2021/03/03

Bioethics as a way of resistance to biopolitics and biopowers

 

 



Update articles





Bioethics as a way of resistance to biopolitics and biopowers



Fermin Roland Schramm




Fermin Roland Schramm

PhD, professor at the National School of Public Health (Ensp/Fiocruz) and at the University of Brasília (UnB), researcher at the national Institute of Cancer (Inca), Rio de Janeiro/Brasília, Brazil



Abstract The work attempts to deconstruct the concepts of biopolitics and biopower and seeks to create conditions for a correct action of bioethics, understood both as an analytical tool and normative of the morality of biopolitics and biopower and as practical application in the form of democratic resistance and dissidence with respect to morally questionable purposes, resulting from biopolitical practices and the improper use of such concepts to perform them. Their assumption is that the concepts of biopolitics and biopower are used most of times, in an inconsistent way or as passepartout words, which affects its power of intelligibility for understanding the profound changes in contemporary society, including with respect to perceptions of itself while a 'living system'. Deconstruction is therefore a necessary pre-operation due to the subsumption of ethics to politics, supposedly legitimized by the common reference to "life", indicated by the Greek word bios, which, however, reveals itself inextricably linked to zoé, if not subsumed to this. Finally, this paper discusses the proposals for biopolitical democracy and democratic biopolitics, showing the need for a bioethical control of biopolitics.



Key-words: Bioethics. Biopolitics. Control. Justice. Immunity.







This work attempts to deconstruct the concepts of biopower and biopolitics and aims to detect the contradictions resulting from the misuse of these two concepts, showing some interpretative conflicts involved. Deconstruction is understood here in the sense given by Derrida, that is, a practice of critical reading of the speeches that take refuge in the concepts of biopower and biopolitics and a method - or strategy - to analyze the existing imaginary and symbolic constructions, but highlighting the need to reconstruct what has been forgotten or repressed in them, from what anyone believes that ethics cannot be deconstructed: justice - which can also be understood as a principle, both formal and substantive in any ethics and / or policy. The conception of justice as originates from the formal principle of Aristotle, who considered it the architectural virtue that sustains and should govern the common life.



For Derrida, this procedure for the dismantling of categories, concepts and speeches, thanks to the practice of critical reading, is achieved through a thinking of structured genealogy of its concepts as faithful and internal way as possible, but at the same time external, determining that what this story could conceal or forbid, becoming history through this repression somehow interested.1



The assumption of this approach is that deconstruction is a necessary condition for bioethics to be able to fulfill not only its dual descriptive and normative role in relation to moral facts, i.e., of rational and impartial analysis of the morality of the facts of biopolitics and biopower, proposing rules to regulate the conflicts involved, but also to provide support to the recipients of these facts, thanks to justice, which, for Derrida, would be that which cannot be deconstructed and that encourages and legitimizes the project of deconstruction. Furthermore, it also assumes the existence of the roles of resistance and dissence regarding the attempts to subsume the bioethical problematic and the biopolitical problematic, i.e., of submitting or subsuming ethical questioning to supposed pragmatic needs of a political realism, considered the most concrete, effective and legitimate in its management of bodies, populations and life in general, but which may in fact be a mere cynicism and justification for biopolitical practices that continue to be morally questionable because they are unjust.



Particularly, the operation of deconstruction has a practical effect, because it can be considered a necessary condition in order a pluralistic and secular bioethics can be rebuilt as a tool of resistance to the unfair effects resulting from uses and abuses of biopolitics, having as a paradigmatic reference the authoritarian and bioethical power represented by Nazism. In short, deconstruction is an analytical and interpretative method of moral conflicts placed on biopolitics, but also a practical tool that justifies bioethical practices questioning biopolitics and biopower.



In fact, the concepts of biopolitics and biopower are used often on an inconsistently and unnecessary way, or as passe-partout words (or clichés), including two in the field of bioethics2, reason why it seems to be necessary their deconstruction so a field of criticism of the existing can be rebuilt, as can be that of bioethics, grounded by 'undesconstructability' of justice that makes deconstruction possible 3.



Thinking in terms of genealogy, when it comes to biopolitics and biopower a mandatory reference and the text by Michel Foucault's The Will to Knowledge, 1976, in which, its final chapter presents a first systematic reflection of these two concepts, relating them with the forms of power (and power-knowledge) on the vital processes in the fields of health and hygiene, production and reproduction, but trying to avoid any kind of anthropologism in their approaches 4.



Another author who became a constant reference and Giorgio Agamben, with the work Homo sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, published in 1995, which incorporates the concept of biopolitics, but deconstructs the concepts of bare life and homo sacer and focuses its attention on the power devices over the biological body, having as a paradigmatic reference the concentration camp 5.



