought

is already inside a person, helps him to Find the truth in himself, and does not simply tell him the truth. This presupposes the Platonic idea that man's soul has an eternal relation to all the essences of things. So knowledge is a matter of memory. The famous example given in Plato's dialogue Meno is of the slave who is asked about the Pythagorean proposition of the three angles of a triangle, and although he is com­pletely uneducated, he is able to understand it because of the mathe­matical evidences within him. This is not produced in him by external teaching. This is indeed true of geometry and algebra. Everyone can experience in himself the evidence of such things, but this is not true of certain other things. This then led to the resistance of the empirical school against Socrates and Plato, on the one hand, and leads to the other religious type represented by Jesus, on the other hand.

Both Socrates and Jesus communicate indirectly, as Kierkegaard says, but they do not have textbook knowledge of any kind. By indirect communication Socrates brings to consciousness what is in man. There­fore, he is called a religious teacher. I am in full agreement with that. I think it is ridiculous to say that Socrates is a philosopher and Jesus is religious, or perhaps a religionist, a really blasphemous term. Both of them deal with man in his existential situation from the point of view of the meaning of life and of ultimate concern. They do it existentially. In this sense we can call Socrates the founder of liberal humanism, as one of the quasi-religions. Now, if the difference between Socrates and Jesus is not that of the difference between philosophy and religion—which is absolute nonsense here—then what is the difference? The difference is that the indirect ironical teacher, Socrates, does not transform the totality of the being of the other person. This is done only in religiousness B, by the teacher who is at the same time the Savior, who helps the person whom he teaches in terms of healing and liberating. Here another type of consciousness comes into existence. According to this idea, God is not in man. Man is separated from God by estrangement. Therefore God must come to man from outside, and address him. God comes to man in the Christ.

God is not the paradoxical presence in the individual, but he is present outside of man in the Christ. Nobody can derive the coming of the Christ from the human situation. This is another leap, the leap of

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   469

God into time through the sending of his Son. This cannot be derived from man, but is given to him. This makes Jesus the teacher into the Savior of men. While Socrates is the great existential teacher, Jesus is both the teacher and the Savior who transforms man.

In this way the religious stage has within itself a tension. Hegel's interpretation of the Christ was in the line of Platonism. In Hegel the eternal essential unity of God and man is represented in a complete way in the Christ, but it is also present in every individual. For Kierkegaard God comes from the outside or from above. Here you see immediately the starting point of Karl Barth. According to him, you cannot start with man, not even in terms of questioning. You must start with God who comes to man. The human situation is not such that you can find in man's predicament the question which may lead to the religious answer. In terms of this conviction Barth criticizes my own systematic theology, which in this sense is un-Kierkegaardian. This idea of God coming to man totally from the outside had great religious power, but I would say that its religious power is disproportional to its philosophical power, to the power of thought. It cannot be carried out in such a way. But that is not the point here. The point is that you see the bridge from Kierke-gaard to Barth and neo-orthodoxy in the idea of God coming to man from above and from outside him, with no point of contact in man. When Emil Brunner wanted to say that there must be some point of contact, Barth answered with his passionate "No"—this famous essay in which he defends his idea of the absolute otherness of God outside of man. Now, I do not believe this idea can be maintained, but, in any case, negatively speaking, it had great religious power.

This is connected with a concept of truth that has to do with the metaphor of leap. This truth is quite different from the objective truth in the scientific sense. So Kierkegaard makes the following statement, which gives the gist of all his philosophical and theological authorship: "Truth is the objective uncertainty held fast in the most personal passionate experience. This is the truth, the highest truth attainable for the existing individual." Here he defines faith as well as truth, for this is just the leap of faith. A very important element is what he calls the objective uncertainty. This means that theology is not based on objective certainty. A merely objective certainty, as Hegel wanted to reach, is not

470            A History of Christian Thought

adequate to the situation between God and man. This would be possible only if the individual had already entered the system of essences, the essential structure of reality. But he has not; he is outside of it, as God is outside of him. Therefore, objective certainty in religion is impossible; faith remains objectively uncertain. Truth in the realm of the objective scientific approach is not existential truth. Kierkegaard would not deny the possibility of scientific truth, but this is the truth of detachment. It is not the truth of involvement; it is not existential truth. Existential truth is objective uncertainty and personal, passionate experience or subjective certainty, but a certainty which can never be objectified. It is the certainty of the leap.

This subjective certainty of the leap of faith is always under criticism and attack, and therefore Kierkegaard speaks of holding fast to it in a passionate way. In personal existence there is passionate inner move­ment, and in the power of this passion we have the only truth which is existentially important for us. This is the most significant thing in the world, the question of "to be or not to be." It is the ultimate concern about man's eternal destiny, the question of the meaning of life. This is, of course, different from the truth we approach in terms of approxi-mative scientific objectivity. If we use the term "subjectivity" in connec­tion with Kierkegaard's idea of existential truth, then please avoid the mistake of equating it with willfulness. This is the connotation the word has today. Therefore, it is so difficult to understand a man like Kierke-gaard and practically all classical philosophers. Subject means what it says, something standing upon itself, sub-jectum, that which underlies. Man is a sub-jectum, one who stands upon himself, and not an oh-jectum, an object which is in opposition to a subject looking at it. If man is this, then he becomes a thing. This is the sickness of our time. The protest of subjectivity does not mean the protest of willfulness. It means the protest of freedom, of the creative individual, of personality, of man who is in the tragic situation of having to decide in a state of estrangement, in the human predicament. In these ideas we have almost the whole summary of Kierkegaard's theology.

But then Kierkegaard goes beyond this to the question: What can be done to give content to this situation? With respect to the content we must say that not much can be found of it in Kierkegaard. He was not a

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   471

constructive theologian, and he could not be, because one can be a constructive theologian only if he is not only existentially interested and passionate, but also has an essentialist vision of the structure of reality. Without this, systematic theology is impossible. So we find very little content in the theological or religious writings of Kierkegaard. We have only a continuous repetition of the term "paradox"—leap is simply another word for paradox, that which cannot be derived, that which is irrational and surprising.

There is, however, one content to which he refers all the time, and this is the appearance of the Christ. Thus the leap which is necessary to overcome the situation of doubt and despair is the leap into the reality of the Christ. He states this in a very unusual, paradoxical, and theo­logically questionable form. He says that only one thing matters: In the year A.D. 30 God sent the Christ for my salvation. I do not need any more theology; I do not need to know the results of historical criticism. It is enough to know that one thing. Into this I have to leap. Then we must ask: Can we solve the problem which historical criticism has opened up by a theology of the leap? I do not believe it is possible. Philosophically the question is this: In which direction am I to leap? You can leap in all directions, but if you have a direction in mind, you already have some knowledge, so it is not a pure leap anymore. If you are in complete darkness and jump without knowing in what direction you are jumping, then you can land anyhere, maybe even on the place from which you jumped. The danger in this concept is asking someone to jump without showing him the direction. Then we have more than subjectivity and paradox; we have willfulness and arbitrariness; we have complete contingency. But if you already know in which direction to jump, in the direction of Christ, for example, then you must have a reason for this. This reason may be some experience with him, some historical knowledge, some image of him from church tradition, etc., but in any case, you have some content. The mere name alone does not say anything. And if you have these things, you are already in the tradition of theology and the church, and it is not a sheer leap any more. This is a problem which we have to say Kierkegaard left completely unsolved. His statement that you have to leap over two thousand years to the year A.D. 30 is simply unrealistic, because nobody can do that. The intellec‑

472            A History of Christian Thought

tual leap, or the emotional-intellectual leap, which you are supposed to make with your whole self, is conditioned by two thousand years of church and cultural history. You cannot do that without using con­temporary language, and you use language even though you are silent, for internally you speak whenever you are thinking. When you make such a leap, you are using the language of the 1960's, and so you are dependent on the two preceding millennia. It is an illusion to think we can become contemporary with Christ insofar as the historical Jesus is the Christ. We can be contemporary with the Christ only in the way described by the apostle Paul, that is, insofar as the Christ is the Spirit, for the Spirit is present within and beyond the intervening centuries. But this is something else. Kierkegaard wanted to solve the problem of historical criticism by this concept of contemporaneity. You can do this if you take contemporaneity in the Pauline sense of the divine Spirit present to us, and showing the face of Jesus as the Christ. But you cannot escape historical criticism by becoming contemporaneous with Jesus himself. This is the fundamental criticism which we must make from a theological point of view.

