알라딘: 스피노자 서간집
스피노자 서간집 | 대우고전총서 48
B. 스피노자 (지은이),이근세 (옮긴이)아카넷2018-12-27
정가
26,000원
판매가
24,700원 (5%, 1,300원 할인)
10.0100자평(1)리뷰(0)
이 책 어때요?
476쪽
128*188mm (B6)
476g
ISBN : 9788957336182
책소개
1925년 카를 게브하르트(Carl Gebhardt)가 편집한 『스피노자 전집(SPINOZA OPERA)』의 제4권 『서간집(EPISTOLAE)』에 포함된 84통의 서신들을 완역한 것이다. 17세기의 철학자들이 주고받은 서신들은 오늘날의 논문집과 유사한 역할을 담당했다. 동시에 서신들이 단지 익명적인 것은 아니기 때문에 서신들을 통해 당시 철학자들의 구체적인 태도를 엿볼 수 있다.
서신은 한 철학 안에서 제시된 세계관과 인간관이 그 철학을 산출한 철학자의 삶에서 실질적으로 표현되고 있는지의 여부를 판단하게 해주는 독보적인 문헌이다. 따라서 철학자들의 서신을 통해 우리는 그들의 철학 체계를 단지 이론 체계로 보는 한계를 벗어나 철학적 이해에 구체성을 부여할 수 있다. 스피노자의 서신도 역시 같은 모습을 보여주며 자신의 철학 체계에 대한 직접적인 해설과 함께 그의 실천적 태도를 보여주는 1차 문헌인 것이다.
목차
ㅇ 서신 1. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 2. 스피노자가 올덴부르크에게―서신 1에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 3. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게―서신 2에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 4. 스피노자가 헨리 올덴부르크에게―서신 3에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 5. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게―서신 4에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 6. 스피노자가 헨리 올덴부르크에게
ㅇ 서신 7. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게―서신 6에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 8. 시몬 데 브리스가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 9. 스피노자가 시몬 데 브리스에게―서신 8에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 10. 스피노자가 시몬 데 브리스에게
ㅇ 서신 11. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게―서신 6에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 12. 스피노자가 뤼도웨이크 메이어르에게
ㅇ 서신 13. 스피노자가 헨리 올덴부르크에게―서신 11에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 14. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게―서신 13에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 15. 스피노자가 뤼도웨이크 메이어르에게
ㅇ 서신 16. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 17. 스피노자가 피터르 발링에게
ㅇ 서신 18. 블리엔베르그가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 19. 스피노자가 블리엔베르그에게―서신 18에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 20. 블리엔베르그가 스피노자에게―서신 19에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 21. 스피노자가 블리엔베르그에게―서신 20에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 22. 블리엔베르그가 스피노자에게―서신 21에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 23. 스피노자가 블리엔베르그에게―서신 22에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 24. 블리엔베르그가 스피노자에게―서신 23에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 25. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 26. 스피노자가 헨리 올덴부르크에게―서신 25에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 27. 스피노자가 블리엔베르그에게―서신 24에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 28. 스피노자가 요하네스 바우와메스테르에게
ㅇ 서신 29. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 30. 스피노자가 헨리 올덴부르크에게―서신 29에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 31. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게―서신 30에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 32. 스피노자가 헨리 올덴부르크에게―서신 31에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 33. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게―서신 32에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 34. 스피노자가 후드에게
ㅇ 서신 35. 스피노자가 후드에게
ㅇ 서신 36. 스피노자가 후드에게
ㅇ 서신 37. 스피노자가 요하네스 바우와메스테르에게
ㅇ 서신 38. 스피노자가 요하네스 판 데르 메르에게
ㅇ 서신 39. 스피노자가 야리그 옐레스에게
ㅇ 서신 40. 스피노자가 야리그 옐레스에게
ㅇ 서신 41. 스피노자가 야리그 옐레스에게
ㅇ 서신 42. 람베르트 판 벨튀센이 야콥 오스텐스에게
ㅇ 서신 43. 스피노자가 야콥 오스텐스에게―서신 42에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 44. 스피노자가 야리그 옐레스에게
ㅇ 서신 45. 라이프니츠가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 46. 스피노자가 라이프니츠에게―서신 45에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 47. 파브리키우스가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 48. 스피노자가 파브리키우스에게―서신 47에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 48-2. 스피노자가 야리그 옐레스에게
ㅇ 서신 49. 스피노자가 요하네스 게오르기우스 그래비우스에게
ㅇ 서신 50. 스피노자가 야리그 옐레스에게
ㅇ 서신 51. 휘호 복셀이 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 52. 스피노자가 휘호 복셀에게―서신 51에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 53. 휘호 복셀이 스피노자에게―서신 52에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 54. 스피노자가 휘호 복셀에게―서신 53에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 55. 휘호 복셀이 스피노자에게―서신 54에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 56. 스피노자가 휘호 복셀에게―서신 55에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 57. 에렌프리트 발터 폰 치른하우스가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 58. 스피노자가 슐러에게―서신 57에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 59. 에렌프리트 발터 폰 치른하우스가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 60. 스피노자가 에렌프리트 발터 폰 치른하우스에게―서신 59에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 61. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 62. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 63. 슐러가 스피노자에게―서신 60에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 64. 스피노자가 슐러에게―서신 63에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 65. 에렌프리트 발터 폰 치른하우스가 스피노자에게―서신 64에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 66. 스피노자가 에렌프리트 발터 폰 치른하우스에게―서신 65에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 67. 알베르트 뷔르흐가 스피노자에게
ㅇ 서신 68. 스피노자가 헨리 올덴부르크에게―서신 61에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 69. 스피노자가 람베르트 판 벨튀센에게
ㅇ 서신 70. 슐러가 스피노자에게―서신 66에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 71. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게―서신 68에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 72. 스피노자가 슐러에게―서신 70에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 73. 스피노자가 헨리 올덴부르크에게―서신 71에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 74. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게―서신 73에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 75. 스피노자가 헨리 올덴부르크에게―서신 74에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 76. 스피노자가 알베르트 뷔르흐에게―서신 67에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 77. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게―서신 75에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 78. 스피노자가 헨리 올덴부르크에게―서신 77에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 79. 헨리 올덴부르크가 스피노자에게―서신 78에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 80. 에렌프리트 발터 폰 치른하우스가 스피노자에게―서신 72에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 81. 스피노자가 에렌프리트 발터 폰 치른하우스에게―서신 80에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 82. 에렌프리트 발터 폰 치른하우스가 스피노자에게―서신 81에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 83. 스피노자가 에렌프리트 발터 폰 치른하우스에게―서신 82에 대한 회신
ㅇ 서신 84. 스피노자가 벗에게
옮긴이 해제
옮긴이 후기
접기
책속에서
책속에서
스피노자의 사상은 요컨대 철학적 논의에 막대한 양분을 제공 하는 유신론과 무신론의 논쟁이라는 맥락에서 파악해야 한다. 이 논쟁은 형이상학과 더불어 윤리학, 즉 삶의 구체적 방향을 결정지을 수 있기 때문에 피상적으로 접근해서는 안 될 것이다.(p428) - 겨울호랑이
스피노자가 인정하는 신의 개념은 어떠한 것인가? 그의 신은 인격신이 아니다. 목적성을 가진 창조, 혹은 무로부터의창조(creatio ex nihilo)는 인격신을 통해 이루어지는 것이다. 즉 지성을 통해 창조할 세계를 구상하고 의지와 힘을 통해 세계를 현존케 하는 신 개념을 필요로 하는 것이 창조이다. 그러나 스피노자는 인격신 개념에서 신 안에서의 간극과 결여 및 불완전성을 보고 있기 때문에 세계가 지성에 의해 미리 구상되고 의지나 힘에 의해 나중에 실현되는 방식을 받아들일 수 없다.(p439) 접기 - 겨울호랑이
이 세계는 여러 세계들 가운데 선택된 세계가 아니라 유일한 전체일 뿐이다. 이 세계는 어떤 지성에 의해 미리 생각되고 창조된 것이 아니라, 계획과 실현 간의 그 어떠한 간극도 없이 그 자체로 영원으로부터 존재하는 것이다. 신이 바로 이 세계이다. 스피노자 철학의 핵심 을 표현하는 ˝신 즉 자연(Deus sive Natura)˝이 바로 이런 의미이다. 자연이라는 자연주의적 존재론을 확립하고 인간이 행복에 이르는 길을 이 존재론의 토대 위에 그리는 것이 스피노자 윤리학의 골자이다. 접기 - 겨울호랑이
인간의 본질은 자신의 존재를 보존하려는 욕망이다. 스피노자의 윤리학은 욕망의 윤리학이다. 존재를 보존하고 완전한 자기 자신이 되는 것이 현존자의 유일한 규범이고 목표이다. 원초적 힘과 욕망이 인간의 근본을 이룬다. 이런 근원적 존재 보존 노력이, 스피노자가 코나투스(conatus)라 명명하는 인간의 본질이다. 욕망은 본질적으로 힘의 증진, 더 큰 완전성의 획득, 즉 기쁨으로 향한다.(p441) 접기 - 겨울호랑이
스피노자의 욕망의 윤리학은 실존적이고 행복주의이다. 욕망의 윤리학은 인식이고 여정이며, 구조이고 지혜이며, 엄격함이고 기쁨이다. 욕망의 완성은 완전한 기쁨이며 극도의 존재 의식이다. 이런 욕망의 여정은 지극히 험준하지만 도달할 수 있는 길이다. 그러나 모든 고귀한 것은 드문 만큼 어려운 것이다. (Sed omniapraeclara tam difficilia, quam rara sunt.)(p445) 접기 - 겨울호랑이
추천글
이 책을 추천한 다른 분들 :
한겨레 신문
- 한겨레 신문 2019년 1월 11일자
연합뉴스
- 연합뉴스 2019년 1월 15일자
저자 및 역자소개
B. 스피노자 (Baruch de Spinoza) (지은이)
저자파일
최고의 작품 투표
신간알림 신청
데카르트, 라이프니츠와 함께 근대 합리론을 대변하는 철학자이다. 그는 유태교 목사가 되기를 거부하고 자유롭게 사유하고 그것을 발표하는 데 자신의 일생을 바쳤다. 그의 사상은 정신과 물질을 구분하는 데카르트의 이원론을 극복하려는 데서 시작한다. 따라서 무한성에 대한 사상, 수학적 사고방식, 근대 자연과학의 원리들, 자연적 종교의 개념과 플라톤 철학의 반영 등이 그의 사상의 특징으로 부각된다. 이는 우주 의 본질을 실체 또는 자연이라고 하여 신과 실체와 자연이 하나라고 보는 데서 잘 나타난다. 그가 생전에 출판한 책은 『데카르트의 철학의 원리』, 『신학-정치론』 두 편이고, 『에티카』, 『정치학 논고』, 『지성 개선론』, 『신과 인간과 인간의 행복에 대한 짧은 논문』 등은 모두 유작으로 그의 친구들에 의해 출판되었다. 접기
최근작 : <에티카>,<스피노자 서간집>,<신학-정치론> … 총 74종 (모두보기)
이근세 (옮긴이)
경희대학교 철학과를 졸업하고 벨기에 루뱅 대학교 철학고등연구소(ISP)에서 박사학위를 취득했다. 브뤼셀 통·번역대학교(ISTI) 강사를 역임하고 귀국하여 현재 국민대학교 교양대학 교수로 재직하고 있다. 주요 연구 분야는 서양 근대 철학, 프랑스 철학이며, 점차 연구의 초점을 동서 비교철학으로 이동시키고 있다.
저서로 『효율성, 문명의 편견』 등이 있고, 역서로 『스피노자와 도덕의 문제』 『변신론』 『전략: 고대 그리스에서 현대 중국까지』 등이 있다. 연구 논문으로는 「스피노자의 존재론 기초」 「스피노자의 철학에 있어서 시간성과 윤리」 「블롱델의 행동 철학과 라이프니츠의 실체적 연결고리 가설」 「프랑수아 줄리앙의 비교철학에서 중국과 서양의 효율성 개념 비교」 「야코비의 사유 구조와 스피노자의 영향」 「이념의 문제와 글쓰기 전략」 「동아시아적 이념의 가능성」 「모리스 블롱델의 현상학적 방법론」 「데카르트와 코기토 논쟁」 「조선 천주교 박해와 관용의 원리」 외 다수가 있다.
접기
최근작 : <효율성, 문명의 편견> … 총 12종 (모두보기)
출판사 제공 책소개
서간집 ̄한 철학 안에서 제시된 세계관과 인간관이 그 철학을 산출한
철학자의 삶에서 표현되는 방식을 보여주는 독보적인 문헌
이 책은 1925년 카를 게브하르트(Carl Gebhardt)가 편집한 『스피노자 전집(SPINOZA OPERA)』의 제4권 『서간집(EPISTOLAE)』에 포함된 84통의 서신들을 완역한 것이다.
17세기의 철학자들이 주고받은 서신들은 오늘날의 논문집과 유사한 역할을 담당했다. 동시에 서신들이 단지 익명적인 것은 아니기 때문에 서신들을 통해 당시 철학자들의 구체적인 태도를 엿볼 수 있다. 서신은 한 철학 안에서 제시된 세계관과 인간관이 그 철학을 산출한 철학자의 삶에서 실질적으로 표현되고 있는지의 여부를 판단하게 해주는 독보적인 문헌이다. 따라서 철학자들의 서신을 통해 우리는 그들의 철학 체계를 단지 이론 체계로 보는 한계를 벗어나 철학적 이해에 구체성을 부여할 수 있다. 스피노자의 서신도 역시 같은 모습을 보여주며 자신의 철학 체계에 대한 직접적인 해설과 함께 그의 실천적 태도를 보여주는 1차 문헌인 것이다.
모든 커다란 철학이 다양한 해석을 낳는 것은 주지의 사실이지만 스피노자의 철학만큼 상반된 해석 대상이 되어 온 철학 체계는 드물 것이다. 그의 사후(1677)부터 현대까지 스피노자의 철학은 끊임없이 다양한 관점에서 해석되어 왔다. 스피노자는 18세기에는 무신론적 이성론의 원형으로, 19세기에는 특히 독일에서 신비적·범신론적·종교적 철학의 이미지로 나타났다. 1993년 파리1대학에서 35명의 스피노자 전문가들이 발표한 논문집 『20세기의 스피노자』는 스피노자를 “혁명적” 철학자로서 “모든 사유 체계의 변천의 매개자”로 소개하고 있다. 이 저작에 실린 논문들은 스피노자와 베르그손, 브런슈빅, 바슐라르, 들뢰즈, 레비나스, 칼 포퍼, 하이데거, 러셀, 한나 아렌트 등 다른 철학자들의 비교에서부터 시작하여 문학, 마르크스 사상, 프로이트와 라캉의 정신분석학 등과의 관계를 조명함으로써 스피노자 철학이 지닌 의미의 함축성과 다
양성을 폭넓게 제시하고 있다. 이런 연구는 스피노자 철학에 대한 연구가 세계적으로 얼마나 활발히 진행되고 있는지를 상징적으로 보여준다.