A third author also became, recently, a reference. He is Roberto Esposito, who in 2004 launched Bios: Biopolitics and Philosophy, in which he retakes and reconfigures the project of Foucault and Agamben, aimed at the concept of biopolitics from the deconstruction of the concept of bios and relating biopolitics and tana politics to understand the enigma of biopolitics and try its affirmative reconversion, i.e., in terms of democratic biopolitics or biopolitical democracy, but without distinguishing the two possible reconfigurations 6.



However, none of the three authors made explicit reference to bioethics which, on the contrary, is made by bioethicists dealing with biopolitics, as it is the case of sanitary bioethics, which, however, must face this confrontation with biopolitics, including with the internal criticism that would have detected internal faults and failures that have led to suggest the replacement of the shortcomings inherent to an applied ethics for a more effective and robust biopolitics 7. Therefore, the need to see what, indeed, may indicate the terms biopolitics and biopower, and which they are or may be, the relationship between biopolitics, biopower, and bioethics, or, rather, between the so-called political realism personified by biopolitics and biopower, and the political justice, personified by a correctly interpreting and acting bioethics.


The problematic biopolitics word



The word biopolitics appears in the Houaiss Dictionary of Portuguese Language, which gives the following ambiguous definition: an interdisciplinary science that studies the integration and reconciliation of modern society and its institutions with the infrastructure of basic organic support (nature, climate, soil health, water purity etc.) 8. But the word does not appear in the Novo Aurelio of the 21st Century.



Such ambiguity does not appear to be due to chance, since what characterizes biopolitics would be a clear conceptual vagueness, since that the concept of biopolitics appears crossed by an uncertainty [that] prevents any stable connotation [and that] seems to make him not only the instrument but also an object of a harsh political and philosophical confrontation about the configuration and the fate of our time, raising the question of knowing: how a policy that will be directly addressed to it should be thought? 9



One of the consequences relevant to bioethics and the ambiguity and vagueness of the biopolitics concept allows it to be used to connote phenomena seemingly antithetical, as can be, on the one hand, contemporary policies for care, protection and welfare - as were and still are the public policies of democratic states – and on the other hand, the ways that biotanatopolíticas that conceived the state as a body that must be immunized against pathogenic elements - such as, for example, biocracy of Nazi politics.



On the first connotation, biopolitics applies to government practices defined as forms of biopower that, according to Foucault, aim to ensure and strengthen the population's health through the control and intervention over births, morbidities, skills and environment, and also through the control, management and intervention over the human body (the individual) and over the human species (this being understood more than as polis or society than as biological species).

In this case, the concepts of bios and polis may have two types of relationship: a) a relationship among themselves with no priority of a concept over another - that linguists call paratactic and that may also be the form of an interface, or b) a relationship of subsumption of the first (bios) in relation to the second (polis) - called by linguists hypotactic - which corresponds roughly to the type of relationship existing in the Greek period.



This hypotactic relationship was recovered by Hannah Arendt, when the philosopher tries to restore the difference made by Aristotle (but unlit by modernity) between bios and zoé, understanding this as the biological life which man shares with other living beings and that as the specifically human life (…) full of events which can later be narrated as history and establish a biography 10. But in this second circumstance, rather than a interface between bios and polis we have a subsumption which can be either the bios of the polls – that is that the case referred to by Aristotle and Arendt - as an annexation (Anschluss) of the polis to bios, that is, a policy submitted to biology and its laws, as was certainly the case in Nazi biocracy.



However, a clear distinction between the two conceptions is not always easy to do, and one of such amphibologies or conceptual duplicity can be seen in public health itself, where sanitary policies seem to oscillate between the poles of medicalization of life, encouraged, mainly by the pharmaceutical industry 11, and politics itself (we could say), encouraged by the sanitary movement which led to the Unified Health System (SUS) and established focal points between health sciences, political science, human science and social movements. That is, where aspects of biopolitics and biopower are manifest in the fact that sanitary policies manage, discipline and control the bodies, lives, morbidity and death of populations under their responsibility (or management) but leaving uncovered the question of the ethical and bioethical aspects involved by becoming the inclusion of life in the devices of biopolitics and biopower applied to the perception and management of collective health. And this seems to be one of the priority tasks of sanitary bioethics, which shall begin its work analyzing its possible links with biopolitics and biopower.


The biopolitics-biopower– bioethics set ad its relationship with bios



The conceptual relationships between biopolitics, biopower and bioethics can be detected by analyzing the common reference to the prefix bios, noting that the relationship is not necessarily the same for the three and that this is due probably to the problematic use of the concept 'life' in bioethics and [to] their interfaces [established] with the biopolitical praxis and the biopower devices 12, which are not very clear.