4. Criticism of Theology and Church

We have still to discuss Kierkegaard's critical attitudes toward the­ology and the church.' One can almost say that when Kierkegaard deals with the church or theology, the image which he presents is more a cari­cature than a fair description. In particular the ecclesiastical office was an object of criticism. He attacked the fact that the minister becomes an employee like all other employees, with special duties and economic se­curities. This position of the minister, especially its bourgeois elements, of having a career, getting married, raising children, while at the same time proclaiming the impossible possibility of the Christ is for Kierke-gaard involved in a self-contradiction. But Kierkegaard does not indicate how this conflict might be solved. Certainly it is a reality, and for Kierkegaard a reality which contradicts the absoluteness of the essence of Christianity. One cannot take this as an objectively valid criticism,

6Cf. Kierkegaard's Attack upon 'Christendom,' translated by Walter Lowrie (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1944).

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   473

because if one did, then one would have to abolish every church office. If the office is not abolished, it is inevitable that the laws of sociology will make themselves felt and influence the form of the office and those who hold it.

The same thing is true of his attacks on theology. He attacks theology because it is an objectifying attempt to construct a well-formulated system out of the existential paradox. Here again the inadequacy of the situation of the theologian is marvelously expressed, but in terms of a caricature. On the other hand, the question is whether theology is a necessary service of the church. If it is—and it has always been that as long as Christianity has existed; there is theology in Paul and John—then the question arises: Can the theological task be united with the paradox of the Christian message in a different way? When Kierkegaard speaks about the theologian in his attack on theology, he sarcastically suggests: Since Christ was born, let us establish a chair in theology dealing with the birth of. Christ; Christ was crucified, so let us make a full professorship for the crucifixion of Christ; Christ has risen, so let us make an associate professorship, etc. This kind of comical attack on theology makes a great impact on anyone who reads it, whether he is a theologian or not. But if it is taken as more than a reminder, if it is taken as a prescription, it means the abolition of theology.

The truth which we can gain from this kind of criticism of theology is the truth of the inadequacy of the objectifying attitude in existential matters. This refers both to the ministry and to theology. In the ministry there is the objectifying factor, the factor of a sociological structure in analogy with all sociological structures. In theology there is a structure of thought in analogy with all structures of thought. This reminder is, of course, of great importance. The minister and the theologian should be forever reminded of the inadequacy, and not only that but also of the necessity of what they are doing. The impossible possibility, as Reinhold Niebuhr, I believe, following Kierkegaard has expressed it, is incarnated in the position of the minister and the theologian. For something which is a matter of paradox, contrary to all expectation, is brought into a form of existence comparable to any other object in time and space. But this is the whole paradoxical situation of the church in the world. You can also express it by saying that the Christian religion is one of the

474            A History of Christian Thought

many sections of human culture, but at the same time stands vertically in relation to everything which is culture. From this you can draw the conclusion that Christianity should be removed from every cultural relationship, but if you try to do that, you will find it impossible. The very words you use in order to do it are dependent on the culture from which you will try to detach Christianity. On the other hand, if you do not see the vertical aspect, if Christianity is merely for a class of human beings who are blasphemously called religionists and becomes merely a part of the whole culture, this may be very useful for undergirding patriotism, but the paradox is lost.

Here we face a conflict which is as real, permanent, and insoluble for us as it was for Kierkegaard. Since in Denmark at Kierkegaard's time there was a sophisticated theology of mediation, the prophetic voice could hardly be heard any more. Kierkegaard became the prophetic voice. The prophet always speaks from the vertical dimension and does not care about what happens in the horizontal dimension. But then Kierkegaard became a part of the horizontal; he became the father of existentialist philosophy, of neo-orthodox theology, and of much depth psychology. Thus he was taken into culture just as the prophets of Israel who, after they had spoken their paradoxical, prophetic word out of the vertical, became religious reformers, and were responsible, for example, for the concentration of the cult in Jerusalem because of the cultic abuses in other places. So out of the vertical there comes a new hori­zontal line, that is, a new cultural actualization of the prophetic word. This cannot be avoided. Therefore, there is need for the prophetic word again and again which makes us aware that the situation of every servant of religion is a paradoxical one and is in a sense impossible. Kierkegaard's word was not accepted widely in his time, but when people in the beginning of the twentieth century realized the coming earthquake of this century, Kierkegaard's voice could be heard again.

Question: You summarized Kierkegaard's understanding of Socrates. Do you consider this a correct interpretation of Socrates, or does it contain features peculiar to Kierkegaard?

Answer: First, I would say that it contains features peculiar to Plato.

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   475

We do not know how much it has to do with the historical Socrates. It is parallel to the relation between the Synoptic Gospels and the fourth Gospel. The fourth Gospel has its analogy in Plato, and the Synoptic Gospels in Xenophon. Perhaps neither is right from a strictly historical point of view. But this is the way that a great historical figure appears to us. What is historically decisive is the impact a figure has on those who are with him. So here is a strict analogy between Socrates and Jesus, neither of whom wrote anything.

We know them only through their impact on their disciples, and this impact makes them not only historically significant, but also symbolic figures, figures in whom a symbol or archetype is embodied. Through this elevation to the status of a symbol the figure continues to influence history.

Now the Socrates of Plato certainly does what Kierkegaard says in connection with the Socratic irony and the Socratic maieutic or mid­wifery. The irony destroys that which one believes he knows, and the maieutic method is a way of bringing thoughts out of someone which are implicit in the depths of his soul. These two parts are certainly there in the Socrates whom Plato presents. How high the probability is of the historical accuracy of Plato's picture of Socrates is something that has been discussed for two thousand years. It cannot be said with certainty how much of Plato's image of Socrates is based on the actual Socrates himself. Scholars try to determine that, and with our modem methods of historical research we can perhaps come very near to the historical truth. We find that it is likely that the historical Socrates was not as banal as Xenophon makes him, but neither was he a pupil of Plato; it was the other way around.

But Kierkegaard is right in making another fundamental distinction. We spoke about religiousness A and religiousness B. Religiousness A is a religion in which the divine is present in every human being immedi­ately and can be found in the depths of his being. This is basically a mystical form of religious experience, with God in us, the infinite within the finite. We showed how the whole modern development is dependent on this principle which was most sharply expressed by Nicholas of Cusa, the principle of the coincidence of the infinite and the finite in every finite thing. On the other hand, in religiousness B the

476            A History of Christian Thought

basic point is the separation, the estrangement. This means that there is a gap between the divine and the human, so that man needs more than a midwife like Socrates who brings out of us what we already have within us; something new must come from the outside. The Savior or the Christ must come. This is the difference between Jesus and Socra­tes. Jesus is not only the existential teacher as Socrates; he is also the Savior who overcomes the gap between Cod and man. I think you have realized that the dialectic between these two principles is important in my own theological lectures, the dialectic between the principle of identity or the coincidence of the infinite and the finite in every person and the principle of a revelatory communication from outside, which is both revelatory and saving or transforming. Revelation in Kierkegaard's sense is not the communication of doctrines or knowledge about God. That is a badly distorted concept of revelation. But revelation is the self-manifestation of the divine to a human being which has transforming power. Both the symbolic and the doctrinal statements which arise out of the revelatory experience are secondary.

* * * * * * * * * *

E. P0LmcAL RADICALISM AND ITS THEOL0CICAL SIcNIFIccE

What I will do now is perhaps surprising to you. I want to give you here the theology of the most successful of all theologians since the Reformation, namely, Karl Marx. I will consider him as a theologian. And I will show you that without doing this, it is impossible to under­stand the history of the twentieth century and large sections of the late nineteenth century. If you consider him only as a political leader or as a great economist, which he also was, or as a great sociologist, which he was even more, then you cannot understand from what sources the power came which transformed the whole world and conquered nearly half of it in the twentieth century. How can Marx have been a theologian in view of the fact that every word he said is connected with the split in humanity which he is largely responsible for having produced? Yet, there is a deep gap between the original Karl Marx and what is going on now in Russia or China, although the historical effects of his work are manifest in these countries.