스피노자 철학의 중요성이 부각되면서 최근 20여 년간 국내에서도 스피노자에 관한 연구는 활발히 진행되어 왔다. 스피노자의 사상은 한편으로는 『소론』, 『지성개선론』, 『데카르트의 철학원리』 등의 초기 저작들 및 『에티카』에서 전개되는 존재론, 인식론, 감정론, 윤리학, 다른 한편으로는 『신학정치론』과 『정치론』에서 중점적으로 다루어지는 신학 및 정치철학으로 크게 구분될 수 있다. 이미 『에티카』나 『신학정치론』 등의 완결된 주저는 여러 연구자들에 의해 번역 출간되었고 초기의 미완성 저작들도 부분적으로나마 번역되어 소개되었으며, 다수의 스피노자 관련 연구서 및 교양 저작들도 발간되었다. 그러나 정작 영미, 유럽권의 모든 스피노자 전문가들이 1차 문헌으로서 적극적으로 활용해왔으며 스피노자 전집에 당당히 포함되어 있는 서간집은 국내에 전혀 소개되지 않고 있다. 단지 몇몇 연구자들에 의해서 전문 논문에서 다루어질 뿐이다. 이 책을 통해 국내 스피노자 연구의 이 같은 공백이 메워졌으면 한다
서신이라는 형식 때문에 철학자들은 상대방의 언어를 사용하는 경우가 많으므로 서간집은 비교적 쉬운 언어로 그들의 사상이 표현된 값진 자료를 제공해준다. 또한 서신들을 통해 우리는 철학 사상의 진화 과정 및 시대적 배경 등을 확인할 수 있기 때문에, 서간집과 함께 철학 작품을 고찰할 경우 철학 체계에 대한 이해도를 극대화할 수 있다. 실제로 스피노자의 서간집은 철학적 토론 외에도 집필 과정, 용어 변화, 출판 현황, 시대 배경 등을 구체적으로 알려주기 때문에 그의 사상을 재구성하는 데 필수적인 역할을 한다.
철학자의 사상을 이해하기 위해 그의 주저들을 해독해야 함은 물론이다. 그러나 철학 저작들은 주요 개념이나 체계에 대한 구체적 예를 제시하지 않는 경우가 많다. 우리는 철학자의 서신을 통해 주요 개념의 풍부한 예시를 획득함으로써 이론 체계를 깊이 이해할 수 있을 뿐 아니라 이론 체계의 확장성을 확인할 수 있다. 실제로 스피노자의 서간집이 없었다면, 그의 존재론에서 매우 난해하고도 중요한 개념인 속성이나 무한 양태에 대한 구체적 이해는 불가능했을 것이다. 또한 ‘예수의 부활’ 같은 민감한 사안은 그의 신학 저작에서도 잘 다루어지지 않고 있지만, 서신에서는 적극적 설명의 대상이 되고 있다. 따라서 스피노자의 서간집은 후대의 연구자들에게 보조적 역할을 넘어서 그의 철학 체계를 온전히 재정립하기 위한 독보적 문헌이다. 접기
---------
『스피노자 서간집』과 사유의 실천
이근세 국민대 · 교양대학
승인 2019.01.29
https://www.kyosu.net/news/articleView.html?idxno=43768
책을 말하다_ 『스피노자 서간집』 (베네딕트 데 스피노자 지음, 이근세 옮김, 아카넷, 2018.12)
“오늘날의 신학자들이 제 저작으로 불쾌해하고 그들의 습관적인 적개심으로 저를 비난할까 걱정이 됩니다. (......) 이 저작이 설교자들을 다소 불쾌하게 할 수 있는 내용을 선생님께 알려드린다면 다음과 같습니다. 저는 그들이 신에게 귀속시키는 신의 여러 속성들을 피조물들로서 간주하며, 그들이 편견 때문에 피조물로 간주하는 다른 것들을 신의 속성들로 간주합니다. 저는 그들이 신의 속성들을 제대로 이해하고 있지 못하다는 것을 제시하려고 합니다. 나아가 저는 제가 알고 있는 저자들이 그렇게 하듯이 신과 자연을 분리하지 않습니다.”
영국 왕립학술원 초대 사무총장인 헨리 올덴부르크에게 스피노자가 1661년에 보낸 편지의 일부이다. 편지에서 나타나듯이 스피노자는 자신의 철학이 지닌 논란의 성격을 정확히 자각하고 있었다. 그는 유대인으로서 유대교를 거부한 이유로 동족에게 저주 섞인 파문을 당했고 서구문명을 크게 지배해온 기독교를 인정하지도 않았다. 스피노자는 지성을 통해 창조할 세계를 구상하고 의지와 능력을 통해 세계를 창조하는 인격신 개념, 그리고 이 개념에 근거한 창조론을 정면으로 부정한다. 스피노자는 인격신 개념에서 신 안에서의 간극, 결여, 불완전성을 보고 있기 때문에 세계가 지성에 의해 미리 구상되고 의지나 능력에 의해 논리적으로든 존재론적으로든 나중에 실현되는 방식을 받아들일 수 없다. 그가 인정하는 신은 지성이나 의지를 본질로 갖는 신이 아니다. 스피노자의 신은 인격적 존재가 아니며 계획과 실현 간의 어떤 간극도 없이 자기 본성의 필연성에 따라 존재하고 작용하는 자연 전체이다. 그러나 스피노자는 이런 생각이 담긴 『에티카』의 출간을 포기했다. 그의 생전에 출간된 『데카르트의 철학의 원리』는 스피노자 자신의 철학을 포함하지 않았고 『신학정치론』은 익명으로 출간되었다. 우리는 우리 자신의 생각을 완전히 감출 수 있는가?
▲ 베네딕트 데 스피노자 사진출처=구글
서구 문명권에서 계시종교의 역할은 막대한 것이고 모든 사상가는 어떤 방식으로든 기성 종교에 대한 견해 표명을 요구 받았다. 『스피노자 서간집』은 자기 생각을 전면적으로 드러낼 수도 없고 온전히 숨길 수도 없었던 스피노자의 삶의 전략이 담긴 문헌이다. 편지는 사적(私的)인 동시에 상대방이 있는 사회적 차원의 글이다. 스피노자의 편지들은 난해하기로 악명 높은 그의 철학 체계에 대한 해석의 권위가 보장된 문헌으로서 스피노자 철학의 풍성한 이해를 가능케 한다. 『스피노자 서간집』은 스피노자 철학에 대한 직접적인 해설과 함께 ‘사유의 실천’을 보여준다. 스피노자는 철학적 주제를 보편적인 방식으로 다루면서도 자신이 누구와 서신을 교환하고 있는지 정확히 알고 있다. 그는 상대방의 태도에 따라 자신의 태도를 규정함으로써 소모적인 논쟁에 휘말리지 않는다. 이 같은 신중함은 자기 자신에서 이탈하지 않는 가운데 타인을 이해하는 독특한 방식이며 그의 사상 체계로부터 도출되는 깊은 반성과 숙고의 결실이다. 모든 철학자가 그렇겠지만 스피노자에게 사유와 글쓰기는 삶의 가장 큰 부분이었고 서구의 지배적 담론과 엇갈린 길을 가던 그에게 편지는 자기 사유를 실천하는 조심스러운 통로였다.
『스피노자 서간집』은 1925년 칼 게브하르트(Carl Gebhardt)가 편집한 『스피노자 전집』(SPINOZA OPERA)의 제4권 『서간집』(EPISTOLAE)에 포함된 84통의 서신들의 번역이다.
『스피노자 서간집』과 사유의 실천
이근세 국민대 · 교양대학
승인 2019.01.29
https://www.kyosu.net/news/articleView.html?idxno=43768
책을 말하다_ 『스피노자 서간집』 (베네딕트 데 스피노자 지음, 이근세 옮김, 아카넷, 2018.12)
“오늘날의 신학자들이 제 저작으로 불쾌해하고 그들의 습관적인 적개심으로 저를 비난할까 걱정이 됩니다. (......) 이 저작이 설교자들을 다소 불쾌하게 할 수 있는 내용을 선생님께 알려드린다면 다음과 같습니다. 저는 그들이 신에게 귀속시키는 신의 여러 속성들을 피조물들로서 간주하며, 그들이 편견 때문에 피조물로 간주하는 다른 것들을 신의 속성들로 간주합니다. 저는 그들이 신의 속성들을 제대로 이해하고 있지 못하다는 것을 제시하려고 합니다. 나아가 저는 제가 알고 있는 저자들이 그렇게 하듯이 신과 자연을 분리하지 않습니다.”
영국 왕립학술원 초대 사무총장인 헨리 올덴부르크에게 스피노자가 1661년에 보낸 편지의 일부이다. 편지에서 나타나듯이 스피노자는 자신의 철학이 지닌 논란의 성격을 정확히 자각하고 있었다. 그는 유대인으로서 유대교를 거부한 이유로 동족에게 저주 섞인 파문을 당했고 서구문명을 크게 지배해온 기독교를 인정하지도 않았다. 스피노자는 지성을 통해 창조할 세계를 구상하고 의지와 능력을 통해 세계를 창조하는 인격신 개념, 그리고 이 개념에 근거한 창조론을 정면으로 부정한다. 스피노자는 인격신 개념에서 신 안에서의 간극, 결여, 불완전성을 보고 있기 때문에 세계가 지성에 의해 미리 구상되고 의지나 능력에 의해 논리적으로든 존재론적으로든 나중에 실현되는 방식을 받아들일 수 없다. 그가 인정하는 신은 지성이나 의지를 본질로 갖는 신이 아니다. 스피노자의 신은 인격적 존재가 아니며 계획과 실현 간의 어떤 간극도 없이 자기 본성의 필연성에 따라 존재하고 작용하는 자연 전체이다. 그러나 스피노자는 이런 생각이 담긴 『에티카』의 출간을 포기했다. 그의 생전에 출간된 『데카르트의 철학의 원리』는 스피노자 자신의 철학을 포함하지 않았고 『신학정치론』은 익명으로 출간되었다. 우리는 우리 자신의 생각을 완전히 감출 수 있는가?
▲ 베네딕트 데 스피노자 사진출처=구글
서구 문명권에서 계시종교의 역할은 막대한 것이고 모든 사상가는 어떤 방식으로든 기성 종교에 대한 견해 표명을 요구 받았다. 『스피노자 서간집』은 자기 생각을 전면적으로 드러낼 수도 없고 온전히 숨길 수도 없었던 스피노자의 삶의 전략이 담긴 문헌이다. 편지는 사적(私的)인 동시에 상대방이 있는 사회적 차원의 글이다. 스피노자의 편지들은 난해하기로 악명 높은 그의 철학 체계에 대한 해석의 권위가 보장된 문헌으로서 스피노자 철학의 풍성한 이해를 가능케 한다. 『스피노자 서간집』은 스피노자 철학에 대한 직접적인 해설과 함께 ‘사유의 실천’을 보여준다. 스피노자는 철학적 주제를 보편적인 방식으로 다루면서도 자신이 누구와 서신을 교환하고 있는지 정확히 알고 있다. 그는 상대방의 태도에 따라 자신의 태도를 규정함으로써 소모적인 논쟁에 휘말리지 않는다. 이 같은 신중함은 자기 자신에서 이탈하지 않는 가운데 타인을 이해하는 독특한 방식이며 그의 사상 체계로부터 도출되는 깊은 반성과 숙고의 결실이다. 모든 철학자가 그렇겠지만 스피노자에게 사유와 글쓰기는 삶의 가장 큰 부분이었고 서구의 지배적 담론과 엇갈린 길을 가던 그에게 편지는 자기 사유를 실천하는 조심스러운 통로였다.
『스피노자 서간집』은 1925년 칼 게브하르트(Carl Gebhardt)가 편집한 『스피노자 전집』(SPINOZA OPERA)의 제4권 『서간집』(EPISTOLAE)에 포함된 84통의 서신들의 번역이다.
서양근대철학자들이 남긴 서신은 그들의 주저들을 압도할 정도로 풍부한 내용을 담고 있다. 데카르트 전집 11권 중 서신이 5권이고 라이프니츠의 서신은 2만 통이 넘는다. 작은 시작에 불과한 『스피노자 서간집』이지만 여타 서신 번역과 연구의 촉매제로 쓰였으면 한다.
이근세 국민대학교·교양대학
경희대학교 철학과를 졸업하고 벨기에 루뱅대학교 철학고등연구소(ISP)에서 박사학위를 취득했다. 주요 연구 분야는 서양근대철학, 프랑스철학이며, 점차 연구의 초점을 동서비교담론으로 이동시키고 있다. 주요 저서로는 『효율성, 문명의 편견』, 『철학의 물음들』 등이 있다.
저작권자 © 교수신문 무단전재 및 재배포 금지
----------
이근세 국민대학교·교양대학
경희대학교 철학과를 졸업하고 벨기에 루뱅대학교 철학고등연구소(ISP)에서 박사학위를 취득했다. 주요 연구 분야는 서양근대철학, 프랑스철학이며, 점차 연구의 초점을 동서비교담론으로 이동시키고 있다. 주요 저서로는 『효율성, 문명의 편견』, 『철학의 물음들』 등이 있다.
저작권자 © 교수신문 무단전재 및 재배포 금지
----------
스피노자 연구의 빈칸 메워 주는 서간집
스피노자 서간집
스피노자 지음, 이근세 옮김/아카넷·2만6000원
17세기 철학자들이 주고받은 서신들은 오늘날 논문집과 유사한 구실을 했다. 또한 서신은 출판된 저서보다 특정 사안에 대해 필자의 관점을 더 구체적이고 용이하게 접할 수 있게 해주는 좋은 통로다. 철학적 토론 외에도 집필 과정이나 용어 변화, 시대 배경 등을 구체적으로 알려주는 문서이기에 후대 연구자들에겐 중요성이 저서 못지않다.
<스피노자 서간집> 또한 바뤼흐 스피노자(1632~1677) 연구에서 중요성이 높은 문서다. 이 서간집이 없었다면 그의 존재론에서 매우 난해하고도 중요한 개념인 ‘속성’이나 ‘무한 양태’에 대한 구체적인 이해는 불가능했을 것이며, 예수의 부활 같은 민감한 사안에 대한 설명도 알 수 없었으리라는 것이 학계의 평가다. <스피노자 서간집>은 1925년 카를 게브하르트가 편집한 ‘스피노자 전집’ 제4권에 포함된 84통의 서신들을 완역한 것으로 국내 초역이다. 벨기에 루뱅대학교에서 스피노자 연구 등으로 박사 학위를 받은 이근세 국민대 교양대학 교수가 번역을 맡았다.
바뤼흐 스피노자의 초상. 한겨레 자료사진
스피노자는 유대교 신앙을 버렸다는 이유로 24살에 파문당한 이후로 도시들을 떠돌며 렌즈를 연마하며 생계를 이으며 어렵게 생활하다 45살의 젊은 나이로 사망한 것으로 잘 알려져 있다. 하지만 이 서간집에는 영국 왕립학술원 초대 사무총장 헨리 올덴부르크나 암스테르담의 시장이자 수학자인 요하네스 후드 등 유력 인물들과 철학자 등과 주고받은 편지들이 실려 있어, 당시 학계에 널리 퍼진 스피노자의 명성을 확인할 수 있다. 또한 스피노자가 철학과 신학만이 아니라 수학과 과학을 두고 토론을 벌이는 대목에선 철학과 과학을 모두 섭렵한 당대 지식인의 모습을 엿볼 수 있다.