For Agamben, behind this ambiguity there would be a real indistinction between the zoé and bios concepts themselves, which for the Greeks (who created such terms) indicated realities distinct from life as a whole: the simple natural life (zoé) and a particular way of life (bios), i.e., life in general and qualified lifestyle that is typical of men, immersed in the biological body and [in the] political body 13. This distinction will be eliminated from the Modernity, when confusion will be installed between the two concepts that Agamben considers the decisive fact in the origin of the totalitarian biopolitics of the twentieth century. When bios and zoé, right and fact, enter into a zone of irreducible blur, one can affirm that this entry of zoé in the sphere of polis, the politicization of bare life as such, constitutes the decisive event of modernity, which marks a radical transformation of the political-philosophical categories classic thinking14.



Thus, the blurring may become confused when we consider that bioethics, biopolitics and biopower have as a common reference the bios concept, allowing, for example, that to one speaks, on the one hand, on life ethics, politics of life and power of life, but also, on the other hand, in ethics about life, politics, about life and power over life. But this common reference to the bios term does not allow so say that it is the same meaning of life being referred to, even assuming the classic distinction between bios and zoé, since the two prepositions of and about indicate different relationships between politics and life. In particular, the reference to bios made by the biopower / biopolitics - in which the first refers to devices for the effective exercise of power over life represented by biopolitics and the second to the policy aimed to implement and manage biopower - has in fact a nature different from that of bioethics, when this is understood as bioethics of life and not on power against biopower, i.e., as empowerment of citizens.15



Moreover, until the present moment, it has not been established any consensus on relations between biopolitics and biopower or between potency and power. There is, for example, some who consider that the relationship paratactic relationship biopower- biopolitics (which is in substance Foucault's position) can be seen as an biopower / biopolitics opposition. This dichotomy between the two concepts is considered, for example, by Toni Negri and Michael Hardt, who define biopower - represented by power of the crowd - as opposed to biopolitics or as a form of resistance to it 16.



This form of resistance can, for example, be seen as a rejection of the repressive hypothesis according to which modern power censures, interdicts and represses freedom and desire, since the power would be less what prevents than what produces, and life is not simply the victim of its repression. Upgrading its resources and potentialities biopower [would give] to life the necessary weapons to its emancipation, as if life should pass through biopower to access to a full system of subjectivity. So biopower would reveal from the exterior the productive dynamism immanent from vital powers, exploring them and moving them, being, therefore, a transformation of this power over life in a power of life, to find again the conditions for a fully developed life. 17 . However, according to Jacques Rancière, this would eventually reaffirm a life rooting of politics18 - which, as discussed below, may represent one of its most questionable forms, according to its full biocratic version.


The need to deconstruct biopolitics



As shown by Esposito6, the term biopolitics (or bio-politics) has conceptual background since at least the early twentieth century, with the appearance of the geopolitical conception of vital space and biogeographic state19 or that of State understood as an organism, which would have anatomy and physiology of its own to be protected by state medicine 20



In 1911 the term biopolitics emerges, with the following explanation: the term 'biopolitics' means a policy that should consider two aspects of nation: first, the increase in population and competition, and secondly, the individual attributes of human that are available to fill posts of responsibility in the State.21



In 1920 appears the term biopolitics (without hyphen) associated with a vitalistic conception of State, conceived as a body with natural instincts and impulses, but still leaves space for the specificities of bios: this strain characteristic of life itself (...) led me to call such his discipline biopolitics, by analogy with [a] biology; it is better understood when one considers that the Greek word 'bios' means not only the natural, physically life, but still but also in an equally significant measure the cultural life. This designation is also intended to express that dependence on the laws of life that society expressed herein and promotes the state itself [to] the role of arbitrator or at least of a mediator 22.



When spelled bio-politics the word reappears with the installation of Nazi biocracy when bios is subsumed to zoé and bio-politics will be understood as the study of the risks and diseases of the social body, and associated to the question of the immune defense to be assumed by policy 23. The many meanings of biopolitics were preserved throughout the twentieth century. For example, biopolitics perceived as a policy guided by the life sciences as 24 or as a strategy of compatibilization between the human gender and the environment 25, with respect to linkages between politics and life sciences, in particular the subsumption of politics and biology.



But the term is also re-sementicized in a neohumanist key after the defeat of Nazism: [a] biopolitics does not deny [the] blind forces of violence and the will of power, nor the self-destructive forces that exist in man and in human civilization [because] these forces are elemental forces of life. But biopolitics denies that such forces are fatal and that cannot be contradicted and directed by spiritual forces - the forces of justice, charity, clarity, the truth 26.