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   477

1. The Bourgeois Radicals

There was in the time that Marx was starting his work a group of people whom we can call liberal radicals. On the basis of the principle of autonomy in bourgeois society a liberal radicalism developed. A man whose name you should at least know is Max Stirner (1806-1856) who wrote a book entitled The Individual and His Right.7 In this very radical book he tried to remove all the overarching norms which tradi­tional society, including the Enlightenment, had imposed on people. Very similarly to Kierkegaard he placed the individual in the center, but unlike Kierkegaard it was the individual without any relationship to God, but only to himself, and therefore without any norm. This was one of the things which produced the resistance of Marx. For this reason I must mention Max Stirner here. He was a neurotic personality and an extremist. Of course, as a mere individual he could not survive for one day without being dependent on others who provided for him. But this is not important for him; he forgets it. The absolute autonomy of the individual is described by him in almost ecstatic words.

Now you can imagine that Marx with his analytic knowledge of society would be full of aggressive irony against such an idea. He knew of the economically productive society, about the peasant and the grocery store, etc., and could not abstract from them as the neurotic bohemian could do so easily. And the beatniks of today who attack society forget the fact that it is the basis of their whole existence every minute. The same is true of Kierkegaard. The church which he at­tacked so radically, with its tradition within culture, was the basis of his statement that in the years A.D. 1-30 God came to man. Without the tradition of the church which produced both the Bible and the church nothing would have come to Kierkegaard, and his whole relationship to God would not have been possible. This is an idea that you should remember when someone attacks "organized religion"—a bad term—and says, I am very religious, but I am against organized religion. That is nonsense. It is nonsense because in his personal religiousness—excuse this terrible word—he is dependent on the tradition of the church for

7 Max Stirner is the pseudonym of Johann Kasper Schmidt, author of Der Einzige und sein Eigentum (Leipzig: 0. Wigand, 1901).

478            A History of Christian Thought

every word, every symbol that he might use in prayer, in contemplation or mystical experience. Without the community of speaking, there is no speaking whatsoever, and without an inner speaking, there is no spirit­ual life whatsoever. In this way it is easy to refute these attacks against organized religion. You can and should attack the forms and the ways in which it may be organized, but to use the term "organized religion" as name-calling is totally senseless. It simply shows lack of thought, and is usually rooted in bad experiences in childhood or more likely in Sunday School, which is one of the great laboratories in which Christian faith is expelled from children.

2. Marx's Relation to 14egel and Feuerbach

Now we must start with Marx's relation to Hegel and Feuerbach. He was a pupil of Hegel. Feuerbach, another pupil of Hegel, had put Hegel on his feet after he had been standing on his head, as Marx said. Hegel believed that reality is identical with the head of the philosopher. Feuerbach showed that the philosopher like everybody else is dependent on the material conditions of life. So Feuerbach developed a material­istic or naturalistic doctrine of man—man's dependence on his senses, etc. Marx said that Feuerbach had done the main thing; he had criti­cized Hegel's explanation of religion. Marx felt that he did not have to do that any more. But he had to criticize Feuerbach's materialistic ontology, and Feuerbach's idea that being is individual being, that the individual as such is the one who is decisive for the whole situation. Marx's criticism of Feuerbach held that materialism is not much better than idealism. It is a little bit better because idealism is merely ideology without any basis in reality. Materialism is closer to reality. But if only the individual is considered in the materialistic philosophy, then it is as bad as idealism. For its universal concept of man is abstracted from the individual and overleaps the social conditions in which man finds himself.

So Marx attacked both the materialists and the idealists. In regard to the term "Marxist materialism" it would be much better to leave that to the propagandists who use and confuse three different meanings of materialism in order to carry on their propaganda. But that has nothing

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis    479

to do with historical truth and an academic education. So it is better for you to understand that there are three meanings of materialism.

a.  The one is the ontological or metaphysical materialism. You find this in Feuerbach who derives everything in nature from the movements of atoms in terms of calculable mechanical causality. It is a theory which has not often been represented in history. Present-day naturalism in America is certainly not materialism. Metaphysical materialism is also called reductionist naturalism, whereby reductionism means reducing everything to the mechanical movement of atoms and molecules. This is an obsolete philosophy. It existed in Europe at the end of the nineteenth century; also it existed in France at the end of the eighteenth century in the French encyclopedists of the pre-Revolution period; and it has ex­isted only very rarely in this country. But on the whole it is a philosophy which has been overcome, and is very remote from Marxism.

b.  Then there is ethical materialism, which means being interested only in material goods, in money, etc. When someone is called a materialist in propaganda, no clear distinction is made between ethical and metaphysical materialism. If Marxism is called materialistic, for example, the trick of propaganda is to leave the impression of an ethical materialism. In reality, however, the original socialist movement and also the kind of communism you find in the original Marx attacked the materialism of the bourgeois society, where everything was dependent on buying and selling, on profit, etc. So Marxism was just the opposite. Now the critics of the materialism of the bourgeois society are called materialists, usually with the connotation of ethical materialism, of being interested only in material goods.

c.  Historical materialism is the third type. This means that the whole historical process is ultimately dependent on the ways of economic production. This is Marxist materialism. It should be called historical or economic materialism. It is quite different from the other two meanings.

Marx deals with the question of the individual and society. This was not so new in France, England, and Holland, but it was very new in Germany. In Germany the social structure was always taken for granted as something ordained by God. This was in accordance with Lutheran doctrine. Sociological analysis was avoided. Sociology had been fully developed in France in the nineteenth century before German scholars

480           A History of Christian Thought

even started to think sociologically. Marx received his sociological view partly from France and partly from his insight into the miserable social conditions of large sections of people in Europe. Man is not man as an individual. The idea of the individual existing by himself is an illusion. This sounds quite different from Kierkegaard and Stirner. But Marx saw that we are really members of a social group. It is impossible to abstract ourselves from sociological reality. So he criticized Hegel and Feuerbach because they did not see individual men as members of a social struc­ture. What is needed is an analysis of the social structure and the individual's place within it.

3. Marx's View of the Human Situation (Alienation)

Like Kierkegaard, Marx speaks of the estranged situation of man in the social structure of the bourgeois society. He uses the word "aliena­tion" (Entfremdung) not from the point of view of the individual but of society. In Ilegel estrangement means the absolute Spirit goes over into nature, becoming estranged from itself. In Kierkegaard it means the fall of man, the transition by a leap from innocence into knowledge and tragedy. In Marx it means the structure of the capitalist society.

Marx's description of modern society is of great importance. If we as theologians speak of original sin, for example, and are not aware of the problems of estrangement in the social situation, then we cannot really address people in their actual situation in everyday life. For Marx estrangement means that the social situation results in dehumanization. When he speaks of mankind in the future, he speaks of true humanism. He looks forward to a situation in which true humanism is not a pleasure merely for the cultured few; humanism is not the possession of cultural goods either. He looks for the re-establishment of a true, hu­manity to replace the dehumanization in an estranged society. The main thing in the idea of dehumanization is that man has become a cog within the great process of production and consumption. In the process of production the individual worker has become a thing, a tool, or a commodity which is bought and sold on the market. The individual must sell himself in order to live.

These descriptions imply that man is essentially not an object, not a

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   481

thing, but a person. Man is not the tool but the highest end or aim. He is not a commodity but the inner telos for everything that is done. Man is the inner meaning and aim. Marx's description of dehumanization or the particular form of estrangement that existed in capitalist society completely contradicts what he had inherited from classical humanism. He saw no reconciliation. In historical reality there is only dehumaniza­tion and estrangement. Out of this came the power to change the situa­tion. When Marx in the Communist Manifesto spoke about the liberation of the masses from their chains, these chains were the powers of dehumanization produced by the working conditions of capitalist society. Consequently, the essential character of man is lost. Man on both sides of the class conflict is distorted by the conditions of existence. Only if these conditions are removed can we know what man truly is. Christian theology says that we can know what man essentially is be­cause essential man has appeared in the conditions of existence in the Christ.