김지훈 기자
원문보기:
http://www.hani.co.kr/arti/culture/book/877962.html#csidx4515ddb52026ef8ae8fec7161804c9d
------
Opera Posthuma
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Baruch Spinoza's Opera Posthuma comprise his works that were published posthumously in 1677, the year of Spinoza's death, by some of his closest friends. Four of these are well known: the Ethica, the Tractatus Politicus, the Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione, and the Epistolae (letters by Spinoza to correspondents, expounding aspects of his philosophy). The fifth and final work of the Opera Posthuma is a grammar of the Hebrew language, Compendium Grammatices Linguae Hebraeae.
Spinoza's Short Treatise on God, Man, and His Well-Being - expressing opinions sharply conflicting with the dominant Calvinist theology of his time as with the Judaism practiced by the Amsterdam Jewish community - was not included in the Opera Posthuma. It was only published much later, on the basis of two Dutch translations of it which were discovered about 1810."[1]
스피노자 지음, 이근세 옮김/아카넷·2만6000원
17세기 철학자들이 주고받은 서신들은 오늘날 논문집과 유사한 구실을 했다. 또한 서신은 출판된 저서보다 특정 사안에 대해 필자의 관점을 더 구체적이고 용이하게 접할 수 있게 해주는 좋은 통로다. 철학적 토론 외에도 집필 과정이나 용어 변화, 시대 배경 등을 구체적으로 알려주는 문서이기에 후대 연구자들에겐 중요성이 저서 못지않다.
<스피노자 서간집> 또한 바뤼흐 스피노자(1632~1677) 연구에서 중요성이 높은 문서다. 이 서간집이 없었다면 그의 존재론에서 매우 난해하고도 중요한 개념인 ‘속성’이나 ‘무한 양태’에 대한 구체적인 이해는 불가능했을 것이며, 예수의 부활 같은 민감한 사안에 대한 설명도 알 수 없었으리라는 것이 학계의 평가다. <스피노자 서간집>은 1925년 카를 게브하르트가 편집한 ‘스피노자 전집’ 제4권에 포함된 84통의 서신들을 완역한 것으로 국내 초역이다. 벨기에 루뱅대학교에서 스피노자 연구 등으로 박사 학위를 받은 이근세 국민대 교양대학 교수가 번역을 맡았다.
바뤼흐 스피노자의 초상. 한겨레 자료사진
스피노자는 유대교 신앙을 버렸다는 이유로 24살에 파문당한 이후로 도시들을 떠돌며 렌즈를 연마하며 생계를 이으며 어렵게 생활하다 45살의 젊은 나이로 사망한 것으로 잘 알려져 있다. 하지만 이 서간집에는 영국 왕립학술원 초대 사무총장 헨리 올덴부르크나 암스테르담의 시장이자 수학자인 요하네스 후드 등 유력 인물들과 철학자 등과 주고받은 편지들이 실려 있어, 당시 학계에 널리 퍼진 스피노자의 명성을 확인할 수 있다. 또한 스피노자가 철학과 신학만이 아니라 수학과 과학을 두고 토론을 벌이는 대목에선 철학과 과학을 모두 섭렵한 당대 지식인의 모습을 엿볼 수 있다.
김지훈 기자
원문보기:
http://www.hani.co.kr/arti/culture/book/877962.html#csidx4515ddb52026ef8ae8fec7161804c9d
------
Opera Posthuma
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Baruch Spinoza's Opera Posthuma comprise his works that were published posthumously in 1677, the year of Spinoza's death, by some of his closest friends. Four of these are well known: the Ethica, the Tractatus Politicus, the Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione, and the Epistolae (letters by Spinoza to correspondents, expounding aspects of his philosophy). The fifth and final work of the Opera Posthuma is a grammar of the Hebrew language, Compendium Grammatices Linguae Hebraeae.
Spinoza's Short Treatise on God, Man, and His Well-Being - expressing opinions sharply conflicting with the dominant Calvinist theology of his time as with the Judaism practiced by the Amsterdam Jewish community - was not included in the Opera Posthuma. It was only published much later, on the basis of two Dutch translations of it which were discovered about 1810."[1]
External links[edit]
Entry in Jewish Virtual Library
Opera posthuma Amsterdam 1677. Complete photographic reproduction, ed. by F. Mignini (Quodlibet publishing house website)
This article about a book on language, linguistics or translation is a stub. You can help Wikipedia by expanding it.
---------
Extracts from Spinoza’s Opera Posthuma
https://static1.squarespace.com/static/55f6d5bde4b02cbdec67622e/t/57f40a4d725e25cc3e6e612d/1475611213495/MONO08.pdf
Extracts
from Spinoza’s Opera Posthuma Notes by G. W. Leibniz (1678)
Individuation
in Leibniz and Spinoza
A
Note on De Mairan and Spinozism
Extracts
from Spinoza’s Opera Posthuma Notes by G. W. Leibniz (1678)
Extracts
from Spinoza’s Opera Posthuma Notes by G. W. Leibniz (1678)
Ethics Part I
Ethics Part II
Ethics Part III
Ethics Part IV
Ethics Part V
Individuation
in Leibniz and Spinoza Lee C. Rice Marquette University
1.
Introduction: The Problem in Leibniz
2.
The Logical Model
3.
The Physical Model
4.
Spinozistic Rejoinders
A
Selective Leibniz-Spinoza Bibliography
A
Note on De Mairan and Spinozism Frederick
Ablondi Hendrix College
NASS
Officers & Editorial Board (1998-99)
NASS
Monographs, Purchase Prices
An
International & Interdisciplinary Series
-------------
North
American Spinoza Society
NASS
MONOGRAPH #8 (1999)
Extracts
from Spinoza’s Opera Posthuma Notes by G. W. Leibniz (1678)
Translated by
Samuel Shirley
Individuation
in Leibniz and Spinoza
Lee C. Rice
Marquette University
A
Note on De Mairan and Spinozism
Frederick Ablondi
Hendrix College
Copyright,
1999, North American Spinoza Society
Baltimore,
Maryland
Contents
NASS
Monograph #8
Extracts
from Spinoza’s Opera Posthuma
Notes
by G. W. Leibniz (1678)
Introduction by Lee
Rice..................................... ................................3
Translation by Samuel
Shirley............................. ................................7
Individuation
in Leibniz and Spinoza
Lee
C. Rice
Marquette University.......................................
..............................13
A
Note on De Mairan and Spinozism
Frederick
Ablondi
Hendrix College........................................................
..............................33
Extracts
from Spinoza’s Opera Posthuma Notes by G. W. Leibniz (1678)
Introduction
Lee C. Rice
In
1678, after receiving the Opera Posthuma of
Spinoza, Leibniz wrote a set of notes on the Ethica. These notes first appeared in print in an edition by Grua,[1] and the Latin
text was subsequently reprinted with French translation and commentary by
Bouveresse.[2] Later in 1678
Leibniz was to write a detailed and more critical analysis of Ethica I, entitled De Deo, whose Latin text with French translation has been published
by Foucher de Careil.[3] Later, during the
period 1706-1710, Leibniz would also write his Animadversiones ad Wachteri librum recondita Hebraeorum philosophia.[4] These three works
share the common feature that none were destined for publication by their
author, which at least suggests a measure of sincerity in Leibniz’s comments
which is not otherwise present in the works which he intended for publication.[5]
Although Leibniz wrote to
Justel in 1678 that he found in Spinoza ‘‘a quantity of elegant thoughts
conforming with my own, as is well known by several of my friends who have also
read Spinoza,’’[6] beyond that
single remark Leibniz was never to acknowledge in print an intellectual
propinquity to Spinoza, though references to Spinoza’s thought abound
throughout his printed works.[7] Friedmann argues[8] that, although
Leibniz’s own dev elopment was not due to Spinoza’s thought, he ‘profited’ from
a reading of Spinoza and in the continuous effort to incorporate those insights
which he believed valid into his own systematic thought. Subsequent
commentators have been less certain.[9]
What is clear is that there are noteworthy similarities between the
systematic thought of the two philosophers, and also that Leibniz was
particularly concerned to disassociate himself from Spinoza’s monistic
naturalism in the public eye. This latter preoccupation may go a long way
toward explaining Leibniz’s own efforts to underline differences between his
thought and that of Spinoza, differences which have often tended to eother
dissolve or to diminish in significance under subsequent logical analysis and
historical inquiry.
Leibniz’s notes on the Ethica constitute the least aggressive
of the three commentaries by him, and thus reveal more than the others his
admiration for certain themes in Spinoza. In dealing especially with E1 and E2,
Leibniz often attempts to reformulate or interpret a definition, axiom or
proposition; and the result is often a more concise statement than the one
given by Spinoza. In his introduction to the Latin edition, Grua notes that
Leibniz copied (or had others copy) all of
the definitions, axioms, and propositions of the Ethica as it appeared in the Opera
Posthuma of 1677. Grua’s edition, like the present translation, is an
abridgement; since the editor did not reproduce those definitions, axioms, or
propositions which are exact transcriptions
from the Opera Posthuma. Internal references
to the Ethica are also written out
fully in Leibniz’s own notes, while the English translation follows Grua’s
transparent abbreviations. Grua encloses
Leibniz’s own comments (as
opposed to literal transcriptions or paraphrases) within plus-signs (+), where
the English translation precedes each comment or criticism with a plus-sign and
indents it to a new line in the interest of perspicuity. Leibniz’s opening
comment, that the notes are partly by others and may need correcting, probably
refers to the exact transcriptions, which he apparently had made by others and
then copied himself into his manuscript, which is wholly in his own hand. Grua
argues convincingly that the notes, interpretive recastings, and criticisms are
all the work of Leibniz himself.
Often,
in the course of reformulating one of Spinoza’s axioms or definitions, Leibniz
attempts to bring it closer to his own conception; and I have tried to indicate
in the footnotes the more obvious of such instances. Certain passages (also
footnoted by the translator) are also rather oblique in their references or
intent; and I have attempted to provide some possible resolutions of Leibniz’s
thought for most of these. Footnotes have otherwise been kept to a minimum in
order to allow the text and Leibniz’s own commentary and critique to speak for
themselves.
Several
general remarks should be made concerning the direction of Leibniz’s thought in
the notes. His criticisms of Spinoza’s naturalistic determinism (E1P17Schol)
indicate the general direction which he was to take in later works in the
effort never completely successful in my opinion, to reconcile freedom and
determinism. His remarks and qualifications dealing with the material on
individuation following E2P13 indicate the subsequent directions which his own
thought would take in the development of a theory of individuation based on vis viva, as opposed to Spinoza’s dev
elopment of a theory of conatus.
Bouveresse also argues that, in his comments on E3, Leibniz formulates the first known statement of his own account
of parallelism, which is significantly different from the parallelism offered
by Spinoza in E2P7 and developed throughout E3. Further, in his notes on E3 and
E4, Leibniz appears to express the greatest admiration (and the fewest number
of criticisms) of Spinoza’s account of the human affects. Perhaps Leibniz, like
Spinoza, had already realized that the effort to establish a new theory of
affectivity made by Descartes in the Passions
de l’aˆme was largely a disaster. Finally, Leibniz’s notes on E5 are
particularly brief. As Grua notes, the entire set of notes provides little more
than a literal transcription. But this section is no less critical than brief.
One of Leibniz’s primary negative reactions to Spinoza was the latter’s denial
of the traditional christian doctrine of immortality,[10]
and formulates a number of the themes which Leibniz was to later develop
as central to his own systematic thought.
Leibniz’s
1678 notes reveal the philosopher in his most sympathetic reading of the Ethica, while the two later works
indicate a thinker more concerned to develop alternative concepts and
explanations as a means of avoiding what he conceives as the major pitfalls of
the spinozistic world view. While the appearance of these later works in an
English translation is no less to be desired, the present translation documents
a seminal juncture in the development of Leibniz’s own thought, and a careful,
if not always sympathetic, reading of Spinoza’s Ethica.
Extracts
from Spinoza’s Opera Posthuma Notes by G. W. Leibniz (1678)
Tr anslated by Samuel
Shirley
The following notes are
partly my own, partly by others. Those written by others need to be corrected
on many points.
Ethics Part I
Finite
in its own kind is that apart from which another thing of the
same nature can be conceived, or that which can be limited by another thing of
the same nature. (Def. 2)
Substance
is
that which is in itself, or that which is not in another thing as its
substratum.[11] (Def. 3)
Attribute
is
an essential predicate[12] or a necessary
predicate. (Def. 4)
Mode
is
a predicate that is not necessary, i.e., it is subject to change. (Def. 5)[13]
God
is
an absolutely infinite being, that is, infinite in respect of his essence.
While other things are infinite in respect of extension or duration, he is infinite
in respect of all things that express some degree of reality. (Def. 6)[14]
That thing is said to be free which is determined only by virtue of its own nature to exist
and to act in a definite way. (Def. 7)
To
be constrained is to be determined by another thing to exist
in a definite way and to produce an effect. (Def. 7)
Eternity
is
the necessity to exist. (Def. 8)
That
which is conceived in itself and through itself is
that the knowledge of which does not require the knowledge of another thing.
(Def. 2)
There is nothing that is without cause.
(Ax. 3)[15]
Knowledge of an effect
depends on and involves knowledge of the cause. (Ax. 4)
Things which have nothing in
common with each other cannot be understood through each other. (Ax. 5)
No definition involves a fixed
number of individuals. Therefore Being, in an absolute sense is one, and only
one. (Pr. 8, Sch. 2)
A reason must be able to be
assigned not only for a thing’s existence but also for its non-existence. (Pr.
11, Second proof).
The greater the degree of
reality there is in a thing, the more force it has to exist. (Pr. 11, Sch.)
An infinite quantity cannot be
composed of finite parts. If corporeal substance could be so divided that all
its parts would be really distinct, why could not one of its parts be
annihilated while the other parts remained as before? Or in other words, why
could there not be a vacuum? Matter is everywhere the same, and we distinguish
parts in it only when we conceive it as affected in various ways. Hence it
follows that its parts are distinct only modally, not really. Water, in so far
as it is merely water, can be divided up and go out of existence, but not in so
far as it is corporeal substance. (Prop. 15,
Sch.)
+
Body is a mode of extension.
God does everything he can
do, and it is from God’s nature that all things flow always and necessarily,
just as the affections of a triangle flow from its essence. (Pr. 17, Sch.)
+ These statements are based on a play upon words with
regard to the word necessity. And the
comparison with a triangle is ill-conceived, since in the case of a triangle
there is no place for thought [cogitatio],
as there is in the case of God. As a result, God produces only the things that
he thinks best.[16] The only way in
which, in a particular manner of speaking, the word impossible (sic) is applicable, is that it is
impossible that God should not prefer those things (the best) to others.[17]
+ There is a contradiction between Pr. 17, Sch., towards
the end, and Pr.3. In Pr.3 cause and effect have something in common, whereas
in the Scholium the divine intellect agrees with ours only in name.[18]
+ The comparison between the affections of God and those
of a triangle is unapt. There could be no affections of a triangle unless other
things could be conceived independently of the triangle, even if the triangle
could be conceived through itself.[19]
God is not the remote cause of things.
(Pr. 28, Sch.)