In this respect it is worth remembering also the "ontopolitica" conception of Edgar Morin, aimed at subtracting the evolution of mankind from economicism and productivism in favor of a multidimensional policy of man, so that all paths of life and all the ways of politics begin to meet and interpenetrate themselves, and announce a ontopolitics, respecting more and more and globally the human being 27.



Finally, we must remember the neo-naturalistic concept, a trend that is still present and that refers to nature as a parameter for determining politics, influenced by Darwinism (Social), ethology and sociobiology: [biopolitics and the] term commonly used to describe the approach of the political scientists who use biological concepts (especially the Darwinian evolutionary theory) and techniques of biological research to study, explain, predict and sometimes also prescribe political behavior 28.



It can be deducted from this rapid genealogy that the extension of the semantic field of biopolitics and from the Foucault conference in Rio de Janeiro, in 197429 and the subsequent publication of his book The Will to Knowledge , in 1976, the term biopolitics spread among scientists concerned in studying and understanding the social and political transformations of our time.



In the 1974 lecture, Foucault had used the term bio-politics associating it to the body and medicine, regarding it as a capitalistic strategy: for the capitalistic society the biopolitics is what is important before anything else: the biological, the somatic, the corporeal. The body is a bio-political reality; medicine is a biopolitical strategy 29. Subsequently he moved away from previous conceptions of biopolitics, although it shares its criticisms to modernity: 'Biopolitics'shouçld be understood as the way by which, from the eighteenth century, it was sought to rationalize the problems posed for governmental practice by the phenomena peculiar of a set of living being while population: health, hygiene, birth, longevity, race 30.



In another text he specifies the meaning of biopower: it seems to me that one of the fundamental phenomena of the nineteenth century has been, [and] is that the power has assumed life, in a perspective that we could call welfare. It is, so to speak, a catching of power over man as a living being, of a kind of statization of the biological, or at least a trend toward to what we could call the statization of the biological (...) something that is no longer an anatomo-politics of human body, but that would call a 'biopolitics of the human species 31.



In the critical evaluation by Esposito – recognizing the Foucauldian change in the genealogy of biopolitics as we understand it today – in a few years, the notion of 'biopolitics' (...) opened a completely new phase of contemporary reflection. Since Foucault (…) proposed again and reclassified the concept, the whole quadrant of political philosophy was profoundly modified. It did not left the scene [classical categories] as those of 'right', 'sovereignty' or 'democracy' (...). But his meaning effect is increasingly weak [and] the normalization process increasingly invades ample spaces 32.


Three references: Foucault, Agamben and Esposito



When talking about biopower and biopolitics the first mandatory reference is almost always an affirmation of the final chapter of History of sexuality 1- The will to know – in which Foucault writes: for millennia man remained what he was for Aristotle: a living animal with the additional capacity for a political existence; modern man is an animal whose politics places his existence as a living being in question33. And in this text the author introduces the term biopolitics by writing:: we must speak of 'biopolitics' to designate what makes life and its mechanisms enter in the field of explicit calculations and makes power-knowledge a change agent of human life 34.



Another important reference is Homo sacer: the sovereign power and bare life, by Agamben 5, in which the author develops the concepts of bare life and homo sacer in order to rethink the categories of biopolitics and biopower, the light of the Nazi pragmatic biocracy and its extermination device (Shoah), represented by the concentration camp. In a subsequent text, he considered that in contemporary biopolitics there would not be actually a submission of the bios to zoé, but rather a mysterious disconnection between them: in our culture has always been the human was always thought as an articulation and a conjunction of a body and a soul, of a living being and a logos of a natural element (or animal) and a supernatural, social or divine element. We must instead learn to think man as that which results from the disconnection of these elements and examine [the] practical and political mystery of separation 35.



In the genealogy done by Agamben what would prevail in the current biopolitical debates would point out to an indistinction between the zoé and bios concepts, where the disappearance of such distinction would correspond to the emergence of totalitarian biopolitics of the twentieth century. For him, in this case, the terms bios and zoé, right and fact, enter into a zone of irreducible indistinction, because its current use reveals the entry of zoé in the sphere of the polis, the politicization of bare life as such, [which would make] the decisive event of modernity, which marks a radical transformation of the political-philosophical categories of classic thought 36.



In this sense, the double fundamental category of Western policy not [would be] that friend-enemy, but bare life-political existence, zoé-bios, inclusion-exclusion. A conclusion that derives from the fact that politics exists because man is the living being who, in language, separates and opposes to it the very bare life itself and, at the same time, remains in a relationship with it in an inclusive exclusion, since modern democracy compared to the classic one [has] a claim and a release of zoé, [and because] it seeks constantly to transform the same bare life in terms of life and [find], so to speak, bios zoé 37.