Estrangement refers not only to human relations, characterized by the cleavage between classes, but also to the relation of man to nature. The eros element has been taken away. Nature is only the stuff out of which tools are made, and by means of the tools consumer goods are manufac­tured. Nature itself has ceased to be a subject with which we as subjects can be united in terms of eros, the love which sees in nature the inner power of being, the ground of being which is creatively active through nature. In the industrial society we make nature only the material out of which to make things for buying and selling.

4. Marx's Doctrine of Ideology and His Attack on Religion

Ideology is another extremely important concept for theology. What is ideology? The word itself is older than Marx. It was used, for in­stance, by Napoleon when he criticized professors for being ideologists instead of being practical statesmen and generals. The word has a history which remains ambiguous even today. Ideology can be a neutral word, meaning simply the system of ideas which one can develop. Every group or class has such a system of ideas. But ideology can also mean—becoming then the most dangerous weapon in the class struggle—the

482            A History of Christian Thought

unconscious production of ideas which justify the will-to-power of a ruling group. This is mostly an unconscious production, but it can be used in a conscious way.

Marx used this word "ideology" as a weapon. It was probably his sharpest weapon against the ideas of the ruling classes with which the churches were allied. All the great European churches, the Orthodox, the Lutheran, and the Episcopalian, were on the side of the ruling classes. The Roman Catholic Church was better in this respect for it had preserved a tradition of social feeling and social analysis from its classical medieval period.

A term which we used in our daily language that is very close to the meaning of ideology is rationalization. We speak of the rationalization of individuals who use ideas to justify the power they hold over other persons or to justify their indulgence in certain kinds of pleasures. Applied to social groups rationalization becomes ideology. This is a very important theological concept. Every Christian and every church should always be suspicious of their own ideologies which they use to justify their own traditional self-satisfactions. Every church should be suspi­cious of itself lest it formulate truths only as an expression of its will-to-power.

This notion of ideology is used by Marx to supplement Feuerbach's criticism of religion. He says that in principle Feuerbach succeeded in removing religion, but his criticism was not founded on sociological analysis. Marx says that the religious symbolism of a transcendent fulfillment (of heaven or immortality) is not merely the hope of every human being, but is the invention of the ruling classes to prevent the masses from seeking fulfillment in this life. Their attention is diverted to a so-called life hereafter. This is formulated in the famous phrase that religion is the opiate of the people. He simply means that if you have the assurance of an eternal fulfillment, you will not fight in a revolu­tionary way for the temporal fulfillment of man on earth.

Now I do not think that this is true. It is very similar to the way that Kierkegaard criticized the church of his time. It is the radicalism of the prophetic word. But then, of course, this same idea has to be applied to Marx himself and to all the movement which followed him. Then we must ask: What about the ideological character of the ideologies of the

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   483

victorious revolutionary movements? Are they not also expressions of a new will-to-power? When we see what has happened to the Marxist ideas in Soviet Russia, we must immediately answer in the affirmative. The ruling classes in Russia maintain ideologies derived from Marx to keep themselves in power, although their ideas have only an indirect connection with Marx. There is the ideological element in the will to maintain themselves in power. The reason for this is that Marx lacked a vertical criticism against himself. This is the same situation that we have in all Communist countries, the lack of a vertical criticism. On the horizontal they have a lot of truth, but they cannot put this under the criticism of the vertical, because they have cut it off. Nobody can do that completely, but they have done it to a great extent. The danger in our culture is that we do the same thing with less radical and revolu­tionary methods, but with the more refined and sophisticated methods of mass culture.

A great gap between the churches and the labor movements in Europe developed. The churches were the representatives of the ideol­ogies which kept the ruling classes in power over against the working masses. This was the tragic situation. It is a great thing that in America this tragedy has happened on a much smaller scale. But in Europe it has led to the radical antireligious and anti-Christian attitudes of all labor movements, not only of the Communists but also of the social demo-crats.

emocrats. It was not the "bad atheists"—as propagandists call them—who were responsible for this; it was the fact that the European churches, Orthodox, Lutheran, and Episcopalian, were without social sensitivity and direction. They were diredted toward their own actualization; they were directed toward liturgical or dogmatic efforts and refinements, but the social problem was left to divine providence. The Czarist ruling classes, the German imperial ruling classes, and the British ruling classes were not in contact with what was going on in the working classes either. In Great Britain the situation was much milder, and therefore Great Britain never had a Marxist revolution. Nevertheless, the situa­tion was very similar.

This situation can be seen the world over. On the one side there is a theology of mere horizontal fulfillment, with the kingdom of God being identified with the classless society or with a continuous transformation

484           A History of Christian Thought

of society as in the British Labor party and in German social democracy. On the other side are the churches with their theology which has a vertical dimension. But a few things have happened which attempt to bridge the gap. In England there was a religious socialist movement very early; whether it called itself by that name or not, its ideas were the same. Then in Germany there was a religious socialist movement which came from some prophetic personalities in Switzerland. But nothing of this existed in Germany before the first World War.

I remember the great churches in the workers' quarters in Berlin. Workers did not enter the church except for baptism, marriage, and the funeral. The churches provided some glorification of these events. But any inner relation to the churches did not exist. To a typical Lutheran minister of that time I said: The workers cannot hear the Christian message. You must do it differently. You cannot expect that they will come into the churches. His answer was: They hear the church bells ringing every Sunday morning, and if they do not come to the church services, they will feel guilty. But they did not hear anything, and they did not know anything. They had no relation to the religious symbols of the tradition. The Lutheran attitude was that the people can come to hear the Christian message in the church. At least the people hear the bell ringing, and that is enough. If they do not come, they will be rejected by God. Fortunately, this attitude has ceased to exist. But it was this kind of attitude which produced the tremendous gap between the church and the laboring classes. Religious socialism tried to close that gap.

5. Marx's Political Existentialism

The existentialist element in Marx is very great. His concept of truth has a similarity to Kierkegaard's. Truth is truth for human existence, truth which concerns our life-situation. We said that Kierkegaard defined truth as an objective uncertainty passionately held. Marx defines truth in terms of the gap between theory and practice. That is to say, truth must be related to the social situation. A philosophical theory which is not involved in the social situation is not true. We have something of this in pragmatism and in John Dewey. There are in fact

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis    485

great similarities between existentialism and pragmatism. One of the things which has made John Dewey the great educator in this country is his insistence that all knowledge must be united with practical activ­ities in the educational process. This was even more basic for Marx. We cannot know the truth about the human situation without existential participation in the social structure in which we are living. We cannot have truth outside the actuality of the human situation. Therefore, in our period of history one must participate in the proletarian situation in order to understand the depths of estrangement. Here we must cau­tiously avoid a mistaken idea. In Marx there is no glorification of the proletariat. The revolutionary movements made the proletariat the messiah, the savior, so to speak, not because the proletarians are such wonderful people—Marx never believed that; he knew them—but because they stood at a particular point in history which involved them in a class struggle, and through this struggle a new reality might come into existence. Marx knew that the class split distorted both sides in the situation. Men were made into objects. The leading bourgeois and the working masses are in the same boat with respect to dehumanization. But the proletariat had one advantage. They experienced the estrange­ment in such a way that they would be forced to revolt. The prole­tarians are the blessed, in the sense of the Beatitudes, for they exist on the extreme negative edge of the class situation. So in the Marxist criticism of society a biblical truth has been applied to an analysis of the social situation. When one speaks about the saving power of the prole­tariat, this does not mean that the proletariat is good and the others are bad. Marx's friend Engels was a big businessman, a capitalist. But the structure of the situation puts the proletariat on the lowest level where the need for revolution is felt. Through its revolutionary role it is thought to be the saving power.

6. The Prophetic Element in Marx

We cannot miss the messianic note in Marx's writings. Especially in the earlier writings we hear the voice of a modern secular prophet. He speaks like the old prophets of Israel. Marx as a Jew was in the tradition of Jewish criticism which had lasted through the millennia. His wrath

486           A History of Christian Thought

against the reality as he saw it had something of the old prophetic wrath in it, although it was distorted by propagandistic elements as happens in

every political leader. Nevertheless we cannot overlook the prophetic element in his whole work. When the prophets spoke to Israel, even when they spoke about the other nations, the whole weight of their attack was directed also against their own nation. They saw that their word did not transform their own nation. So, they said, the wrath of God would strike Israel. Especially Jeremiah was aware of this. But there is also the promise of God. It could not come to naught; it would come to fulfillment. So the prophets had the idea of the remnant, the small group which would be the bearer of the divine promise.