Natura
naturans is that which is in itself and is conceived through
itself; Natura naturata is that which
follows therefrom. (Pr. 29)[20]
A thing is impossible either because its definition
involves a contradiction or because there is no external cause determined to
produce such a thing. (Pr. 33, Sch.1)
Nothing
exists from whose nature an effect does not follow. (Pr. 36)
Why did God not create men in such a way that they would
be governed solely by reason? Because he did not lack material for creating all
things from the highest to the lowest degree of perfection; or rather because
the laws of his nature were so comprehensive as to suffice for the production
of everything that can be conceived by infinite intellect. (Appendix to Part 1,
near the end)
Ethics Part II
Perfection is
degree of reality. (Def. 6)
In God there is the idea of his essence, and of those
things that follow from that essence. (Pr. 3)
+ Therefore that idea is not in his
essence itself; therefore there is in God something that does not pertain to
his essence.[21]
Whatever happens in the
object of the idea constituting the human mind is bound to be perceived by the
human mind; i.e., the idea of that thing will necessarily be in the human mind.
That is to say, if the object of the idea constituting the human mind is a
body, nothing can happen in that body without its being perceived by the mind.
(Pr. 12, not noted)
In proportion as a body is
more apt than other bodies to act and to be acted upon simultaneously in many
ways, so is its mind more apt than other minds to perceive many things
simultaneously; and in proportion as the actions of one body depend on itself
alone and the less that other bodies concur with it in its actions, the more
apt is its mind to understand distinctly. (Pr. 13, Sch.)
If the parts of an individual thing undergo change while
yet preserving their shape and motion, or even if there is an increase in their
motion, their magnitude and their matter while the former proportion is
preserved, the individual thing will remain the same. (Pr. 13, lemma 5)
+ It is also necessary that the same
relation to external things be preserved.[24]
Memory
is
the linking of ideas involving the nature of things outside the human body, a
linking which occurs in the mind in parallel with the order and the linking of
the affections of the human body. (Pr. 18, Sch.)
+
Therefore when we have sensed things together and the image of one of them
recurs, we also imagine the other.
The mind has no knowledge of
the body, nor does it know it to exist, except through ideas of the body’s
affections. (Pr. 19)
The mind does not know
itself except in so far as it perceives ideas of the affections of the body.
(Pr. 23)
Knowledge of a conclusion[25] without
premisses is confused. (Pr. 28, proof)
An idea is inadequate
in us when God has that idea not only in so far as he constitutes the human
mind but also in so far as he has the idea of another thing simultaneously with
the human mind. (Pr. 11, Sch.)
Falsity
consists
in the privation of knowledge which inadequate ideas involve. For example, men
are deceived in thinking that they act without cause, for they do not perceive
the causes which determine their actions. In the same way we are wrong in thinking
that the sun is about 200 feet distant from us, or that it is small. The error
does not consist in our seeing the sun in this way, but in that we do not know
its true distance and the cause of our seeing it so. (Pr. 35 and Sch.)
Propositions 37, 38, 38, 40. . .
Here are set forth the fundamental causes of the notions
we call common, some being more
useful than others. Secondary notions are axioms. (Pr. 40, Sch.)
An image is an
affection of the human body, the idea of which sets forth an external body as
present to us. (Pr. 17, Sch.)
+
Because of the similarity of the impressions or motions in us which are
produced by its presence.
The human mind is capable of imagining as many bodies
distinctly at the same time as there are images capable of being formed at the
same time in its body. But when these images become confused, the mind will
imagine the bodies in a confused way, and will comprehend them under one
attribute, Entity or Thing. (Pr. 40, Sch. 1)
+ That which we cannot denominate by any
other mark, we call Thing.[26]
When we are unable to make distinction between so many
images deriving from different men, this gives rise to a confused image of
human nature. (Pr. 40, Sch. 1)
+ It seems to me that the image of a
species is given us even when we know only one individual.[27]
Three
kinds of knowledge. There is knowledge of the first kind when the reason for it is not apparent.
Knowledge of the second kind arises
from our possessing common notions and adequate ideas of the properties of
things. Knowledge of the third kind,
which we call intuitive, proceeds from the adequate idea of the formal essence
of certain attributes in God to the adequate knowledge of the essence of
things. Now here are the three kinds of knowledge illustrated by one example:
we find the fourth proportional by multiplying the second by the third and
dividing the product by the first. This procedure is known to tradesmen either
from experience or from being taught it, while mathematicians know it by
studying the proof, that is, from the common property of proportionality. But
in the case of very simple numbers the becomes clear through intuition — as in
the case of 1,
2, 3, the fourth proportional is 6. And
this is clearer from intuition than from a proof of a general kind. (Pr. 40,
Sch. 2)[28]
He who has an adequate idea
knows that he has an adequate idea, and cannot doubt its truth. That is, there
is no better basis for judgment than the clear and distinct idea itself. (Pr.
43)
It is of the nature of
reason to regard things under the form of eternity, and not as related to a definite
time; that is, it is of the nature of reason to consider things as necessary,
not as contingent. (Pr. 44 and Cor. 2)
The idea of any particular thing
involves the infinite and eternal essence of God, because things cannot be
conceived apart from their cause, that is, apart from God. And God as cause
must be conceived adequately, because he is at the same time in the whole and
in the parts. (Prs. 45,
46)
+ It
is the very idea of essence or reality.
Most errors consist only in
the incorrect application of words to things.[29]Thus,
when men make mistakes in arithmetic, they hav e figures in mind that are
different from those on paper. (Pr. 47, Sch.)
By will I understand the faculty of affirming and denying; I do not
mean desire. (Pr. 48, Sch.)
There is in the mind no volition, that is, affirmation
and negation, except that which an idea, in so far as it is an idea, involves.
(Pr. 49)
Ethics Part III
Adequate cause . . . inadequate cause . . . to be active
. . . to be passive . . . emotions. (Definitions 1, 2, 3, Prop. 1, Prop. 2)
+
The series of ideas is distinct from the series of bodies, and there is only a
reciprocal correspondence.[30]
We
desire a thing moderately when our appetite can easily be kept in
check by the remembrance of another thing. (Pr. 2, Sch.)
The endeavour [conatus] to preserve ourselves, when
more closely related to mind, is called Will [voluntas]; when it is related to mind and body together, it is
called Appetite [appetitus], and Desire [cupiditas] is appetite in so far as that
is considered together with the consciousness of itself. (Pr. 9, Sch.)
Hence it follows that we do
not strive for, will, seek a thing because we judge it to be good. On the
contrary, we judge a thing to be good
because we strive . . . etc. (Pr. 9,
Sch.)
+ But it seems to me that neither is the
cause of the other; they accompany each other, as do thought and motion. (Pr.
2)[31]
Prop. 11 — Pleasure [laetitia], Pain [tristitia], Titillation [titillatio], anguish [dolor], Cheerfulness [hilaritas], Melancholy [melancholia]. (Pr. 11, Sch.)
Prop. 12. We endeavour to imagine only those things that
posit our power. For the more distinctly we thus contemplate ourselves, the
more we pass into a state of greater perfection. (Pleasure, Prop. 11, Sch.)
Love
[amor], hatred [odium]. (Pr. 13,
Sch.)
Timidity
[timor]. (Pr. 39, Sch.)
+ There should be some emotion relating
to Hope [spes] in the same way as
Timidity relates to Fear [metus].
The pleasure that arises from regarding ourselves is
called Self-love [philautia] or Contentment [acquiescentia]. Hence it follows that ev
eryone is eager to tell of his exploits and to boast of himself. (Pr. 55, Cor.
1, Sch.)
+ If a man does not make some display of
his actions, this is for one of the following reasons: either he is a humble
person, or he is dull or his mind is engaged on other matters, or he is a
despiser of present reality.
Definition of Emotions 38. Cruelty [crudelitas] or Savageness [saevitia] is the desire whereby someone
is urged to inflict injury on one whom we love or whom we pity.
+ One whom we feel we ought to love or
to pity.
Consternation
[consternatio] is the term applied to one
whose desire to avoid some evil is checked by a feeling of of wonder evoked by
the
evil which he fears. (Def. 42)
+ I
disagree, and the definitions do not accord with this.
General Definition of the Emotions.
+ I am surprised that he has not made
clear what is common to pleasure, pain and desire, as he should have done.[32]
Ethics Part IV
. .
. an imagining is stronger when we are thinking of nothing that excludes the
present existence of the external thing. (Pr. 9, Proof) + For it is by that
alone that we distinguish between imagining and sense-perception.
If two similar individuals are combined, they compose an
individual twice as powerful. (Pr. 18, Sch.)
+
Indeed, more than twice as powerful.
Prop. 29.
+ This is not a valid proof.
Confidence
[securitas] and Joy [gaudium] are emotions of pleasure, but they imply a preceding pain.
(Pr. 47, Sch.)
+
Indeed, and the pleasure is greater when preceded by pain.
If
we exercised reason, we would not prefer present things to future things.
(Pr. 62, Sch.)
+
But what about future things?[33]
Prop. 66.
+ I
would say that we should take more account of future things than of present
things.
Prop. 69.
+ I doubt this.[34]
Prop. 72, Schol.
+ What if a man, using deception, could
free himself from imminent danger of death? His answer is obscure.[35]
Ethics Part V
Prop.
9. The proof is supplemented by reference to Pr. 5.
Prop. 23, Proof and Sch.
+ Since the body is always changing, it
is difficult to see how its idea or mind can remain the same.[36]
Prop. 38.
+ An objection can be raised: if that
love is eternal, what need is there to attain it? Moreover, it must be said
that, whereas it is indeed eternal, unless it is actually aroused by me in my
body, it does not pertain to this my body.37
Death is the less hurtful in
proportion as the mind’s clear and distinct knowledge is greater. (Pr. 38,
Sch.) + But what if we have forgotten?38
Individuation
in Leibniz and Spinoza Lee C. Rice Marquette University
1.
Introduction: The Problem in Leibniz
Although the majority of his
commentators see the concept of individuation as one of the fundamental
building blocks of Leibniz’s system, the position of this concept within his
thought has varied in time. Tw o early works are devoted wholly to it: the Disputatio de principio individui of
1663[37] and the Dissertatio de principio individui of
1675.[38] The problem in
both these works was that of determining the nature of an individuating
principle in a world of ‘things’ taken as a given. The principle is taken as a
given in 1686 when Leibniz completes the Discours
de me´taphysique. The phrase ‘individual substance’, however, disappears
after 1686, and is replaced by ‘simple substance’ or ‘monad’ in the Monadology (1714). Bitbol-Hespe´rie`s
(1991, 79) argues that, beginning with the Syste`me
nouveau de la nature et de la communication des substances (1695), the term
‘individual’ (individuum) is reserved
for one particular class of such substances: the human soul.
In
the Disputatio of 1663, Leibniz
writes that ‘‘The individual is. . . either something logical in the order of
predication or something metaphysical in the series of things.’’ Russell (1900)
and Couturat (1901) both see Leibniz’s thoughts on individuation as stemming from
his reflexions on the ‘predicate-in-notion’ claim: the subject term of primary
true propositions includes or implies the totality of predicates possessed by
the item denoted by the subject (see also Hacking 1976, 137-139). On this
supposition the entirety of Leibniz’s metaphysics is derived from a logical
theory about the structure of propositions.
The
Russell-Couturat account has been most influential among anglophone authors;
and, while there is certainly some truth to it, it fails to account for the multi-faceted
structure of Leibniz’s dev elopment. Gueroult (1967) is representative of a
tradition which sees Leibniz’s metaphysics as a derivative of his reflexions on
physics, particularly the leibnizean developments of the notion of force (vis viva and conatus) which are omnipresent in Leibniz’s later works. A more
sustained (in terms of physics) argument for Gueroult’s position is given by
Buchdahl (1969, 405-438), who successfully derives Leibniz’s mechanistic models
from his conservation principles in physics, and his teleological principles
from an analogue in optics. It would be an error, I believe, to view
GueroultBuchdahl as a competitive alternative to Russell-Couturat. Rather, each
of the two accounts captures an important and often (but not always) dominant
aspect of Leibniz’s dev elopment.
But
there is also a third source for this development. In 1857 Foucher de Careil
published, with translation and commentary, a set of notes which Leibniz had
written on a book by Wachter on Spinoza.[39]
In these Animadversiones,
Leibniz juxtaposes his own interpretation of Paul’s phrase, ‘‘Everything exists
and moves in God,’’ with that of Spinoza; though his juxtaposition makes it
clear that his own interpretation is quite similar to that of Spinoza at E2P43Schol
(Friedmann 1962, 161-162). The few critical points which Leibniz raises against
Spinoza seem misplaced (Bouveresse 1992, 190-191), especially his claim that
Spinoza’s view of the human soul leads to the concept of world soul. These same
critical points are recapitulated later (1702) by Leibniz in his Conside´rations sur la doctrine d’un esprit
universel[40] and still later
at many points in the Theodicy. These
texts give rise to yet a third source for the development of Leibniz’s thought
on individuation: the desire to avoid the monistic naturalism of Spinoza. While
this preoccupation is a negative one, it certainly acts as a controlling factor
in the extension of both the ‘predicatein-subject’ and the physical models to
the metaphysical domain.
In what follows, I wish to
isolate the logical and physical strands in the development of Leibniz’s
thought, while at the same time paying attention to the anti-spinozism latent
in both. My perspective here will be largely reconstructive and conceptual,
rather than historical or chronological. I wish to consider the two lines
separately, and then speculate as to the reasons why Leibniz should want to
unify them within a single principle of individuation. I then wish to show that
the same two lines of thought are present in Spinoza’s system, and to suggest
arguments which Spinoza would have proffered (against Leibniz) for maintaining
two distinct principles of individuation. One of these, the logical, as we
shall see, gives rise to Spinoza’s doctrine of the attributes; whereas the
other gives rise to the physico-ontological account of individuation delivered
following E2P13.
2.
The Logical Model
In
the Discours de me ´taphysique 8,
Leibniz argues that the concept of an individual substance must contain all of
the predicates of the subject to which it is attributed. He adds (Discours 14, 46) that ‘‘. . . it is very
evident that created substances depend upon God, who preserves them and who
even produces them continually by a kind of emanation, just as we produce our thoughts.’’
This establishes a tight parallelism between the manner in which created
substances are produced by God and our manner of conceiving them via subject
and predicates. Although Leibniz freely utilizes the scotistic term haecceitas in the Discours, he relies strongly upon a refutation (whose origins date
from the Disputatio of 1663) of
scotistic realism: Leibniz and Spinoza are both agreed in denying the existence
of genera and species outside the human mind (see E2P40Schol1 for Spinoza).[41] The parallelism
between predication and the nature of things is derived from the fact that God
continuously produces individual substances by a manner of emanation analogous
to that by which we produce our thoughts (Discours
8, 40-41).
The
transition from a theory of predication to a nominalistic and metaphysical
account of the concept of substance requires in fact the identification of a
certain proprium quid which is unique
to each individual and which constitutes it independently of any reference to
its predicates. Leibniz concedes that the actual specification of such a
principle is impossible: ‘‘. . . it is impossible for us to have knowledge of
individuals and to find the means for exactly determining the individuality of
anything whatever.’’[42] This is an important
concession, and one which, as Leibniz himself acknowledges in the Disputatio of 1663, threatens
scepticism. Having agreed with the nominalists that genera and species cannot
exist outside the mind, and with Suarez’s critique of Scotus, Leibniz concludes
that the principle of individuation lies in both form and matter; but then goes
on to concede that such a principle cannot be known by finite minds. The reason
for this is easily seen. A cluster of monadic predicates (some of which are
collapsed forms of polyadic predicates referencing other individuals)[43] will be actually
infinite in number. Indeed, if the number of individuals in the universe at any
specific time t(n) is infinite, then a subset of those predicates, the number
of detensed predicates referencing t(n), will itself be infinite. This result
lies at the base of Leibniz’s later claim that each individual, inasmuch as it
constitutes a complete reflexion of the entire universe, is infinite and infinitely
complex (see Discours 9, 41-42). The
notion of an individual as infinite, as we shall shortly see, quickly comes
into conflict with the second model of individuation.