In short, the implication of bare life in the political sphere constitutes the original nucleus – although disguised - of sovereign power. One could say that the production of a biopolitical body is the original contribution of the sovereign power and that biopolitics is, in this sense, at least as old as the sovereign exception, since putting biological life in the center of its calculations the modern state [redirects] to light the secret link that unites the power to bare life 38.

The third reference is the work Bios: Biopolitics and philosophy, by Esposito. For him, what would characterize the concept of biopolitics would be not only its patent conceptual indefinition - highlighted by Agamben - but also – and more radically - a biologicist view of biopolitics, that would make it morally and politically dangerous, since a policy built directly on the bios has the risk of overlapping violently bios to policy 39. The author also criticizes what he considers an anthropological reductionism of biopolitics since in, the concept of biopolitics is in danger of losing weight to the point of losing its identity, becoming a form of traditional humanism 40, in fact incapable of facing the challenges represented in the inter-relationship between life and politics.



Finally, to Esposito, we should also refuse the naturalistic conception, due to confusion between the descriptive aspect and the prescriptive aspect in which it holds itself and that would actually make the argumentation and justification circular. Indeed, in this conception the resulting notion of biopolitics is this time sufficiently clear, but if the political behavior is inextricably wired in the size of the bios and the bios is what binds man to the sphere of nature, the only possible politics shall be that already registered natural in our natural code. In this case, every argumentation would be based in a rhetorical circuit in which theory does not interpret reality, but reality dictates a theory to confirm it. That is, the enigma of biopolitics seems solved - but in a way that gives as an assumption exactly what ones was looking for.41



Esposito also notes that, apparently, all the confusion seems to arise from the very word bios, because if we put our trust to the Greek lexicon (...) more than to the term bios, understood in the sense of 'qualified life' or 'way of life, 'biopolitics refers to the zoé dimension, i.e., of life in its simplest biological expression, or to the line of conjunction along which bios emerges over the zoé also naturalizing itself. But [because of ] from this change in terminology the idea of biopolitics seems to be in a zone of double indiscernibility 42.



Therefore, it could be said that there is a dual indiscernibility in the concept of biopolitics, resulting from the fact that it is inhabited by a term that does not suit it - and that assumes risks even to distort its more remarkable features. In this semantic context the term zoé would become a problematic definition since it would refer to a conception of life absolutely natural (...) without any formal connotation what would be something unthinkable, even today, when the human body appears more challenged, and even literally crossed by the technique 42.



One can therefore say that in his work of deconstruction Esposito would have detected the unthought (or indeed the repressed) of biopolitics 43. The unthought, indeed, would orient it but would have been forgotten by those who highlight the concepts of homo sacer and the state of exception while constituent characteristics of biopolitics (Agamben) as per those that refer to a kind of vitalism in its biopolitics of the crowd (Negri). This unthought, detected by Esposito, and what the author calls the immunitary paradigm associated with the practices of protection against all kinds of risks, since the bacteriological contagion until the so-called terrorism 44.Such paradigm would be for him, a mechanism subjacent to biopolitics that would allow avoiding difficulties of its conceptual vagueness. Indeed, in the immunitas bios and nomos, life and politics, [are indeed] the two components of a single, inseparable, set that only makes sense from the relation between them. Thus, immunity would not only be the relation that connects life to power, but the power to preserve life, since contrarily to everything that involves the concept of biopolitics - understood as a result of the meeting which at one point occurs between the two component elements – of this point of view there is no power external to life, just as life never occurs outside the relations of power. For this reason, in this case, politics could only be seen as a possibility or the instrument to preserve life and immunization as a negative protection of life 45.


Contradictory effects of conceptual vagueness of biopolitics



The conceptual vagueness of biopolitics seems to allow us to use this concept to indicate phenomena as diverse as the public biopolicies for assistance, protection and welfare of democratic states on the one hand, and ways to biotanatopolítica, as was the case of Nazi biopolitics (or biocracy), on the other hand. The two situations that the term biopolitics seems to make indistinguishable, shall however, be analytically distinguishable and practically distinct.



In the first case, the term biopolitics emerges from an inter-relationship (or interface) between bios and polis and refers to welfare policies aimed at guaranteeing and strengthening the health of the population, thanks to devices or the prevention, control, management and intervention over individual human body and over the population, not necessarily identifying itself with a policy on the human species (although may be related to the immunitary paradigm). In the second case, what emerges is a policy where individuals and human populations are conceptually subsumed to the human species, to be (supposedly) protected from pathogens, i.e., instead a relationship (or interface) between bios and polis we have a subsumption (which in fact is an annexation) of polis to bios. In short, a policy subjected to biology and its laws.