The idea of a remnant is not the idea of only the prophets. Everybody who speaks prophetically to a large group or to a nation has such an idea. Without such an idea you would be driven to despair and forced to give up. But you do not need to give up, because there is the remnant. The word "remnant" means those who are left over, those who do not adore the idols, who do not do injustices, etc. in the larger sense this word means those few within the group who are conscious of the situa­tion and who therefore become the bearers of the future development. This idea of the remnant restricts to a certain extent the messianism of the proletariat. In the last analysis it is not the whole proletariat, but the leading groups in it, the vanguards, who are decisive. So a simple identification of the proletariat with messianism is limited by the fact that it is those who are the vanguards who have a messianic role. These vanguards are not always even members of the proletariat. They are people like Marx and Engels who come from the intelligentsia or the upper classes and have broken through their own ideological self-seclusion. They have learned what is going on in history and can join the vanguards.

The difference between Marx's secularized prophetism and that of the Jewish prophets is that the latter always kept in mind the vertical line and did not rely either on human groups or on logical or economic necessities of development, as Marx did. They ultimately relied on God, and this was lacking in the modern secularized movement. Certainly, this movement is quasi-religious. It is not pseudo-religious, for pseudo-religious means "deceptive" or "lying." But it is quasi-religious because it

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis    487

has in itself the structure of prophetism, but with one differenée—the transcendent, the vertical line, has been lost.

The tragic thing is that the revolutionary movements in Europe, Asia, and Africa originally came from a prophetic message, but when they became victorious, they did not apply their own criticism against themselves. They could not do it, because they had nothing above themselves. The Communists in Russia answer all the problems in the East-West discussion without showing the element of ultimate self-criticism. Of course, there is much self-criticism in individual groups in Communist countries, There are individuals who confess they have sinned. But they have always sinned against the party; there is nothing higher than the party; the party cannot err; the party is infallible. The lack of the transcendent line is the reason for the tragic situation that the revolutionary movement which set out to liberate a whole social class has resulted in a new slavery, the totalitarian slavery as we have it today in the Communist systems. This is a world-historical tragedy. Similar things have happened before in history. Consider, for example, how the movement of Jesus Christ resulted in the church of the Inquisition in the later Middle Ages. All these tragic transformations come about because of the lack of the self-criticism derived from the vertical line. When the church did not judge itself any longer in terms of the vertical line, something like the Inquisition could happen. The Marxist move­ment was not able to judge itself because of its whole actual structure, and so it could become the social group which we now identify as Stalinism. In this form everything for which the original groups were struggling became suppressed and distorted. It is in our century that we can best see the tragic reality of man's estrangement in the social realm.

F. VOLUNTARISM AND THE PHILOSOPHY OP Lnn

Now I come to the last of the movements which contributed to the collapse of the great syntheses of Schleiermacher and Hegel. This movement is voluntarism, a term derived from voluntas, the Latin word for "will." Voluntarism is a philosophy in which the element of will is decisive. It began in the nineteenth century with Schelling who in his earlier years was a philosopher of the will before he became the

488            A History of Christian Thought

philosopher of nature. For him will is original being. It is being itself. We can describe being most adequately in terms of will. Being is not a thing; it is not a person; it is will. This idea of will refers to what is often called today "unconscious instinct." But the word "instinct" should be dropped if you are translating Freud. The word "drive" should be used instead. Man has no death instinct. That is a misuse of the word "instinct." But man does have the death drive in himself.

Voluntarism is one of the great lines of thought in the history of philosophy and theology, which has been in continual tension with the other great line of thought which goes back to Aristotle and includes among others Thomas Aquinas, the nominalists, the British empiricists, Kant, to a great extent Schelling and Hegel, and modern language analysis. These two lines of thought have made the Western philosophi­cal movements full of life and tension. In naming Thomas Aquinas we should also mention immediately Duns Scotus and William of Ockham as his voluntaristic opponents.

1. Schopenhauer's Idea of the Will

From Schelling we come to Scbopenhauer. What impressed him was not Hegel's great synthesis nor Schelling's philosophy of identity, but rather Schelling's doctrine of will. Usually he is considered as the first representative of voluntarism in nineteenth-century thought. He com­bined with his voluntarism a deep pessimism. He is always quoted if one speaks of philosophical pessimism. But voluntarism is not necessarily pessimism, as we shall see in Nietzsche, his great pupil and critic.

Not only Schopenhauer's temperament but also his personal destiny must be kept in view. He lived in the overwhelming shadow of Hegel and never really came into his own during his lifetime. His famous book, The World as Will and Idea,8 became known only very late. It had a tremendous influence in the second half of the nineteenth century and through Freud in our own century. The most important pupil of Schopenhauer was Nietzsche. The line then runs from Nietzsche to Bergson, the French voluntarist, Heidegger and Sartre, and to White‑

8 Translated by R. B. Haldane and J. Kemp (London Trübner and Co., 1883-86).

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   489

head, the great metaphysician of our century. All this came from the powerful voluntaristic element in Schelling, but became generally influential only later through Schopenhauer and Nietzsche.

To understand this nineteenth-century movement it is helpful to go far back for a moment. Where does voluntarism come from? Its first clear appearance is in Augustine, who embodies the element of will in his own personal character in a much more dynamic way than it appears in most of the Greek philosophers and writers. Augustine is the philosopher of will, and especially of that will which is love. The substance of all reality for him is will. He could have written Schell-ings statement that original being is will, but since it deals with the creation of God he calls it love. Love is original being; the power of love is the substance in everything that is. This love (amor) loves itself (amor amoris), the self-affirmation of the will which is divine love.

In the Middle Ages Augustine's ideas were represented by the great Franciscan theologians, while the Dominican theologians represented Aristotle's ideas. The tensions between these two in the thirteenth century represent the high point in medieval thought. In the Franciscan school will precedes intellect. In the Aristotelian-Thomistic school, or Dominican school, intellect precedes will. This is not a vague statement about man's psychology; it is always meant ontologically. That means that in God himself, in the creative ground of being, either will or intellect is the primary power. In this course we have dealt mainly with people who represent the primacy of the intellect. This is very much the case in German classical philosophy. It is also predominant in the eighteenth century, with some exceptions. The priority which Kant gave to practical reason represents a breakthrough of the element of will. In Schelling we have a complete breakthrough, and also in Fichte. But throughout that period the emphasis on intellect was predominant. Now in the thirteenth century Bonaventura was one of the great Franciscans in whom will was the decisive thing, that is, will as love. He was a great mystic and also an early general of the Franciscan order. This mysticism of love goes back also to Saint Francis. Standing in radical opposition to Thomas Aquinas was Duns Scotus, himself a Franciscan, and the greatest critical mind of the whole Middle Ages and one of the most important philosophical minds of the Western world. Both Thomas and

490            A History of Christian Thought

Scotus lived in the thirteenth century. Scotus defined God as will and nothing other than will. In another Franciscan, William Ockham, this became an irrational will. Ockham is the father of nominalistic philos­ophy of the later Middle Ages. There was an earlier nominalistic movement about which Abelard and Anseim of Canterbury were fighting.

If God is sheer will, he can do what he wants. He has within himself no intellectual limits. There is no logos structure which would prevent him from doing what he wants. The world is in every moment dependent on something absolutely unknown. Ultimately nothing in the world can be calculated. Only insofar as it is ordered by God can it be calculated, but God can withdraw both the natural and the moral orders. If he wanted, he could make murder good, and love bad. The theology of Martin Luther was influenced by nominalism, although not really dependent on it. Luther himself was a voluntarist and had in himself much of the Dionysian awareness of the underground of life in man. He was a great depth psychologist before our present-day depth psychologists. He had insight into the demonic forces in the world and in man. As the legends tell us, he had to fight continuously against the demonic forces in himself, during the attacks which he called Anfech-tungen. When he described these demonic attacks—perhaps the best translation of Anfechtungen—he said that one moment in this situation of absolute despair, which is an element of the demonic attack, is worse than hell itself.