Aside
from its nominalistic roots, however, Leibniz’s logical conception of an
individual falls back upon an arithmetic model — even pythagorean according to
Belaval (1983). The third corollary of the Disputation
of 1663 claims that ‘‘the essences of things are like numbers.’’ The
analogy of individual essences to particular numbers remains unexplained, in
perhaps much the same manner as Spinoza’s notion of a unique ratio of motion-and-rest which
individuates bodies remains without analytic detail in the short treatment of
physics following E2P13: Spinoza provides a placeholder for the subsequent
development of physics, whereas Leibniz provides an undeveloped analogy at the
root of his metaphysics (see Buchdahl 1969, 449-454). While in Descartes the
nature of thinking substances is wholly different from that of bodies, and thus
relies on an entirely different principle of individuation than that of
extended substances, all individual substances for Leibniz (as for Spinoza)
must fall under the same principle of particular individuation. In E3P6 and
following, Spinoza transfers the physical model into the psychological domain
by extending conatus from a physical
doctrine to a theory of appetition, whereas Leibniz attempts to block the
physical (and ultimately mechanistic) model from psychology by removing it from
physics. This lies at the basis of his claim that the essence of individual bodies
cannot be extension (see Discours 12, 44).
The
above move, of course, implies that the principle of individuation for bodies
is no less unknowable than that for minds, and threatens scepticism in physics
in the absence of a working out of the arithmetic analogy. As long as he
considers space and time as realities of the same order as that of individuals
themselves, Leibniz can offer an alternative (and knowable) mode of
individuation for bodies through their extrinsic properties of place and
temporal coordinates: this he offers in the Confessio
philosophi of 1673 (see Bitbol-Hespe´ries 1991, 82-83). But sixteen years
later, beginning with On Copernicanism
and the Relativity of Motion (1689), he has adopted a relational account of
space and time which can no longer form the basis for the definitions of
individuals placed in space and time. This compels him to argue that, ‘‘beyond
the difference of time and of place, there must always be an internal principle
of distinction’’ (Nouveaux essais II,
27#2, 196).
C.
D. Broad has argued[44] that the logical
account of individuation in the mature thought of Leibniz involves two distinct
principles for characterizing the internal principle of individuation. The first
asserts that to every individual there corresponds a set of non-dispositional
facts of tenseless characterization which refer to each moment of its history.
This principle, I suggest, arises from Leibniz’s suarezian form-matter account
of haecceity, combined with the (mature) relational account of time. The second
principle, not implied by the first, says that every dispositional fact about
an individual is also contained in its internal structure. Everything which
happens or could happen to an individual is the emergence of one of these facts
from quiescence, or its consequent reversion into quiescence. The tenselessness
of these facts, or the corresponding predicates which denote them, is reflected
in Leibniz’s analogy of ‘windowlessness’ (see Monadology 7, 214), since causality is inherently a temporal
process. Broad goes on to argue that such an account of the
‘predicate-in-notion’ is consistent with Leibniz’s claim that contingency
exists in the universe. I shall return to this question later.
There are in fact two
problems connected with this version of individuation. The one which we have already
seen is that, while it asserts the existence of a unique principle for each
individual, it also implies that such a principle is unknowable by any finite
intelligence.[45] A second, but
equally serious, problem is that, while every individual can be construed in a
certain sense as a bundle of predicates (a` la Russell in the theory of
descriptions), not every bundle of predicates should be thereby construed as an
individual. The logical account of individuation is, accordingly, seriously
incomplete at best, and requires supplementation from another model. It is to
this model, the physical, that I now turn.
3.
The Physical Model
Beginning
about 1680 Leibniz is in possession of his new account of dynamics: the main
details of his new concept of force and the critique of cartesian mechanism are
both present in the Animadversiones of
1676. We saw in the preceding section that the logical analysis of
individuation had at least suggested to Leibniz that individual bodies cannot
be defined in terms of cartesian extension alone. As Bitpol-Hespe´ries (1991,
84) notes, ‘‘De la pre´sence des pre´dicats dans le sujet, on en arrive ainsi
a` la succession des e´ve´nements pour une substance.’’ A further extension,
once again by analogy rather than by argument, is the claim that all of nature
is ‘full of life’.[46] Whereas in the
earlier works of Leibniz life (and conatus)
are conceived as a spiritual unity, the new conception of force is that of a
physical reality, not a feature of extension per se, which lies outside the range
of imaginational cognition and geometrical representation. As Bouveresse (1992,
90, translation mine) notes, ‘‘Force is the sum of the impetus, elementary drives or impulses (F=Smvdt); corporeal
substance is defined as acting in its own right, and there is no longer a need
for the premature intervention of spiritualistic metaphysics.’’
Hacking
(1972, 138) is wrong, however, in claiming that ‘‘Active principle seems to
have been Leibniz’s first deep thought about substance.’’ It is certainly true,
as Gueroult (1967, 138-140) argues, that Leibniz’s dynamics contained the germ
of the notion of ‘pre-established harmony’, since dynamical particles cannot
interact in the sense of passing some property from one to the other. But the
implications of this fact, and the characterization of a physical individual as
a unity of force is a development certainly posterior to 1676; for even at that
date, as BitbolHespe´ries (1991, 85-86) has shown, Leibniz was still
distinguishing corporeal substances, moved directly by their union with divine
substance, from substances endowed with reason and which contained an internal
source of spontaneity. By 1680, in part through his reading of Huyghens’
mechanical experiments and in part through his critique of the cartesian principle
of the conservation of momentum,[47] Leibniz is able
to claim that an individual sensu proprio
is a source of action through its possession of an internal force or conatus.
In A New System of Nature (1695), Leibniz describes the evolution of
his notion of a life-force animating every individual in terms of a partial
restoration of aristotelian substantial forms (139-140). It is at this stage of
his development that he has arrived at a point close to Spinoza’s claim that ‘omnia animata sunt’. The scholastic
underpinnings of ‘life-force’ as soul (anima)
in a living thing, however, present a problem for him which is not present for
Spinoza (whose concept has no such underpinnings). For, ‘‘. . . what becomes of
these souls or forms at the death of the animal or at the destruction of the
individual organized substance?’’ (New
System, 140). Leibniz’s answer to this question is ambiguous at best, but
reveals the uncomfortable position of the notion of conatus in his physical system:
This made me judge that
there is only one reasonable view to take — namely, the conservation not only
of the soul, but also of the animal itself and its organic machine, even though
the destruction of its larger parts reduces it to a smallness which escapes our
senses. . . (New System, 141).
Though the life-force of a corporeal
individual is in a certain sense conserved, Leibniz goes on to argue that
rational souls follow higher laws, in that their continuous existence makes
them members of the ‘‘society of minds.’’ And, so despite the transplantation
of the notion of a life-force or conatus into
his dynamics, Leibniz retains the vestiges of a cartesian mindbody dualism:
In addition, by means of the
soul or form there is a true unity corresponding to what is called the self [moy] in us. Such a unity could not occur in the machines made by a
craftsman or in a simple mass of matter, howev er organized it may be; such a
mass can only be considered as an army or a herd, or a pond full of fish, or
like a watch composed of springs and wheels. Yet if there were no true substantial unities, there would be
nothing substantial or real in the collection. (New System, 142).
Force
has here been physicalized, but its role in the explanation of corporeal
individuals remains vague.
In a
letter to Huyghens dated 29 December 1691, Leibniz characterizes the cartesian
quantity of matter (mv) as an inert or passive force, and argues that his own vis viva, an active power, is required
for the explanation of physical processes. While this new force can be
determined mathematically,[48] it fails to be a
scientific object in any originative sense; for, like the continuum itself, it
is not a substance, and thus requires a metaphysical foundation — primitive
force, the formal and determinative element of an individual substance. The
transition from kinematics to dynamics is thus, in a certain sense, also a
transition from physics (as a geometry of space and time) to metaphysics; since
the concept of force, while it may play a role in the former, is dependent upon
the latter.
The
notion of an individual as an active principle of unity is also central to the Monadology of 1714, but the same difficulties
occur there as earlier. Arnauld had urged Leibniz for a clearer explanation of
this notion of active principle. In reply to Arnauld (8 December 1686), Leibniz
explains that not every object governed by physical laws counts as an
individual.[49] If one places
two parts of a dogul onto a brooch, the result is a rigid and throwable object,
but it remains only an aggregate. Even a solid slab of marble is only an
aggregate; since, says Leibniz, the mason can snap it in half, which proves
that it is not a substance. One might object, of course, that a human being, or
virtually any physical object, can likewise be snapped in half. Leibniz has
developed the notion of a principle of active unity, but his model is bereft of
any information as to how it can be applied to real objects in the physical
domain. The transition from kinematics to dynamics remains hopelessly
incomplete despite the ability of the integral calculus to calculate the values
of the forces which are claimed to account for the individuation of bodies
conceived as dynamic individuals.
Each of the two models of
individuation which Leibniz proposes is logically independent from the other;
and each, as we have seen, implies certain problems. Why, then, should Leibniz
have employed the two models as coextensive — or as describing coextensive
individuals? This question may be ultimately unanswerable, insofar as Leibniz
most frequently deploys the two models in different situations and in different
works. We hav e seen that he himself appreciated the difficulties implicit in
each model: perhaps an underlying thought was that a combinatorial approach
would weaken the difficulties taken separately. There is also Gueroult’s
suggestion, mentioned above, that the concept of force which Leibniz develops
out of Huyghens’ work suggests the ideality of relations (or the reduction of
all polyadic predicates to monadic), which in turn is in some sense at the
basis of the ‘predicate-in-notion’ model for individuation. But the basis for
any union of the two models is at best a weak analogy in the absence of
argumentation.[50] But, as we shall
shortly see, combining the two models, rather than reducing the distinctive difficulties
of each, contributes to a new problem of which Leibniz seems totally unaware.
4.
Spinozistic Rejoinders
Gueroult’s
analysis of Huyghens’ concept of force, and its obvious consequence that
individuals conceived as unitary loci of forces cannot literally transfer properties from one to the
other can be interpreted in two manners. From one perspective, exemplified
partially by Hacking (1976, 145), it can be seen as an anticipation of Hume’s
‘constant-conjunction’ interpretation of causal nexus, one antecedent of which
is Leibniz’s ‘predicate in notion’ model.[51]
But there is yet another way of approaching the dynamic concept of an
individual. A force in the modern sense (of which Leibniz and Spinoza are
clearly both prophets) does not exist in isolation from an environment or field
in which it operates. In the modern field theory model, what we call a force is
simply a spatio-temporal equilibrium within a larger field. So that the notion
of force is itself relative to, and parasitic upon, the field of which that
force is a constitutive element. In short, in order to exist or operate, a
force must function as part of a larger whole. But that in itself constitutes
an inherent obstacle to combining the dynamic model with the logical one; for,
in the physical sense, force itself is finitary, operating within the
determined boundaries of the field of which it is constitutive.[52] We hav e already
seen, however, that the logical model of individuation is inherently infinitary,
via the leibnizean requirement that an individual in this sense must contain a
complete and exhaustive set of its own state-descriptions in the absence of any
external relationships.
It
is now time to play the spinozistic card, and to argue that it resolves some of
the difficulties which Leibniz faces. Seen as a locus of force within a larger field
or environment, the correlates of leibnizean individuals are spinozistic modes.
Disregarding the problem of the infinite modes and their status, we can see
that for Spinoza a mode is a finite determination
of a larger whole. Modes exist and operate in interaction with other modes, by
which they are determined to exist and to act and which they in turn determine
to exist and to act.[53] Modes by their
very nature (whether they are modes of thought or of extension) operate in a
temporal order which is interactive.[54]
This is the basis of Bennett’s talk of a spinozistic ‘field metaphysics’.[55][56]
Such a metaphysics makes particular extended individuals adjectival on
regions of space, and reduces talk about regions of space to talk about the
features of space (extended substance) without having to quantify directly over
the regions themselves. Each individual is, of course, constituted by and
constitutive of a particular region of space, which in turn is an individual of
a still higher order (still finite), which in turn is an individual of a yet
higher (but still finite) order. Note that this model makes all (finite) modes
temporal, but only extended modes corporeal (tri-dimensional).
Leibniz’s claim that
individuation cannot depend on external relations can now be relativized to
Spinoza’s modal model. An external relation between any two or more finite
modes at any giv en lev el of individuation becomes an internal relation
holding for some individual at some higher level of org anization. So Leibniz’s
claim that external relations do not exist becomes the claim that they are
always reducible to higher-order
properties of some individual. Spinoza makes the claim in this manner:
If we now conceive another
individual thing composed of several individual things of different natures, we shall find that this can be affected in
many other ways while still preserving its nature. . . Now if we go on to
conceive a third kind of thing of individual things composed of this second
kind, we shall find that it can be affected in many other ways without any
change in its structure (forma). If
we thus continue to infinity, we
shall readily conceive the whole of nature as one individual whose parts — that
is, all the constituent bodies — vary in infinite ways (modis) without any change in the individual as a whole.
(E2P13Lemma7Schol: italics mine)
Of
course neither the human nor any other mind can actually continue the
part-whole composition to infinity, and the entire conceptual process remains a
finitary one. The infinite individual here described must be conceived or
constructed by other logical means, and is what Spinoza calls an ‘attribute’.
A spinozistic attribute is
an individual in Leibniz’s ‘predicate-innotion’ sense of individual. Everything
which is true of it refers to an
internal state: it is, in Leibniz’s language, windowless. It can in principle
be described adequately using two infinite sets of propositions: the first a
set of descriptions of the individual modes (and hierarchies thereof) which
constitute it, the second a set of nomological statements which describe the
relations within it. The first set
will contain existential claims which are tenseless with respect to the infinite
individual but tensed with respect to its constitutive modes. The second set
will contain wholly tenseless statements (Spinoza’s ‘laws of nature’). Readers
may recognize in this an anticipation of the Hempel-Oppenheim cover-model for
scientific explanation: to explain an event is to provide a deductive argument
whose premises contain a statement of initial states plus a set of laws, and
whose conclusion is the event itself.[57]
We
can now also resolve Leibniz’s query about a ‘genuine’ individual and a lump of
marble, which can be split into parts. This difficulty, as we hav e seem,
forces Leibniz to claim that corporeal individuals are at best what I would
call ‘quasi-individuals’ insofar as they do not display the unitary notion of
individuation upon which he insists. This in turn reintroduces a species of
cartesian dualism, which sees thinking things as ‘genuine’ individuals and
corporeal objects as quasiindividuals. The distinction between individuals sensu proprio and quasiindividuals can
be made within spinozism as well (though Spinoza employs no such terminology),
but it is not attribute-specific as it is in Leibniz. The key, I believe, is to
be found in Spinoza’s insistence above (E2P13Lemma7Schol) that individuals of
any giv en order are composed of lower-order individuals diversis naturis: in short, the hierarchy of individuation is one
of complexification and not simple combination. A human organism (which is
corporeal) can be broken into parts, but these parts are individuals of
different natures, whereas Leibniz’s marble, being a quasi-individual, can be
broken into parts eaˆdem naturaˆ.[58] For the
attribute-individuals, causality is a wholly internal story: causal chains
occur within a given attribute, but never move from one attribute to another.