But, as pointed out earlier, the bios and polis concepts have two possible logical relationships: 1) the interrelationship with no priority of a concept over the other (paratactic); 2) a subsumption of a term to the other (hypotactic). In turn, the second form of relationship between bios and polis has two possible variants: the subsumption of the bios to polis (which corresponds to the kind of relationship that existed for Aristotle) and the subsumption of polis to bios and, in turn, from bios to zoé, as probably still occurs in immunitary policies.



Despite these logical distinctions, duplicity of meaning (or amphibology) persists today, and is a source of conceptual confusion and practically of possible authoritarian slippage supposedly legitimized by science of life and by the immunitary-type protective policies. And that's exactly what leads to need to deconstruct biopolitics and, from this deconstruction, trying to apply the bioethics tools to detect morality (which includes immorality) of biopolitics and biopower. From this analysis it may then reconstruct forms of resistance on behalf of what cannot be subject to deconstruction: justice.



The form of resistance, represented by the bioethics should, however, comply with certain conditions. First, it should not be seen as substitute (or representative) of social control (which is indeed a guarantee of democracy), but as a tool of resistance to service of possible democratic control of the control, represented by the power exercised by biopower and biopolitics. Secondly, it should make accounts with the actual political consequences resulting from the moral imperative and social justice, what can be possible from the point of view of an intervention bioethics [understood as] the analysis of macro collective problems and conflict 46, in turn coupled to a bioethics of protection, understood not only as a descriptive and normative tool, but particularly as a protection against threats to 'bare life' and as 'minimum' moral indispensable for the existence of organized social life 47.



However, this position should consider the criticism, internal to the bioethics itself, according to which bioethics would be a discipline at risk, due to his alleged excessive academicism, focused on specific and irrelevant problems when compared with the great themes as social inequity, public sanitary policies, ecological crisis, which would be in fact being assumed or attached by biopolitics, and should, therefore, prevent its appropriation from other sides, away from specific agenda of bioethical thought 48. From Indeed, this risk condition of bioethics can be considered as a stimulus for power a bioethics think-resistant, which would include both an intervention bioethics as a bioethics of protection, but knowing that it only become possible if there is a deconstruction predicted category of biopolitics and biopower, as well as the essential criticism of unjustified annexation of bioethics to biopolitics.


Final considerations



What can we tentatively conclude from such deconstruction of the ambiguous and dense category of biopolitics? From this entry in the political field of notion of biological life? The answer is not simple if we consider that biopolitics is not based on a philosophical assumption [but] of concrete events 49, and should therefore do the accounts with facts which, in turn, should be weighted with undesconstructible justice – according to Aristotle – and the architectural virtue of social life.



The paradigmatic example of this process goes back to the Nazi biocracy which, in addition to resulting in a depoliticization of modern philosophy (as intended by Arendt), came to disarrange and reverse the political categories previously defined, historically founded on the separation zoé / bios and on the lexical priority of bios over zoé. That is, the entry on the scene of the notion of life - the dual bios and zoé dimension – crossed and transformed by the tools and devices of the biotechnoscientific paradigm not only mixed up the previous relationship, but also obscured the complexity of relationships between these categories, when applied to the phenomenon of life in its articulations with politics, technique, science, the interests involved, the production and consumption.



To Esposito, it would be precisely the force of biopolitical perspective that would arise from the ability of reading this tangle and this conflict, this displacement and this implication. Otherwise - he asks - what would happen when life, perceived as zoé and not as bios, that before the validity of the biopolitical paradigm was 'out' of the political sphere, breaks into such dimension, exploding its alleged autonomy and shifting the discourse of the modern political philosophy on an irreducible ground to the traditional terms - democracy, power, ideology? 50



The author warns, however, that one should know that biological life of individuals and population [settled down a long time ago] in the center of all significant political decisions, which forces us to a paradigm shift, since the model of medical healing has become not just the privileged object, but the very form of political life, i.e., a policy that only in life finds the only source of possible legitimacy 51.



Referring to the radical heterogeneity represented by Nazism and its biocracy he believes that from the biopolitical standpoint the twentieth century, and even the entire course of modernity - which he considers that staredt with Machiavelli - is not determined, decided, by the superficial and contradictory antithesis between totalitarianism and democracy, but for that, much deeper, because it belongs to the field of wildlife conservation, among history and nature, between historicization of nature and naturalization of history. Moreover, this dichotomy could not simply be reconducted to a symmetrical bipolarity, since that nature - understood in the biological sense, as Nazism has done - is not a anti-history, a philosophy or ideology opposite of the story but a non philosophy and a non ideology. Not a political philosophy, but a political biology, a policy of life and about life reversed into its opposite and, therefore, a producer of death 52.