I must mention several other bridges to nineteenth-century volun­tarism. There was the philosopher and shoemaker, Jacob Boehme, who saw in his visions the full demonic power, the will element, in God himself. He called it the nature of God and saw that element in God which contradicts the light in God, the logos in God, the wisdom and truth in God. He understood the conflict in the divine life, the tension between these two elements. This tension makes the divine life not simply a sheer actuality (aclus rurus) as in Aristotle, but a dynamic process with the potentiality for conflict. In God this inner conflict is always victoriously overcome, but in creatures it breaks out destructively as well as creatively.

Boehme had a great influence on Schelling's ideas concerning the

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   491

inner life of Cod. If all this sounds very mythological, then read the books of Charles Hartshorne, A. N. Whitehead, and Henri Bergson. They were all influenced by Boehme (who himself was dependent on Luther's voluntarism) and Schelling. Even Hegel was to some extent dependent on Boehme.

One of the ways in which you can envisage the Western world in its philosophical and theological developments is in terms of this tension between the merely Apollonian—this means putting intellect over against will as the decisive thing in man—and the combination of the Apollonian and the Dionysian—which puts the will in the center and the intellect as a secondary force over against will. If this is said about man, it is also said about God, both in the Middle Ages and in modern theology. So we have here a very dynamic picture of Western philo­sophical development. It is important for us to know about this, because we are still in the midst of it. This struggle is still going on, for example, between the Whiteheadian school and the philosophy of logical analysis.

That gives you the historical perspective. But let us go into a few other considerations here. First the term "will." It is very important that in all these men you understand what the idea of will means. If you examine a text on psychology, you will find that usually will is derived from other elements, the vital drive, on the one hand, and the intellect, on the other hand. It is presented as a secondary phenomenon and primarily as a conscious phenomenon. If will is taken in this way, it is impossible to understand how will can be identified with being itself. How can there be will in stones and crystals and plants and animals? They have no consciousness; they have no purpose which is directed by an intellect expressing itself in language, using universals, etc. But this is not what will means if it is understood in an ontological sense. Will is the dynamics in all forms of life. Only in man does it become conscious will. If I decide to go to my office after this lecture, that is a conscious act of my will. In voluntaristic philosophy will is not restricted to a conscious psychological act. You cannot derive the meaning of will from man's psychological experience of himself as a consciously willing being. Nevertheless, the word must be used. Will for these ontologists appears in man as conscious will, in animals as instinct or drives—these appear also in man—in plants as urges, and in material reality as trends

492            A History of Christian Thought

such as gravitation, etc. If you understand will as the dynamic element in all reality, then it makes sense.

The term "intellect" is also subject to misunderstanding. The idea as the ontologists have used it does not refer to the I.Q. of the college boy. Intellect comes from the Latin "inter-legere," to read between. To read between means to be in something, to be in the reality and reading it, being aware of it. That means participating in the form of things. Readable things have a form. The substance, the dynamics, you cannot read; they are dark; they are the drives. Reading, which is here meant metaphorically, is only possible where there is form. The word "under­standing" has a similar metaphorical meaning. Standing under or reading between have the same meaning. They refer to a position in which we are in the reality itself and are able to become aware of its particular form. This awareness we call cognition.

Schopenhauer's idea is that will, unconscious will, drives toward the actualization of that which it is willing, and since it can never reach it, it reacts with the desire for death. This is a concept which we also find in Freud's death tendency or death drive which is derived from the always unsatisfactory fulfillment of our will. The will never gets what it wills. Out of this the dissatisfaction with life arises. According to Schopenhauer this drives the will to ever new attempts to fulfill its desire and ever new impossibilities of doing it. Life is a restless driving toward fulfillment which can never be attained. The result is the disgust of life, a deep dissatisfaction with every fulfillment. in all the, volun-tarists the sexual drive plays a great role—from unfulfillment to fulfill­ment, then to ever new fulfillment. The restlessness of these drives leads finally to a desire to come to rest by not willing any more.

With this idea something very important for the history of Western civilization occurred. Schopenhauer discovered Buddhism and in it the idea of the will to self-negation, the will to bring one's will to rest by not willing any longer. Of course, Schopenhauer was not a historian but a philosopher and as such identified his own philosophy with the fundamental Indian idea that blessedness is the resignation of the individual will, the overcoming of the self in a formless self, as the Zen-Buddhists call it, or the return into the Brahman principles, the eternal ones, as the Hindus call it. From this the ascetic tendency in life is

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   493

derived. Schopenhauer did not follow along in this point, but anyway he introduced these ideas into the Western world where they have had an influence up to now.

Schopenhauer made one exception to his general view, and this Placed him in line with the romantic philosophy of his time. He said that when we hear music we are able to come to rest in time and space. Music was for him the anticipatory salvation of the restless will. In music the will comes to rest, but since one cannot always be listening to music, one must finally tend toward the ultimate salvation which happens only in the moment of death. Schopenhauer is to be considered as the man who overcame in many people the progressivistic optimism of Hegel and prepared the way for the existentialist pessimism of the twentieth century.

2. Nietzsche's idea of Will-To-Power

Even more important than Schopenhauer for the twentieth century and the theological situation is Friedrich Nietzsche. He was a pupil of Schopenhauer. He used the word "life" rather than "will." Life is essentially will, but a special kind of will. It goes in quite the opposite direction from Schopenhauer's will. It is not the will which brings itself to rest and ceases to will, but it is the will which Nietzsche calls will-to-power.

First we must say something about this word "power." I have already had to rescue the word "will" from the misunderstanding that it is merely a psychological phenomenon; rather, it is the universal driving dynamics of all life processes. Now I must rescue the word "power" in Nietzsche from a similar misunderstanding. For him power is the self-affirmation of being. Will-to-power means will to affirm one's power of living, the will to affirm one's own individual existence. In man this will-to-power becomes will to personal and social power. That is not the primary concept, but it is a part of the whole concept. This power has nothing to do with Nazism, with its irrational power. It is the power of the best; only the power over oneself can give one social power. If one is not able to exercise the aristocratic self-restriction, then one's power will decay. So the abuse of it by the vulgar Nazi movement has nothing to

494            A History of Christian Thought

do with Nietzsche's vision of will-to-power. It is one of the tragedies that this great symbol created by Nietzsche should become something devil­ish in the mouths of vulgar people.

Nietzsche's style is oracular in contrast to Hegel's dialectical philos­ophy. He is one of the great fragmentists in the history of literature. Fragments can be very powerful. In the pre-Socratics we have almost only fragments. In part this is an accident of history, for much of the early pagan literature was destroyed by Christian fanaticism and later by Islamic fanaticism. But in any case these fragments are in themselves complete, understandable, and full of mystery. The same is true of the fragments of Nietzsche. He tells us that he wrote them at a time of an inspired state of mind. He also wrote great poetry.

Nietzsche knew of the ambiguity in all life. He knew of the creative and destructive elements which are always present in every life process. If you want to find out about his idea of God, do not look first to his statement that "God is dead." Read instead the last fragments of The Will To Power,° which is a collection of fragments. It is not a book in itself. The last fragment describes the divine demonic character of life in formulations which show the ambiguity, the greatness, and the destructiveness of life. He asks us to affirm this life in its great ambiguity. Out of this he then has another kind of God, a God in which the demonic underground, the Dionysian underground, is clearly vis­ible. The victory of the element of rationality or of meaning is not as clear as in other philosophers like Kant or Hegel, Hume or Locke, but there is an opening up of vitality, and its half-creative, half-destructive power.

3. Nietzsche's Doctrine of Resentment

Now where do the norms of life come from? Nietzsche has a theory very similar to that of Feuerbach and Marx. This is his theory of resentment. The Jewish-Christian idea of justice, the Greek-Christian idea of logos, and the Christian idea of love are all ideas which result from the resentment of the masses against the aristocratic rulers. It is the revolution of resentment. This is the same type of thing that Marx

Translated by Anthony M. Ludovici (London: T. N. Foulis, 1913-14).