So the internalization of relations holds for infinite individuals of the
‘predicate-in-notion’ sort (attributes), but never for finite individuals of
the dynamic sort (modes).
Note
that nothing which I have dev eloped above depends in any way upon attribute
paralellism or the (in)famous E2P7. That the predicate-innotion model applies
to substance conceived as an infinite whole is all that was needed. Spinoza’s
further claim that there are an actually infinite number of ways in which it
may be adequately applied[59] is a further
claim, and one which, I believe, is not relevant to the general problem of
individuation in either Leibniz or Spinoza.
We hav e seen that Spinoza’s
implicit use of the two models of individuation resolves some of the difficulties
which Leibniz faced. A further consequence of Spinoza’s use of the two models,
however, embodies just the sort of result which Leibniz, in his desire to avoid
spinozistic naturalism, would have sought to avoid. If the dynamic model for
individuation applies to individuals per se, and not merely to corporeal or to
mental individuals (to the exclusion of the other), then a notion of unitary
force must be developed for the latter independently of the notion developed
for the former. The physical model is outlined in the series of schematic
lemmata introduced following E2P13, and the balance of E2 develops a geometry
(or kinematics) for mental individuals (spinozistic minds). The account of conatus beginning at E3P6 provides the
dynamic model for mental individuals. Spinoza is a committed physicalist here:
though the psychological account of conatus
is independent of the physical model adumbrated early in E2, he is not
above ‘bootstrapping’ from the physical laws (i.e., inertia) to corresponding
psychological laws. Perhaps the bootstrapping potential of E2P7 is what made it
so attractive to Spinoza.[60]
A
full-fledged conatus model, however,
applied to minds means that the part-whole relationship applies between mental
individuals of lower and higher orders. This may have been what Leibniz had in
time when he claimed that Spinoza’s model leads to a ‘world-soul’ concept.[61] It also leads to
the complete naturalizing of the human mind which Leibniz had been at such
pains to avoid. And, with that naturalizing, conjoined with spinozistic
parallelism, comes the psychological determinism to which Leibniz poses his own
(and, in my opinion, ultimately incoherent) account of human freedom as an
alternative. For, if the dynamic model is applied directly to the human mind as
Spinoza does via his account of conatus, then the explanation of human behavior
is no less a tale of causal explanation than is the physical model of
interacting bodies. While Spinoza’s twofold account of individuation (modes and
attributes) may resolve the logical problems in Leibniz’s efforts to provide a
single and unified account, Leibniz’s own oft-declared intent of avoiding
spinozism would certainly have sufficed to make it inherently attractive. This
negative feature of Leibniz’s motivation may perhaps account in some
considerable part for his failure to develop a unified model of individuation,
or to provide a resolution of the difficulties which he himself found in the
two models.
In this paper I have
suggested that the logical analysis of problems within both Spinoza and
Leibniz, and their contrasting attempted resolutions of these, can provide a
fruitful means to coming to better understand the systematic thought of each
thinker. Individuation is only one such area where Leibniz and Spinoza are both
grappling with a set of important problems; but it is, I suggest, an area where
we have much to learn from each and also from both.
A
Selective Leibniz-Spinoza Bibliography
Translations from the text of Spinoza,
where given, are my own. I prefer the edition of J. Van Vloten and J. P. N.
Land [Benedicti de Spinoza opera quotquot
reperta sunt. 3rd edition. 4 vols. The Hague: M. Nijhoff, 1914] to that of
Carl Gebhardt [Opera, im Auftrag der
Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften. 4 vols. Heidelberg: Carl Winters
Verlag, 1925]. A new and critical edition of the Opera Postuma is under preparation in the Netherlands, and will
probably resemble closely the Van Vloten and Land edition. References to the Ethica are internal. E2P13Cor is the
corollary to Prop. 13 of Part 2. E3DefAff6 is Definition 6 from the Definitions
of the Affects, an appendix to E3. Other abbreviations are Dem(-onstration),
Schol(-ium), App(-endix), and Def(-inition).
References to the works of Leibniz in
translation are to: G. W. Leibniz, Philosophical
Essays, tr. Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989. The
Disputatio de principio individui is
the thesis which Leibniz presented in May of 1663 for his baccalaureate. It
appears in Vol. 4 of the edition of C. G. Gebhardt, Die philosophischen Schriften von Gotfried Wilhem Leibniz (Hildesheim:
Georg Olms, 1960), 17-26. A French translation of this early work by Jeannine
Quillet, with notes and introduction, appears in Les Etudes Philosophiques 1979#1, 79-105. The Dissertatio de principio individui was written thirteen years later
(April 1676) following Leibniz’s residence in Paris (1672-1676), one year after
his discovery of the infinitesimal calculus.
Alcante´ra, Jean-P. (1996). ‘‘L’ontologie de la
dynamique: Leibniz et la notion de substance a` un attribut.’’ In
Pierre-Franc¸ois Moreau (Ed.), Architectures
de la Raison (pp. 19-34). Fontenay-St-Cloud: ENS Editions.
Alexander, H. G., Ed.
(1956). The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence.
New York: Barnes & Noble.
Allen, D. (1983). Studia Leibnitiana: 11. Mechanical Explanations and the Ultimate Origin
of the Universe According to Leibniz. Wiesbaden: Franz Steiner Verlag.
Altmann, A. (1967). ‘‘Moses
Mendelssohn on Leibniz and Spinoza.’’ In R. Loewe (Ed.), Studies in Rationalism, Judaism and Universalism (pp. 15-46).
London: Routledge and Keg an Paul.
Ashworth, E. J. (1967).
‘‘Joachim Jungius (1587-1657) and the Logic of Relations,’’ Archiv fu¨r Geschichte der Philosophie 49,
72-85.
Bartuschat, W. (1981). ‘‘Spinoza in der Philosophie von
Leibniz.’’ In K. Cramer, W. G. Jacobs, & W. Schmidt-Biggemann (Eds.), Spinozas Ethik und ihre fru¨he Wirkung (pp.
51-66). Wolfenbuttel: Herzog August Bibliothek.
Belaval, Y. (1948). ‘‘Le Leibniz et Spinoza de M. Georges Friedmann,’’ Revue de Me´taphysique et de Morale 53, 307-321.
_______. (1983). ‘‘Leibniz
lecteur de Spinoza,’’ Archives de
Philosophie 1983, 531-552.
Biasutti, F. (1990).
‘‘Reason and Experience in Spinoza and Leibniz,’’ Studia Spinozana 6, 45-72.
Bickmann, C. (1995). ‘‘Auf
dem Wege zu einer Metaphysik der Freiheit,’’ Kantstudien 86, 321-330.
Bitbol-Hespe´rie`s, Annie. (1991). ‘‘Leibniz et la
question de l’individuation.’’ In P.-N. Mayaud (Ed.), Le proble`me de l’individuation. Paris: Vrin.
Blackwell, K. (1985). The
Spinozistic Ethics of Bertrand Russell. London: Allen & Unwin.
Bonjan-Peyron, C. (1983). Gene`se d’une illusion: La cr e`ation divine. Unpublished doctoral
dissertation, Universite´ d’Aix-Marseille.
Boss, G. (1990). ‘‘L’histoire chez Spinoza et Leibniz,’’ Studia Spinozana 6, 179-200.
_______. (1994). ‘‘Spinoza
et Leibniz: l’histoire.’’ In Esquisses de
dialogues philosophiques (pp. 234-257). Zurich: Editions du Grand Midi.
Bourel, D. (1981). ‘‘Leibniz
et Spinoza: un essai de conciliation chez Moses Mendelssohn.’’ In Theoria cum Praxi (Vol. XX#2, pp.
104-109). Hannover: Studia Leibniziana.
_______. (1990). ‘‘La re´futation de Spinoza par
Christian Wolff.’’ In O. Bloch (Ed.), Spinoza
au XVIIIe sie`cle (Actes des Journe´es d’Etudes a` la Sorbonne (1987), pp.
219-224). Paris: Me´ridiens Klincksieck.
Bouveresse, R. (1988). ‘‘Omnia quamvis diversis gradibus animata sunt Remarques due l’ide´e
d’animisme universel chez Spinoza et Leibniz.’’ In Rene´e Bouveresse (Ed.), Spinoza : Science et Religion (pp.
33-46). Paris: Vrin.
_______. (1992). Spinoza et Leibniz : l’ide´e d’animisme universel. Paris: Vrin.
Brunschvicq, L. (1951). Spinoza et ses contemporains (4th ed.). Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France.
Buchdahl, Gerd. (1969). Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science Cambridge (MA): MIT
Press.
Burbage, F., & Chouchan, N. (1993). Leibniz et l’infini. Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France.
Caspar, P. (1985). L’individuation des eˆtres: Aristote, Leibniz, et l’immunologie
contemporaine. Paris: Lethielleux.
Chazerans, J.-F. (1991).
‘‘La substance compose´e chez Leibniz,’’ Revue
Philosophique de la France et de l’Etranger 181, 47-66.
Couturat, Louis. (1972). ‘‘On Leibniz’s Metaphysics.’’ In
H. Frankfurt (Ed.), Leibniz (pp.
19-46). Garden City: Doubleday.
Craig, W. L. (1980). The Cosmological Argument from Plato to
Leibniz. New York: Barnes & Noble.
Curley, E. M. (1972). ‘‘The
Root of Contingency.’’ In H. G. Frankfurt (Ed.), Leibniz: Critical Essays (pp. 69-98). Garden City: Doubleday.
Dascal, M. (1990). ‘‘Spinoza
and Leibniz: Language and Cognition,’’ Studia
Spinozana 6, 103-146.
De Faria Blanc, M. (1996). ‘‘A Leitura hegeliana de
Espinoza e de Leibniz,’’ Philosophica (Portugal)
1996, 95-110.
Foucher de Careil, E.
(1857). Re´futation ine´dite de Spinoza
par Leibniz, pr e´ce d e´ d’un me´ ´moire. Paris: Brie`re. [Animadversiones ad Wachteri librum de
recondita Hebraeorum philosophia] _____. (1862). Leibniz, Descartes et Spinoza. Paris: Ladrange.
Frankfurt, H. (Ed.). (1972). Leibniz. Garden City: Doubleday.
Friedmann, G. (1962). Leibniz et Spinoza (2nd ed.). Paris:
Gallimard.
Furth, M. (1972). ‘‘Monadology.’’ In H. Frankfurt (Ed.), Leibniz (pp. 99-136). Garden City:
Doubleday.
Gagnebin, S. (1971). ‘‘La
synthe`se leibnizienne.’’ In A la
recherche d’un ordre naturel (pp. 337-360). Neuchatel: Baconnie`re.
Garrett, D. (1990). ‘‘Truth, Method, and Correspondence
in Spinoza and Leibniz.’’ Studia
Spinozana 6, 13-44.
Gueroult, Martial. (1934). Dynamique et me´taphysique leibniziennes.
Paris: Belles Lettres.
Hacking, Ian. (1972). ‘‘Individual Substance.’’ In H.
Frankfurt, Ed., Leibniz. Garden City:
Doubleday; 137-154.
Hart, A. (1982). ‘‘Leibniz
on Spinoza’s Concept of Substance,’’ Studia
Leibnitiana 14, 73-86.
Hicks, G. D. (1918). ‘‘The
‘Modes’ of Spinoza and the ‘Monads’ of Leibniz,’’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 18, 329-362.
Hubbeling, H. G. (1983).
‘‘The Understanding of Nature in Renaissance Philosophy: Leibniz and Spinoza.’’
In A. Heinekamp (Ed.), Leibniz et la
Renaissance (pp. 210-220). Wiesbaden: Franz Steiner Verlag.
Iriarte, J. (1938). ‘‘Le filosofia
‘geometrica’ en Descartes, Spinoza y Leibniz,’’ Gregorianum, 19, 481-497.
Ishiguro, H. (1972). ‘‘Leibniz’s Theory of the Ideality
of Relations.’’ In H. Frankfurt (Ed.), Leibniz
(pp. 191-214). Garden City: Doubleday.
Jolley, N. (1990). The Light of the Soul: Theories of Ideas in Leibniz, Malebranche, and
Descartes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Kneale, M. (1972). ‘‘Leibniz
and Spinoza on Activity.’’ In H. G. Frankfurt (Ed.), Leibniz: Critical Essays (pp. 215-238). Garden City: Doubleday.
Koistinen, Olli. (1998).
‘‘On the Consistency of Spinoza’s Modal Theory,’’ Southern Journal of Philosophy 36, 61-80.
Ko yre´, Alexandre. (1972).
‘‘Leibniz and Newton.’’ In H. Frankfurt (Ed.), Leibniz (pp. 239-280). Garden City: Doubleday.
Lovejoy, A. O. (1972).
‘‘Plenitude and Sufficient Reason in Leibniz and Spinoza.’’ In H. G. Frankfurt
(Ed.), Leibniz: Critical Essays (pp.
335-364). Garden City: Doubleday.
Lycan, W. G. (1972).
‘‘Materialism, and Leibniz’s Law,’’ Monist
56, 276-287.
Mates, B. (1972). ‘‘Leibniz on Possible Worlds.’’ In H.
Frankfurt (Ed.), Leibniz (pp.
335-364). Garden City: Doubleday.
_______. (1986). The
Philosophy of Leibniz: Metaphysics & Language. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Mayaud, Pierre-N. (Ed.).
(1991). Le proble`me de l’individuation.
Paris: Vrin.
McRae, R. (1983). ‘‘The Mind, Simple or Composite:
Leibniz versus Spinoza,’’ Southern
Journal of Philosophy 21, 111-120.
Mignini, F. (1985). ‘‘Le proble`me
de l’esthe´tique spinoziste a` la lumie`re de quelques interpre´tations, de
Leibniz a` Hegel.’’ In J. Bonnamour (Ed.), Spinoza
entre Lumie`res et Romantisme (pp. 123-142). Fontenay-aux-Roses: Ecole
Normale Supe´rieure.
Moreau, J. (1981). ‘‘Individuum und Natur bei Spinoza und
Leibniz,’’ In Theoria cum Praxi (Vol.
XX#2, pp. 130-137). Hannover: Studia Leibniziana.
Moreau, Pierre-Franc¸ois. (1978). ‘‘Nature et
Individualite´ chez Spinoza et Leibniz,’’ Revue
philosophique de Louvain 76, 447-455.
Morfino, V. (1994). Spinoza contra Leibniz, Documenti di uno scontro intellettuale
(1676-1678). Milan: Unicopli.
Mueler,
K. (1984). Leibniz Bibliographie.
Frankfurt am Main: Unknown.
Ortueta, J. de S. (1990).
‘‘Ethics and Politics in Spinoza and Leibniz,’’ Studia Spinozana 6, 201-218.
Panou, S. (1981). ‘‘Logos et
Ethos. Quelques remarques sur la politique morale de Leibniz et de Spinoza.’’
In Theoria cum Praxi (Vol. XX#2, pp.
152-155). Hannover: Studia Leibniziana.
Parkinson, G. H. R. (1978).
‘‘Leibniz’s Paris Writings in Relation to Spinoza,’’ Studia Leibnitiana 18, 73-89.
Philonenko, A. (1992).
‘‘Leibniz: Ve´rite´s de raison et ve´rite´s de fait.’’ In P.-F. Moreau, J.