All this has an important consequence which should not be forgotten, because when this bodily dimension becomes the real interlocutor - contemporarily subject and object – of the government, what is being discussed is, before all, the principle of equality that becomes inapplicable to something like the body, constitutively unlike any other criteria each time definable and modifiable. In this case, what would be being withdrawn was not only the principle of equality, but a whole series of distinctions or oppositions on which it is based [the] whole conception of modern politics from which it is generated: that means those between public and private, artifice and nature, law and theology. Thus, when the body replaces, or 'fills', the abstract subjectivity of the corporation, it becomes difficult, if not impossible, to distinguish what concerns the public sphere of what concerns the private one [but also] what belongs to the natural order and what may be subjected to the intervention of technique, with all the issues of ethical character [that] this choice implies 53.



To Esposito, the reason for this lack of distinction and the conflicts it inevitably entails and that human life is exactly that about what the public and the private, natural and artificial, politics and theology are intertwined by a bond that no majority decision will be able to undo, since the revolt of life of in the power devices marks the eclipse of democracy, at least of democracy as we have imagined it so far, which would mean to think in another kind democracy - compatible with the ongoing biopolitical change, henceforth irreversible 53. And the author ends his questioning leaving an open question: But where to look, how to think, which may mean, today, a biopolitics democracy or a democratic biopolitics - capable of influencing over the bodies, but for the sake of the bodies?54 It assumes this is something very difficult to tell on a determined manner, since at the moment it is something we can only glimpse, even though we know that to enable a line of thought in this direction we have to get rid of all old philosophies of history and all conceptual paradigms concepts that lead them 54.



And what would be the role of bioethics in all this? I believe it is possible to consider it as an alternative to biopolitics, contrary to what seems to suggest Esposito, who considers that in the very field of biopolitics the evidence of a democratic biopolitics or a democracy biopolitics would be found, capable of stimulating policies in favor of the bodies and not about them. However, this suggestion may question: first if a democratic biopolitics and a biopolitical democracy were indeed the same thing or if the second would not have in itself the conditions to become inevitably biocracy a supposedly legitimated by a biomedical or sanitary model but in fact morally and politically objectionable; secondly, if the entry of life as object of political concern and the consequent filling up the abstract subjectivity of traditional legal personality may involve abuses against the fundamental rights, morally and politically questionable, too.



Thus, based on the undesconstructible principle of justice, appointed by Derrida, bioethics can, in principle, mediate regulatory issues involved by biopolitics and biopower, that is, the relationships established between bios and zoé, between them and the polis and between them and techne. But what would be the legitimacy of bioethics to do this? I think it is the resistance to the biopolitics reduction the political (in fact a zoopolitcs with the glaring exception of the bios, if we think in Nazi biocracy). I believe that such resistance can be realized from the own tools for this field, respecting the specifics of each knowledge involved to establish dialogue with the various forms of knowledge and power involved. Or, perhaps, resistance occurs only by profanation 55 of the so-called natural 'inevitable' established between biology and politics by the biopolitical paradigm. But the sense of profanation should be understood in this case as a displacement, without abolishing what one intends to displace. A displacement of power devices that would allow return to common use spaces that [power] had confiscated. And that is what deconstruction, along with the bioethics of protection and bioethics intervention, seems to jointly perform in polis

.


Resumo A bioética como forma de resistência à biopolítica e ao biopoder

O trabalho intenta desconstruir os conceitos de biopolítica e biopoder e objetiva criar condições para uma atuação correta da bioética, entendida tanto como ferramenta analítica e normativa da moralidade da biopolítica e do biopoder quanto como aplicação prática sob a forma de resistência e dissidência democrática com relação aos efeitos moralmente questionáveis, resultantes das práticas biopolíticas e dos usos inadequados de tais conceitos para realizá-las. Seu pressuposto é o de que os conceitos de biopolítica e biopoder são utilizados, na maioria das vezes, de forma inconsistente ou como palavras passe-partout, o que afeta seu poder de inteligibilidade para entender as profundas transformações da sociedade contemporânea, inclusive com relação às percepções de si enquanto ‘sistema vivo’. A desconstrução constitui, portanto, uma operação prévia necessária devido à subsunção da ética à política, supostamente legitimada pela referência comum à “vida”, indicada pela palavra grega bíos, a qual, no entanto, se revela inextricavelmente vinculada a zoé, quando não subsumida a esta. Por fim, o trabalho discute as propostas de democracia biopolítica e de biopolítica democrática, mostrando a necessidade de um controle bioético da biopolítica.



Palavras-chave: Bioética. Biopolítica. Controle. Justiça. Imunidade.