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis    495

called ideology when he derived the Christian and generally religious ideas and values from the state of negativity of the masses of people to whom the upper classes promised a fulfillment in a transcendent heaven. Marx used this word as a powerful weapon in the revolution. And psychoanalysis shows how individuals use rationalization to justify drives in themselves which they want to maintain or fulfill. So Nietzsche added a third concept, that of resentment. These three concepts have had tremendous power because they are really revealing of the human situation. The concept of rationalization shows how the individual man tries to give reasons in a system of values for his natural drives of eros and will-to-power. Freud with his empirical methodology discovered how little our conscious life represents what we actually are. This was a revolution in our climate of thought in the twentieth century; it undercut the bourgeois and puritan moralistic conventions in all Western countries, and in particular the Protestant-dominated coun­tries. Most of you belong to the third generation of this revolution, but I belonged to the first generation; I tried to show what it means for Protestant theology that not the surface consciousness but the under­ground of human existence is decisive in human experience and relations. The concept of ideology revealed the interest of the ruling classes in preserving their power by producing a transcendent system to divert the masses from their immediate situation of disinheritance. We see the same thing today going on in the underdeveloped countries where there are revolutionary tendencies. They often look at our democratic ideas, which are rooted partly in Stoicism and partly in the Old Testament, as an ideology of the Western world to maintain its predominance and to introduce its values.

In Nietzsche's psychology of resentment all the ideas of justice, equality, democracy, liberalism, etc., are born out of the resentment of the masses, and the most powerful bearers of this resentment are the religions of Judaism and Christianity. Therefore, this resentment func­tions in the exact opposite way from Marx's notion of ideology. The ideas produced by resentment are an attack against the ruling classes, while in Marx the ideological system is a weapon of the ruling classes to keep the others down.

One especially interesting idea in Nietzsche is his attack on the

496            A History of Christian Thought

Christian idea of love. The idea of love is indeed a great problem. First of all, in the modern languages we do not have the distinctions we have in Greek. Epithumia is the vital drive (in Latin this is libido, the word used by Freud); philia is the friendship type of love, the person-to-person relationship; eros is the creative, cultural love toward the good, the true, and the beautiful; agape is the word used in the New Testament meaning the acceptance of the other one as a person, which includes the principle of justice. It is the power of reuniting with the other person as one standing on the same ultimate ground, and therefore he is the object of acceptance, forgiveness, and transformation. That is the Christian idea of agape.

Now this agape was sentimentalized long before our time. It was sentimentalized in Romanticism. The concept of Christian love could hardly be distinguished from sentimental desire or from pity. Especially pity was identified with the Christian idea of love. So charity replaced love in the sense in which I have just defined it. Against all this Nietzsche fought with the will to the self-affirmation of life. He is the greatest critic, not of the Christian idea of love, although he thinks it is the Christian idea of love, but of the sentimentalized idea of love, where love is reduced to compassion. In the name of power, the will-to-power, self-affirmation of life, he fights against this idea which undercuts the strong life.

Nietzsche made a good point which we ought to remember in our preaching of love. He said, you speak of selfless love and want to sacrifice yourself to the other one, but this is only a way for the weak person to creep under the protection of somebody else. Erich Fromm, the psychoanalyst, has called this wrong kind of love which Nietzsche attacked "symbiotic love"—from syn and bios, meaning "living to­gether." This is a love of the weak man for the other one who once lived from his strength, and it is a form of love which exploits the other one. This kind of self-surrender has the unconscious desire for exploitation. This is what Nietzsche was actually fighting against. We should not forget this when speaking of love in Christianity. Love can mean any of these four things which are distinguished in Greek, and therefore it does not mean anything unless we explain in what sense we are using the word. Usually it is connected with a sentimentalized type of love.

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis    497

Nietzsche was also interested very much in music. He was a great friend of Richard Wagner, the great composer and bridge to modem music. But one of the most interesting events was the break between Nietzsche and Wagner. They were friends, but gradually Nietzsche noticed in Wagner the restoration of a religion of sentimentality. As far as I remember the final break happened in connection with Wagner's Parsifal, the romantic sentimentalization of the myth of the representa­tive suffering. Here Nietzsche with his will-to-power, the will of self-affirmation of life, reacted with radicalism and intensity. If you keep in mind that Hitler was a great lover of Wagner's music, you have a clue to how far away Nazism is from Nietzsche's philosophy, although words like "will-to-power" and "superman" sound as if they were a preparation for Nazism. Somehow they actually were, but not in the mind of Nietzsche, just as Marx was a preparation for Stalin, but not in the intention of Marx. These are tragedies in history.

4. The "Death of God" and the New Ideal of Man

The concept of the "death of God" is a half-poetic, half-prophetic symbol. What does it mean? Ordinarily one would think that it means simply the spread of atheism, whatever that word means. But this is not the point in interpreting Nietzsche. Nietzsche did not repeat the atheistic or naturalistic criticism of the theistic idea of God. He accepted just as Marx did Feuerbach's criticism of religion. But Nietzsche meant that when the traditional idea of God falls, something else must fall along with it. The system of ethical values on which society is based fell, and this is the important consequence of this symbol of the death of God. Of course, this is a symbol, for it can only mean that God is dead as far as man's consciousness of him is concerned. The idea that God in himself is dead would be absurd. The idea is rather that in man the consciousness of an ultimate in the traditional sense has died. The result is—and this confirms this interpretation—that somebody else must replace God as the bearer of the system of traditional values. This is man. In the past man had to hear the "thou shalt" and the "thou shalt not" as that which is derived from God or an objective system of values. But now this is gone. So in place of this Nietzsche put man who says "I

498           A History of Christian Thought

will." Man no longer says "I shall" because of God, but he says "I will" because I will. I act because I will and I decide what is good or evil.

This idea has many implications. One of them is Nietzsche's famous phrase, 'the transvaluation of all values." All the traditional values must be replaced by other ones. Not any transcendent authority does this, but man does it. Who is this man? Does this not imply a tremendous over­estimation of man's greatness? Certainly Nietzsche did not think very highly of man. The mass man who appeared with the industrialization of the European countries was full of resentment; he was weak; he sur­rendered to the powerful; he produced ideologies which promise him happiness in heaven because he cannot have it on earth. That is man as Nietzsche knew him. So it is not this man, this mass man, who can say "I will." It is the superior man. Nietzsche speaks of the (Jberinensch, which could be translated as superman, except that this has become a character in the funny papers. Other suggestions have been made: higher man or superior man, or simply using the foreign word tIber-,nensch. Perhaps superior man is the best.

Where does this superior man come from? He comes from the development of mankind in a Darwinian sense. When you study Nietzsche you should not forget that this was the time in which Darwinism reached its high point. He simply accepted Darwin's idea of the selective process of life in which the weaker species are annihilated and the stronger ones survive to produce still stronger ones. This evolu­tionary idea of Darwin is the background to Nietzsche's idea of the superior man. Of course, in all evolutionary thinking there is an image of a higher man, of mankind being on a higher level. But Nietzsche did not think merely of an educational, spiritual development of mankind from lower to higher levels of moral education and ethical life, as has usually been thought of in the Western world. Nietzsche would accept this idea too, but he took Darwin in a much more literal and naturalistic way. The superior man is also stronger physically. He is a man straight in body and soul, as he said. In some of his metaphors, this man is even the wild beast, but the wild beast on the human level, not irrational, but powerful, representing a new type of existence in which man is not like the mass man of the present day.

The question has often been asked whether if there is evolution, does

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   499

the evolution cease with man? Why should it cease with man, and not go beyond him? There are two possible answers. The one answer is that in man the biological possibilities on earth are exhausted; no higher developments can follow. If there is to be any further development, then it must happen in the realm of the mind or soul or spirit of man. But in any case, it is an inner development of man, and not of a bodily kind. Of course, logically this cannot be proved. It presupposes that there is no possibility of a higher bodily development on earth. If this presupposition is not accepted, Nietzsche would be justified. The superior men are the strong ones, full of unbroken vitality, shaped by strict self-discipline, indeed the very ideal of the aristocratic personality. In contrast to them there is the one symbolized in his expression "the last man." His description of the last man is the antitype to the superior man. He is the man who knows everything, but does not care for anything—half-sleepy, half-indifferent, completely conformist, and full of abandoned creativity. He is like the caricature of the "organization man" described in current sociological literature. The mass man avoids at all costs being controversial; therefore he accepts subjection to conformism in all respects. He is disinterested, without any ultimate concern, bored, cynical, empty. All of these descriptions are given in a poetic way by Nietzsche. This is what he calls the nihilism toward which our culture is running.