Lagre´e, & M. Crampe-Casnabet (Eds.), Nature,
Croyance, Raison: Me´langes offerts a` Sylvain Zac (pp. 135-156). StCloud:
E. N. S. Fontenay.
Piro, F. (1987). ‘‘La
differenca tra ‘in se esse’ e ‘per se concipi.’ Sulla critica leibnizina a
Spinoza.,’’Instituto di Filosofia Annali
Due (Urbino) 1987, 69-111.
_______. (1994). ‘‘Una difficile
comparabilita`: Spinoza, Leibniz e l’animazione universale,’’ Rivista di Storia della Filosofia 49,
323331.
Pombo, O. (1990).
‘‘Comparative Lines Between Leibniz’s Theory of Language and Spinoza’s Reflexion
of Language Themes,’’ Studia Spinozana 6,
147-178.
Poser, H. (1981). ‘‘Zum
Verha¨ltnis von Beobachtung und Theorie bei Descartes, Spinoza und Leibniz,’’ Studia Leibnitiana 9, 117-146.
Robinet, A. (1980). ‘‘Mode`le ge´ome´trique et critique
informatique dans le discours spinozien,’’ Studia
Leibnitiana 12, 96-113.
_______. (1981). ‘‘Theoria
et Praxis chez Spinoza et Leibniz.’’ In Theoria
cum Praxi (Vol. XX#2, pp. 20-30). Hannover: Studia Leibniziana.
Ross, G. M., & Francks, R. (1996). ‘‘Descartes,
Spinoza, and Leibniz.’’ In N. F. Bunnin (Ed.), Blackwell Companion to Philosophy (pp. 509-529). Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
Russell, Bertrand. (1900). A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of
Leibniz. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Salas, J. (1992). ‘‘Politica
y e´tica de la tolerancia en Leibniz y Spinoza.’’ In A. Dominguez (Ed.), La Etica de Spinoza: Fundamentos y
significado (pp. 395-416). Castilla-La Mancha: Ediciones de la Universidad.
Schirmacher, W. (1981).
‘‘Ontologie und Ethik bei Spinoza und Leibniz.’’ In Theoria cum Praxi (Vol. XX#2, pp. 52-61). Hannover: Studia
Leibniziana.
Schuffenhauer, W. (1981). ‘‘Zu Ludwig Feuerbachs Spinoza
-und LeibnizBild.’’ In Theoria cum Praxi (Vol.
XX#2, pp. 110-122). Hannover: Studia Leibniziana.
Serres, M. (1968). Epime´the´e. Le syste`me de Leibniz et ses
mode`les mathe´matiques (2 Vols.). Paris: Presses Universitaires de France
Sleigh, R. C., Jr. (1990). ‘‘Leibniz and Malebranche on
Causality.’’ In J. A. Cover & M. Kulstad (Eds.), Central Themes in Early Modern
Philosophy (pp.
161- 194). Indianapolis: Hackett.
Verges, S. (1989).
‘‘Evolucion de los derechos humanos en Spinoza y Leibniz,’’ Pensamiento 45, 447-460.
Voise, W. (1981). ‘‘Aussere
und innere Freiheit: Spinoza, Leibniz und wir.’’ In Theoria cum Praxi (Vol. XX#2, pp. 145-151). Hannover: Studia
Leibniziana.
Vries, T. de. (1990).
‘‘Gespra¨ch aud der Grenzlinie: Leibniz bei Spinoza,’’ Studia Spinozana 6, 219-230.
Webb, M. O. (1989).
‘‘Natural Theology and the Concept of Perfection in Descartes, Spinoza, and
Leibniz,’’ Religious Studies 25,
459-475.
Wilson, M. D. (1972). ‘‘On Leibniz’s Explication of
‘Necessary Truth’.’’ In H. Frankfurt (Ed.), Leibniz
(pp. 401-420). Garden City: Doubleday.
Witzenmann, H. (1984). Ein Dreigestirn am Horizont unserer Epoche:
Descartes - Spinoza - Leibniz Dornach: Gideon Spicker.
Woolhouse, R. S. (1993). The Concept of Substance in Seventeenth
Century Metaphysics: Descartes, Leibniz, Spinoza. London: Routledge and Keg
an Paul.
Yakira, E. (1989). Contrainte, n e´cessite´, choix: la me´taphysique de la liberte´ chez
Spinoza et chez Leibniz Zurich: Edition du Grand Midi.
_______. (1990). ‘‘What is a
Mathematical Truth?’’ Studia Spinozana 6,
73-102.
A
Note on De Mairan and Spinozism Frederick
Ablondi Hendrix College
Several years ago, I
presented a paper to the North American Spinoza Society on Malebranche and
Spinozism. The paper looked specifically at Malebranche’s correspondence with
Dortous de Mairan.[62]For a brief review of the
argument which I presented, the following is from the published version of that
paper:
In 1713, just two years
before his death, Malebranche received the first of four letters from Dortous
de Mairan. The much younger de Mairan had recently read Spinoza’s Ethics, and was so impressed by its
arguments that he wrote to Malebranche, begging the French priest to point out
Spinoza’s errors, lest he (de Mairan) be forced to accept what he considered to
be its unpleasant implications. Malebranche, who responded to each of the four
letters, writes in his brief reply to de Mairan’s first letter that Spinoza’s
error was that ‘‘he takes the ideas of creatures for the creatures
themselves.’’[63] In his second
letter, de Mairan switches course and takes up a defense of Spinoza, claiming
in particular that Malebranche seems as much, if not more, guilty of the charge
he had leveled against Spinoza, namely, failing to adequately distinguish
between the idea of extension and extended bodies themselves. In his reply to
this letter, as well as in his replies to the next two of de Mairan’s letters,
Malebranche, in varying detail, does little more than repeat the objection
expressed in the first response: Spinoza mistakes the ideas of material bodies
for the bodies themselves, and in doing so, mistakenly claims that material
extension is eternal, necessary, and infinite.[64]
I went on to discuss Malebranche’s criticisms
of Spinoza, but rather than pursuing the force of these criticisms, I examined
specifically Mairan’s claim in his second letter that it was Malebranche
himself who fails to distinguish between objects and the ideas of those
objects. I concluded that given (what I argued to be) the proper understanding
of the nature and role of intelligible extension in Malebranche’s philosophy,
he was able to successfully escape Mairan’s charge of Spinozism.[65]
In the discussion which
followed my presentation, I was asked about the fate of M. de Mairan: did he
‘convert’ to Spinozism, or did Malebranche’s arguments persuade him of his
‘folly’? In the present note, I would like to respond (belatedly) to that
question.
***
It will be helpful to start
by looking at Mairan’s situation when he first writes to Malebranche in
September of 1713. He begins by saying that he has been spending much of the
last year concentrating on physics, studying works by Descartes, Pascal, and Malebranche
himself. Then he confides that he recently came into possession of some of the
works of Spinoza, though only The Ethics is
mentioned by name. He describes what followed:
I read him attentively, and he impressed me. I have since
reread
him, and I have meditated [about him] in solitude, and in what you call the
silence of the passions; but the more I read him, the more I find him sound and
full of good sense. In a word, I don’t know where to break the chain of his
demonstrations. However, the agitation that his overthrow of my first and
dearest ideas produces in me has sometimes made me resolve to abandon him. I
want to forget him. But when one is deeply moved by the desire to know the
truth, can one forget what has seemed so evident? On the one hand, I cannot
envisage without compassion for humanity, and without sorrow, the consequences
that follow from his principles; on the other hand, I cannot resist his
demonstrations. [OC XIX,
852; G 68]
As
noted, Mairan did not accept the charge Malebranche made against Spinoza in his
first response, and the correspondence ends with him still unconvinced of
Spinoza’s ‘error’. The question, then, is whether this can be taken as an
indication that Mairan ‘converted’ to Spinozism.
Genevie`ve Rodis-Lewis has
written on this question, concluding of Mairan that ‘‘en histoire il n’est
gue`re spinoziste.’’ [66] She claims that
the very fact the Mairan asks Malebranche to show him how to ‘‘break the chain
of [Spinoza’s] demonstrations’’ is an indication that he suspects these
demonstrations to be invalid, despite initial appearances. Further, she notes
Mairan’s belief that the history of China must be subordinated to that of Egypt
so as to reconcile certain chronological points in scripture — a decidedly un-Spinozistic
stance, given its adherence to such a literal reading of the Pentateuch.[67]
Marjorie Grene, while not
arguing that Mairan became a full-fledged Spinozist,[68]
suggests the case is not so clear cut. In response to RodisLewis, she
rightly points out that conversions, by their very nature, are often
accompanied by doubt and apprehension in their initial stages. She also notes
that Mairan’s interest in Spinoza sprung from his reading of The Ethics, not the Tr actatus theologico-politicus,[69]
so Mairan’s adherence to a literal reading of Hebrew scripture is
irrelevant to the question of his Spinozism. Further, there are notes made by
Mairan in 1730 on his copy of the letters which indicate that he was still
dissatisfied with Malebranche’s arguments against Spinoza. In the end, however,
Grene feels that ‘‘the debate on the question of whether or not Dortous De
Mairan is a
Spinozist. . . seems inconclusive.’’[70]
Other than the notes of 1730 mentioned
above, there is nothing in
Mairan’s later writings which explicitly
answers the question of his Spinozism. There is something, however, which is
partially indicative of Mairan’s influences and of his character in general.
Shortly after the end of the correspondence with Malebranche, Mairan began to
make something of a name for himself in the French physics community. In 1715
(the year of Malebranche’s death), Mairan captured the Acade´mie de Bordeaux’s
award for best memoir in physics; he would win the prize again in 1716 and
1717.[71][72]
1716 also saw the publication of what would be Mairan’s most recognized
scientific treatise, his Dissertation sur
la glace, and in 1718 he entered the Royal Academy of Sciences. The telling
point is with regard to the Dissertation:
Henry Guerlac notes that in the original edition, Mairan makes approving
reference to Newton’s Optiks,
something of a rarity at a time in the Academy when the Cartesian theory of
optics was generally preferred to Newton’s. Based on the Mairan-Malebranche
correspondence, Guerlac argues that ‘‘it is not difficult to infer that it was
Malebranche who first called young Dortous de Mairan’s attention to the
importance of Newton’s achievements.’’11
So
was Mairan a Spinozist? A Cartesian? A Newtonian? Guerlac offers his judgement:
Mairan ‘‘could far more correctly be called
Malbranchiste,
for [he] was profoundly influenced by that most openminded and scienti[73]fically curious of
seventeenth-century philosophers.’’[74]And
if by ‘Malebranchiste’ one means ‘open-minded and scientifically curious’, this
seems to be for the most part (i.e., excepting the Egypt-China matter) an
accurate description of Mairan’s philosophical spirit. In the end, however, I
think that it seems misguided to try to pigeon-hole Mairan at all. We can say
with Marjorie Grene that, at least with regard to science, he exhibited an
‘‘independent intellectual attitude.’’[75]
And we may further add that he comes across both in his correspondence
with Malebranche and his work in physics as a man more concerned with
discovering truth than one devoted to the dogma of a particular school.
NASS
Officers & Editorial Board (1998-99)
The
NASS Board serves as the Editorial Board for the NASS Monograph Series.
President: Paul
Bagley, Dept. of Philosophy, Loyola College, 4501 N. Charles St., Baltimore, MD
21210-2699. bagley@loyola.edu
Vice President: Douglas
Den Uyl, Dept. of Philosophy, Bellarmine College, Newburg Road, Louisville, KY
40205. DJDENU01@ulkyvx.louisville.edu
Executive Secretary: Steven
Barbone, Dept. of Philosophy, San Diego State University,San Diego, CA 92182.
barbone@rohan.sdsu.edu
EXECUTIVE
BOARD MEMBERS:
J.
Thomas Cook, Dept. of Philosophy, Box 2707, Rollins College, Winter Park, FL
32789-2139. TCOOK@ROLLINS.EDU
Idit
Dobbs-Weinstein, Dept. of Philosophy, Furman III, Vanderbilt University,
Nashville, TN 37235. dobbswi@ctrvax.vanderbilt,edu
Charles
Huenemann, Dept. of Philosophy, Utah State University, Logan UT 84322-0720.
hueneman@cc.usu.edu
S.
P. Kashap, Dept. of Philosophy, Cowell College, University of California, Santa
Cruz, CA 95064.
NASS
Monographs, Purchase Prices
Domestic (Canada and USA): $3.00
postpaid via third class. Foreign (all
others): $5.00 postpaid via airmail. No multiple copy discounts. All orders
must be prepaid.
Series
subscriptions are not accepted. Individuals or institutions on request will be
placed on a mailing list to automatically receive announcements and order forms
for new volumes in the NASS Monograph
Series as these are released.
All
orders and requests for information should be sent to the Executive Secretary
of NASS: [through 1998] Steven Barbone,
Dept. of Philosophy, San Diego State University, San Diego, CA 92182.
STUDIA
SPINOZANA
An
International & Interdisciplinary Series
Volumes
Published:
1 (1985)
— Spinoza’s philosophy of society.
2 (1986)
— Spinoza’s epistemology.
3 (1987)
— Spinoza and Hobbes.
4 (1988)
— Spinoza’s early writings.
5 (1989)
— Spinoza and literature.
6 (1990)
— Spinoza and Leibniz.
7 (1991)
— The ethics in the Ethics.
8 (1992)
— Spinoza’s psychology and social psychology.
Forthcoming:
9 (1993)
— Spinoza and modernity: Ethics and politics.
10 (1994)
— Spinoza and Descartes.
11 (1995)
— Spinoza’s philosophy of religion.
Verlag
Ko¨nigshausen & Neumann, W u¨rzburg, Germany.
Information
& U.S. orders: Dr. Douglas J. Den Uyl, Bellarmine College,
Newburg Road, Louisville, Kentucky 40205.
European Distributor:
Buchhandlung W. Sass, Richard-Wagner Strasse 19, D-30449 Hannover, Germany.
[1] . G. W. Leibniz, Te xtes ine´dits d’apr e`s les manuscrits de
la Bibliothe`que provinciale de Hanovre, publie´s et annote´s par Gaston
Grua (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1948). The notes on the Ethica are on 277-284.
[2] . Rene´e Bouveresse, Spinoza et Leibniz: L’ide´e d’animisme
universel (Paris: J. Vrin, 1992). For the Latin text, cf. 289-294; the
French translation (with Grua’s notes an abbreviations), 281-289; the
commentary, 217-276.
[3] . A. Foucher de Careil, Leibniz, Descartes et Spinoza (Paris:
Ladrange, 1862), 223-248. A new translation into French (without Latin text) by
V. Carraud appears in Philosophie #2
(April, 1984).
[4] . Published under the
title Re´futation ine´dite de Spinoza par
Leibniz, with notes and French translation by A. Foucher de Careil (Paris;
E. Brie`re, 1854).
[5] . See Bouveresse 217-230
for a summary of the rather contradictory published statements which Leibniz
made concerning Spinoza, a species of public duplicity which certainly justifies
the mistrust of the philosopher which Spinoza expresses in Ep72 (to G. H.
Schuller, 18 November 1675).
[6] . Letter to Justel, 4/14 February 1678, cited in L. Stein, Leibniz und Spinoza (Berlin: G.
Reimer, 1890), 307.
[7] . Bouveresse (217-276) provides many references in his
commentary on the general relation between the thinkers.