These ideas have had world-historical consequences. Not only Nazism, but also Fascism used the symbol of the powerful man with the strong self-affirmation of life in himself and in his group. When Fascism and Nazism and early Communism used Nietzsche's categories, they did it with the feeling that the coming nihilism of which Nietzsche spoke would make mankind into a herd of higher animals without creativity, satisfied merely with food and clothes, etc. So this ideology was welcomed by the Fascists and the Nazis. They often used Nietzsche, but they left out one thing. They left out the spiritual aspect. Nietzsche's idea of the superior man includes the bodily and the spiritual or the mental. One of the Nazi leaders said that when he hears the word "spirit" he takes out his pistol, because he felt that this implied the diminution of vitality and creativity. Such ideas were behind the Nazi movement. But do not imagine that we can derive Nazism from

500            A History of Christian Thought

Nietzsche, or from Luther or Hegel for that matter, although some of Nietzsche's formulations have a similarity to the Nazi ideology. But this was only a vulgarization and distortion of ideas which these great men had.

For Nietzsche the idea of the higher race is the aristocratic idea which you can find in all races and nations. It is the vertical idea of racial superiority. It comes from the medieval ideal of the aristocratic person­ality shaped by strict self-discipline. But in Nazism there was the horizontal idea of race, the idea that a particular biological race is superior to others. Then a particular nation or a particular race, like the Nordic race, becomes the group of superior men. Everything becomes vulgar. In this light you can understand better the quasi-religious demonry of Nazism. It was in opposition to the danger of the industrial society symbolized in the idea of the last man who only looks at things with cynicism and without eros.

Nietzsche's affirmation of life goes beyond all this to a classical metaphysical idea, or mythological idea, expressed by the Stoics, the idea of the eternal return. This is the idea that history does not run ahead but returns to its beginning. This is the classical Greek idea of eternal return. It means that everything that happens now happens an infinite number of times. In Thus Spake Zarathustra he described the moment as a door which opens in both directions. In every moment there is a repetition of infinite moments. Everything that happens happens an infinite number of times. This again is symbolic and mythological. If we ask about its meaning, it means the eternalization of the moment. The moment is eternal, not by the presence of eternal life in it, however, as in Schleiermacher and in my own thinking, following the fourth Gospel's idea of eternal life, but for Nietzsche it is a circle. The eternalization of transitory moments means that everything has happened before and will happen again an infinite number of times. It is one of the attempts to understand eternity on the basis of a non-mechanical dynamic naturalism. Religiously it is an affirmation of the eternal meaning of every moment and of everything in every moment. It is eternity not in terms of a hereafter, not in terms of the unique moment into which the eternal breaks, but in terms of any point in a circle from which the circle may start and to which it may return. This

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   501

is the famous idea of the eternal return. What is decisive in it is the affirmation of life. Nietzsche expresses this by having Zarathustra teach his disciples to say that in the experience of death they will affirm every moment of it. This is Nietzsche's eschatology; this is his hope. Although his life was full of misery, in opposition to this he affirmed it infinitely.

All these ideas have had a great influence on the thinking of our time insofar as it deals with problems of ultimate concern. They have influenced many theologians, at least insofar as they try to answer this form of eschatology by some other form, and to show the difference. They have had infinite importance for all preaching which contains apologetic elements. For here was a man who was not holding to a mechanistic, materialistic form of naturalism. It was an ecstatic natu­ralism. When we use the word "naturalism" we should be clear about what type we have in mind. Today we call the mechanistic or material­istic typ of naturalism a reductive naturalism in which everything is reduced to the movement of atoms. It denies that mind and life have any independent reality. They are supposed to be epiphenomenal; phenomenal because they exist and you cannot deny that there is life and spirit; and epi because they are secondary and superficial, and not a part of any substantial reality. That is not a profound philosophy at all. But it is only one form of naturalism. Nietzsche represented quite another one which was great, although presented in a half-demonic form.

Question: You have given a description of Nietzsche, but not a criticism of him. Would you please do so?

Answer: I would like to do so, although this would be a long story if my criticism would take in all the elements of his thought. But let me start with his concept of the will-to-power. I told you that Nietzsche's idea of the will-to-power does not use the terms "will" and "power" in the ordinary sense. Rather, it is the urge toward life in everything that is, even beyond the organic life. It is a metaphysical concept. For the nonhuman dimension the word "urge" would even be more adequate. And "power" is not social, political, or economic power, but rather the self-affirmation of life, not only in the sense of preserving life, but of the

502            A History of Christian Thought

further development of life. In this respect, Nietzsche's idea is an adequate description of life processes as we can observe them in ourselves and in nature, so no criticism is needed. But insofar as the world of norms in relation to the will-to-power is lost in Nietzsche, criticism proves to be necessary. It is precisely this lack of normative principles which has made it possible for the Nazis to misuse Nietzsche. Nietzsche himself had the aristocratic norms. His ideal was the republic of Venice in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. The Strict self-discipline which was characteristic of all members of the aristocratic class was his ideal. So there was not only arbitrariness but also disci­pline. But this discipline had no norms which could be applied to men as a whole. Therefore, people like Heidegger could simply replace the older norms which, according to Nietzsche himself, have disappeared with the death of Cod. I spoke about this last time. Heidegger replaced them by the resolve, the decision to do something without any norm, as Nietzsche also did. Since there is no norm, there is only my will, and this is the highest norm. This "I will" of Nietzsche, his highest norm, is not able to provide criteria for good and evil, so Nietzsche could write his little book, Beyond Good and Evil. This is the one criticism, the lack of norms. The result of this lack is apparent, for it provided the possi­bility of misusing Nietzsche's idea for the sake of an irrational will-to-power as in a phenomenon like Nazism.

I would also have to criticize his doctrine of the eternal return. His idea is a return to the classical circular notion of repetitious time. There is a lack of novelty, of the really new. True, Nietzsche did have a strong emphasis on the new in history. He could speak of the renewal of all values, the transvaluation of values, and the coming of the superior man. There the concept of the new is present. But this happens only within a particular segment of the circle. Nothing absolutely new is created. A symbol such as the kingdom of God as the aim of history is very remote from Nietzsche. Nietzsche denied Augustine's idea that time is running toward something and not toward a point from which it has started. That is, time is going in circles. This was a relapse in Nietzsche, and an inconsistent relapse because he also had the Dar­winian notion of movement from lower to higher forms of life in history.

The Breakdown of the Universal Synthesis   503

A third Criticism would have to focus on the idea of the superior man. The biological increase of perfection in man would not increase the heights of man's spirit. The biological development of man has come to a point from which a new development has started, namely, the development of man's spiritual self-realization in terms of culture, religion, and ethics. This new series of developments cannot be en­hanced by any further improvement of bodily existence. One could say that with respect to nature, man is an end, just as with respect to history, the kingdom of God is an end. Nietzsche was driven by naturalism to a misunderstanding of the new beginning which was inaugurated in life when the first man used the first word to describe the universal.

Then we can also say that his idea of the death of God is only relatively true. For the God of the tradition is still alive and Nietzsche himself introduced another God, this divine-demonic being which he called life. I referred you to the last collection of fragments in his Will to Power. It gives an ecstatic vision of the irrationality and paradoxical character of life as a whole, and calls for obedience to this life by affirming it as it is. He certainly is not atheistic in the popular nonsensical term. But he has a different God than the God of the religious tradition, especially of the Christian tradition. This holds true as well of the Asian tradition. He denied the Asian tradition when he denied Schopenhauer who introduced the Asian tradition into the Western world. He denied both traditions. Yet, I would say that the presupposition of his negation is an awareness of eternity, and this awareness of eternity was as much alive in him as in every human being.

I could also go into his theory of resentment and theory of morality, which is self-contradictory, because the aristocratic groups which im­posed their ethics upon the masses had their own ethical norms inde­pendent of individual willfulness. Nietzsche is an irrational prophet, a naturalistic prophet. But Christian theologians can learn very much from him. I regretted nothing so much as the fact that he could be so misused by Nazism. For this reason he lost much of his significance in Germany, and probably also in other countries.