[8] . Cf. G. Friedmann, Leibniz
et Spinoza (Paris: Gallimard, 1946), 343-344.
[9] . See Lee C. Rice,
‘‘Paradoxes of Parallelism in Spinoza,’’ Iyyun
#48 (1999); and also Lee C. Rice, ‘‘Individuation in Leibniz and Spinoza,’’
following, for bibliographical information.
[10] . See Bouveresse 224-230
for a summary of Leibniz’s published remarks on Spinoza’s theory of eternity.
[11] . I am translating subjectum
as ‘substratum’ to avoid the wrong associations. (Tr.)
[12] . I.e., pertaining to the
essence of the thing. (Tr.) This is one of many examples where Leibniz has
attempted to clarify or reinterpret the text. E1Def4 states: ‘‘By attribute I
mean that which the intellect perceives of substance as constituting its
essence.’’
[13] . E1Def5: ‘‘By mode I
mean the affections of substance; that is, that which is in something else and
is conceived through something else.’’
[14] . Note the absence in
Leibniz’s summary of the spinozistic doctrine of an infinity of attributes.
E1Def3: ‘‘By God I mean an absolutely infinite being; that is, substance
consisting of infinite attributes, each of which expresses eternal and infinite
essence.’’
[15]
. E1Ax3: ‘‘From a given determinate cause there necessarily follows an effect;
on the other hand, if there be no determinate cause it is impossible that an
effect should follow.’’
[16] . This attempt to
introduce Leibniz’s own principle of sufficient reason appears to be based upon
a putative contradiction between E1P31 (which says that intellect is related to
natura naturata) and E1P33Schol2
(which provides a critique of the sort of teleology required by the principle
of sufficient reason).
[17] . The last sentence of
this note is difficult, and the Latin careless. I take it to mean that the word
‘impossible’ is not to be used of God except in the very restricted way
illustrated by the example. (Tr.)
[18] . See Bouveresse 239-241
for a brief discussion of Leibniz’s criticism and the putative contradiction.
Leibniz either misses or ignores the fact that for Spinoza the human intellect
is a part of the divine intellect,
and not properly speaking an effect of
it. So this criticism, as Bouveresse notes, is directed at Spinoza’s monism
rather than at any logical contradiction between E1P17Schol and E1P3.
[19] . Leibniz appears here to
be arguing against Spinoza’s frequent use of mathematical entities to
illustrate relations between real objects, whereas on Spinoza’s own count these
entities are only entia imaginationis.
[20] . The second claim (dealing with Natura naturata) is underlined in the manuscript.
[21] . The last phrase (here
following the semicolon) is underlined in the manuscript. Once again Leibniz’s
criticism is directed at Spinoza’s monism rather than at the coherence of E2P3.
Under Spinoza’s definition of it, what follows from the essence of substance is
part of substance itself.
[22] . animata — beminded,
besouled. (Tr.)
[23]
. This entire sentence is underlined
in the manuscript. For the similarities and differences between spinozistic and
leibnizean ‘animism’ see Bouveresse 185-216.
[24] . This remark appears to
be an adumbration of Leibniz’s own efforts to reduce external relations to
properties (the doctrine that the monads are ‘windowless’), an effort which was
nev er entirely successful. In Spinoza a relation which is external to one individual
will be internal to higher-order individuals of which the first individual is a
part. Gueroult regards Leibniz’s doctrine of windowlessness as an attempt to
avoid problems which Leibniz finds in Spinoza’s own account of individuation
following E2P13. See Martial Gueroult, Dynamique
et me´taphysique leibnizienne (Paris: Belles Lettres, 1934), 180-194.
Bouveresse 236-239 also provides a summary.
[25] . consequentiae is
crossed out and replaced by conclusionis in
the manuscript.
[26] . Leibniz is correct as
far as he goes. Spinoza appears to have two senses of ‘thing’, of which
Leibniz’s remark denotes the most general. Often, however, the sense of res is in contradistinction to that of idea.
[27]
. This appears to be a legitimate critique of Spinoza’s remark that universal
knowledge arises from blurred sensory images (plural); since, as Leibniz notes,
we can formulate a species-characterization whose extension is a unit set.
[28] . It is interesting to
note that Leibniz summarizes Spinoza’s account of the three kinds of knowledge
in E2P40Schol2 without any criticism. Does he perhaps view the distinction
between the three kinds of knowledge as being less important and less
problematic to Spinoza’s methodology than many subsequent commentators?
[29] . This entire sentence is underlined in the manuscript.
[30]
. Bouveresse notes (287) that this statement represents the first formulation by Leibniz of what he
will later call his own parallelism in contrast to his interpretation of
Spinoza’s parallelism (first stated at E2P7). The thinkers are of one mind in
their opposition to occasionalism. See Bouveresse 244-247 for a detailed
analysis.
[31]
. Skinner makes a similar point in Beyond
Freedom and Dignity about the James-Lang theory of emotion, of which
Spinoza’s account is generally presumed to be the predecessor. Skinner notes
that the running away and the fear are not causally related because they are
simultaneous. If we take Spinoza’s ‘‘striving’’ as a mental event rather than
as a physical one, however, Spinoza’s claim can be interpreted as a causal one.
[32] . What is common, of
course, is that they are all and only the primitive affects. Leibniz may be
suggesting here that, since desire is itself identified with conatus, its status as a primitive
affect is questionable. A similar objection is lodged by Jonathan Bennett, A Study of Spinoza’s Ethics (Indianapolis:
Hackett, 1984), 258-261.
[33]
. Bouveresse (288) sees this remark as part of a more extended critique (which
Leibniz will give in his comments De Deo of
Spinoza’s notion of eternity), but the connexion appears difficult to see.
Perhaps Leibniz is here attempting to introduce the notion of contingency as a
component of our knowledge of future events, and thus avoid spinozistic
determinism. His later attempts to avoid rigid determinism in his own ontology
have been severely challenged by even Leibniz’s most sympathetic commentators.
[34] . E4P69: ‘‘The virtue of
a free man is seen to be as great in avoiding dangers as in overcoming them.’’
In a certain sense this proposition illustrates Spinoza’s own lifestyle. He
prevented the translation of the TTP into Dutch to avoid its accessibility to
the vulgus, and was probably not
entirely open when he met and spoke with Leibniz. The motto on his family coat
of arms was ‘‘Caute’’ (‘‘Be Careful’’).
[35] . Leibniz appears quite
correct in finding some obscurity in E4P72Schol, which deals with the modern
highway robber paradox. For commentary and an effort at clarification of the
scholium, see Lee C. Rice, ‘‘Spinoza and Highway Robbery,’’ Archiv fu¨r Geschichte der Philosophie,
1998.
[36]
. Leibniz has already dealt approvingly with Spinoza’s account of (bodily)
individuation in the opening comments on E2. His objection here is probably to
the parallelistic argument for the individuation of the mind. Leibniz’s later
development of the concept of mind as a ‘dominant monad’ was perhaps a reaction
to the mind-body unity claim underlying Spinoza’s parallelism.
[37] . See C. G. Gebhardt, Die philosophischen Schriften von Gotfried
Wilhelm von Leibniz (Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlag, 1960), Vol. 4, 17-26.
[38] . This work was written thirteen years later, after Leibniz’s
visit to Paris (1672-1676) and one year after his discovery of the infinitesimal
calculus. For the early development and subsequent chronology, see
Bitbol-Hespe´rie`s (1991), 79-81.
[39] . Animadversiones ad Wachteri librum. See Foucher de Careil (1857). A
brief commentary and critique of Foucher de Careil is provided in Bouveresse
(1992, 188-191). Wachter’s book, together with a complete account of Leibniz’s
critique of it, is summarized in Friedmann (1962, 155-178).
[40] . Reprinted in Oeuvres
philosophiques de Leibniz, with introduction and notes by P.
Janet, 2 volumes
(Paris: Ladrange, 1866); II, 570-572.
[41]
. For details on Spinoza’s nominalism, see Lee Rice, ‘‘Le nominalisme de
Spinoza,’’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy
24 (1994), 19-32.
[42] . Nouveaux essais sur l’entendement humain (Paris:
Garnier-Flammarion, 1966), III, 3#6, 248-249.
[43] . See Discours 14, 47-48; and Hide´ Ishiguro,
‘‘Leibniz’s Theory of the Ideality of Relations,’’ in Frankfurt (1976,
191-214).
[44] . ‘‘Leibniz’s
Predicate-in-Notion Principle,’’ in Frankfurt 1972, 1-18. Lycan (1972) and
Ishiguro (1972) offer similar arguments.
[45] . Buchdahl (1969,
454-455) sees in this consequence an anticipation of Kant’s notion of noumenal
reality.
[46] . See Bouveresse (1992, 85-90).
[47]
. For details of Leibniz’s theory of the conservation of mv**2, see Bouveresse
(1988), Bouveresse (1992, 91-93), Buchdahl (1969, 415-424), Chazerans (1991),
Friedmann (1962, 120-124), and Lycan (1972). It is also interesting to note
that the development of a conservation principle for corporeal reality itself
immediately postdated Leibniz’s first contacts with spinozism (1669-1679): see
Friedmann (1962, 59-76).
[48] . It is in fact the
integral of the inert forces. See Bouveresse (1992, 97-100) and Buchdahl (1969,
406-408).
[49] . See Hacking (1976, 148-150) for a more detailed discussion of
this correspondence.
[50] . The use of analogies in
Leibniz’s extrapolation from physics to metaphysics is emphasized by Buchdahl
(1969, 434-438), particularly for Leibniz’s principle of continuity, where
Buchdahl claims that there is a ‘‘gap between the technical case which originally
led to the idea of continuity becoming established,
and its generalisation by extrapolation to a much wider field’’ (ibid., 435). I suspect that this is the
case for the principles of individuation as well.
[51] . Yet another, of course, is Malebranche’s occasionalism.
[52] . This is why Spinoza
predicates conatus only of finite modes. While substance itself is
an infinite force, its source of auto-determination is entirely intrinsic.
[53] . See E1Def5, E1P28, and E2Def1.
[54] . The temporality of
ideas in Spinoza’s model has been denied by some interpreters. I think that
Michael Della Rocca’s arguments here are quite decisive. See his Representation and the Mind-Body Problem in
Spinoza (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), esp. 44-67.
[55] . See Jonathan Bennett, A
Study of Spinoza’s Ethics (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1984), esp.
[56] -110.
[57]
. I owe this insight to Edwin Curley. See his Spinoza’s Metaphysics: An Essay in Interpretation (Cambridge (MA):
Harvard University Press, 1969), 50-55.
[58] . This is also why the
civil community or state for Spinoza is not an individual, but only a
pseudo-individual; but that is another story.
[59]
. I follow Bennett here in claiming that Spinoza meant what he wrote when he
deals with ‘an infinity of attributes’, rather than those interpreters who
claim that ‘infinity’ = ‘all there are’ = ‘2’.
[60] . I am here implicitly
agreeing with Bennett’s claim that parallelism is a correlation between
psychological and physical models, not between logical and physical ones, as
Curley argues. I am also in at least partial agreement with Bennett that
Spinoza’s argument for E2P7 is awful. Michael Della Rocca [Representation and the Mind-Body Problem in Spinoza (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1996), 18-43] does succeed, however, in supplying an
alternative argument which is more logically plausible than the alternative
offered by Bennett (127-135).
[61]
. See his ‘‘Comments on Spinoza’s
Philosophy (1707?)’’ in Ariew and Garber (272-281), and also Friedmann (1962,
225-230).
[62] . The paper was given December 27, 1995 at the NASS meeting held
in conjunction with the Eastern Division meeting of the APA in New York City.
[63] . OC XIX, 855; G 70.
References to Malebranche’s works are to the Oeuvres comple`tes, 20 vols., Andre´ Robinet, dir. (Paris,
1959-66), referred to hereafter as ‘OC’, followed by volume number, page
number. Passages of the Malebranche-de Mairan correspondence are from Marjorie
Grene’s translation, contained in Malebranche’s
First and Last Ctitics (Carbondale: Southern Illinois Press, 1995), and
referred hereafter as ‘G’.
[64] . ‘‘Le Spinoziste Malgr e´ Lui?: Malebranche, De Mairan, and
Intelligible Extension,’’ History of
Philosophy Quarterly (April 1998), 191.
[65] . For those interested in
more information on the correspondence, see Daisie Radner, ‘‘Malebranche’s
Refutation of Spinoza,’’ in Spinoza: New
Perspectives, ed. Robert W. Shahan and J. I. Biro (Norman: University of
Oklahoma Press, 1978), 113-128; and George S. Getchev, ‘‘Some of Malebranche’s
reactions to Spinoza revealed in his correspondence with Dortous de Mairan,’’ Philosophical Review 41 (1932), 385-394.
Joseph Moreau’s introduction to the Vrin edition of the correspondence (1947)
provides some useful insights into Malebranche and Spinozism. Richard Watson’s
‘‘Foucher’s and de Mairan’s Critiques of Malebranche’s Beings of the Third
Kind,’’ The Southern Journal of
Philosophy XXXIV (1996), 125-134, argues against my conclusion in the HPQ
article (op. cit.), claiming that
‘‘de Mairan does get Malebranche, and
gets him good’’ (130).
[66] . Genevie`ve Rodis-Lewis,
‘‘Dortous De Mairan fut-il spinoziste?’’ Revue
de me´taphysique et de morale 93 (1988): 165.
[67] . According to
Rodis-Lewis, Mairan’s writings on this matter ‘‘montrent qu’il n’a pas e´te´
convaincu que la subordination de la Chine a` la civilisation e´gyptienne, qui
avait instruit Moi¨se, est une fable. Quelle que soit sa since´rite´ dans son
apparent retour a` une tradition chre´tienne, il n’est suˆrement pas spinoziste
en histoire’’ (ibid., 171-72).
[68] . As has Paul Vernie`re.
His conclusion on the matter is that ‘‘l’objectivite´ de Dortous de Mairan
l’entreine jusqu’a` la conversion au spinozisme’’[Spinoza et la pense´e franc¸aise avant la r e´volution (Paris:
Presse Universitaires de France, 1954), 279; quoted in Rodis-Lewis (ibid.), 166].
[69] . It is not entirely
clear that this is true; all Mairan says is that ‘‘the works of S., especially his Ethics or his philosophy, came into my possession’’ (G 68, my
emphasis). On the other hand, Mairan does specifically praise the ‘‘geometrical
form of his work’’ (ibid.),
suggesting that Mairan has only The
Ethics in mind.
[70] . >From Grene’s introduction to her translation, 64.
[71] . I am indebted for this
and for much of the historical information which follows to Henry Guerlac
[‘‘The Newtonianism Of Dortous De Mairan,’’ in Essays and Papers in the History of Modern Science (Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1977):
[72] -90].
[73] . Guerlac, 485. It should
not be surprising to see Malebranche breaking ranks with the Cartesians;
despite being firmly grounded in the Cartesian tradition, in physics — as in
other areas — Malebranche went his own way, and was gracious enough to concede
to a rival (as Newton was, with regard to their respective theories of color)
if he became convinced of the other’s truth. This is in fact just what
happened, as can be seen in the 16th E´claircissement
in the 6th (1712) edition of Recherche
de la v e´rite´. On this point, see Paul Mouy, ‘‘Malebranche et Newton,’’ Revue de me´taphysique et de morale 45
(1938): 411-435.
[74] . Ibid., 487.
[75] . Introduction, 65.
-------------