Resumen La bioética como forma de resistencia a la biopolítica y al biopoder

El trabajo intenta desconstruir los conceptos de biopolítica y biopoder y objetiva crear condiciones para una actuación correcta de la bioética, entendida tanto como herramienta analítica y normativa de la moralidad de la biopolítica y del biopoder como aplicación práctica bajo la forma de resistencia y disidencia democrática con relación a los efectos moralmente cuestionables, resultantes de las prácticas biopolíticas y de los usos inadecuados de tales conceptos para realizarlas. Su presupuesto es el de que los conceptos de biopolítica y biopoder son utilizados, la mayoría de las veces, de forma inconsistente o como palabras passe-partout, lo que afecta a su poder de inteligibilidad para entender las profundas transformaciones de la sociedad contemporánea, inclusive con relación a las percepciones de sí en tanto ‘sistema vivo’. La desconstrucción constituye, por tanto, una operación previa necesaria debido a la subsunción de la ética a la política, supuestamente legitimada por la referencia común a la “vida”, indicada por la palabra griega bíos, la cual, no obstante, se revela inextricablemente vinculada a zoé, cuando no subsumida a ésta. Por fin, el trabajo discute las propuestas de democracia biopolítica y de biopolítica democrática, mostrando la necesidad de un control bioético de a biopolítica.



Palabras-clave: Bioética. Biopolítica. Control. Justicia. Impunidad.




References

1. Derrida J. Positions. Paris: Minuit; 1972. p.15.

2. Kottow M. Ética de protección: una propuesta de protección bioética. Bogotá:

Universidad Nacional de Colombia; 2007.

3. Derrida J. Força de lei. São Paulo: Martins Fontes; 2007. p. 27.

4. Foucault M. Histoire de la sexualité 1: la volonté de savoir. Paris: Gallimard; 1976. p. 175-211.

5. Agamben G. Homo sacer: o poder soberano e a vida nua I. Belo Horizonte: Ed. UFMG; 2002a.

6. Esposito R. Bios: biopolítica e filosofia. Lisboa: Ediçoes 70; 2010a.

7. Kottow M. Bioética: una disciplina en riesgo. Revista Redbioética/Unesco 2010;1(1):158-72. p.160.

8. Houaiss A, Villar MS. Dicionário Houaiss da língua portuguesa. Rio de Janeiro:

Objetiva; 2001. Biopolítica; p. 457.

9. Esposito R. Op.cit.; 2010. p. 30.

10. Arendt H. A condiçao humana. 5a ed. Rio de Janeiro: Forense Universitária; 1991. p.108-9.

11. Caponi S, Verdi M, Brzozowski FS, Hellmann F, organizadores. Medicalizaçao da vida: ética, saúde pública e indústria farmacêutica. Palhoça: Ed. Unisul; 2010. Revista Bioética 2010; 18(3): 519 – 35 534

12. Schramm FR. O uso problemático do conceito ‘vida’ em bioética e suas interfaces com a práxis biopolítica e os dispositivos de biopoder. Rev Bioét 2009a.;17(3):377-89.

13. Agamben G. Op. cit; 2002a. p. 9, 74, 190.

14. __________. Op. cit.; 2002a. p. 12.

15. Schramm Fr. Op. cit; 2009a:384.

16. Hardt M, Negri A. Impero: il nuovo ordine della globalizzazione. Milano: Rizzoli; 2002.

17. Skornicki A. Le biopouvoir: détournement des puissances vitales ou invention de la vie? L´economie politique, le pain et le peuple au XVIIIe siecle. Labyrinthe 2005;22(3):56-65. p. 56-7.

18. Ranciere J. Biopolitique ou politique? Multitudes [internet] 2000 Mar [cited 5 Set 2010];1. Available: http://multitudes.samizdat.net/article.php3?id_article = 210.

19. Ratzel F. Der Lebensraum: eine biogeograpische studie. In: Festgaben fur Albert Schäffle AAVV. Darmstadt: Wissenchaftliche Buchgesellschaft; 1901. p. 103-89.

20. Von Uexküll J. Staatsbiologie: anatomie, phisiologie, pathologie des staates. Berlin: Gebruder Paetel Verlag; 1920.

21. Harris GW. Bio-politics. The New Age [internet]. 1911 Dec [cited 5 Set. 2010];28:197. Available:http:/foucaultblog.wordpress.com/2009/03/15/first-use-of-biopolitics.

22. Kjellén R. Grundriss zu einem system der politik. Paris: Gallimard; 1920. p. 818.

23. Roberts M. Bio-politics: an essay on the phisiology, pathology and politics of social and somatic organisms. London: Dent; 1938.

24. Somit A. Biopolitics. In: Somit, editor. Biology and politics: recent explorations. The Hague: Mouton; 1976.

25. Vlavianos-Arvantis A, Oleskin AV. Biopolitics: the bio-environment, bio-syllabus. Athens: Biopolitics International Organization; 1992.

26. Starobinski A. Essai d´interprétation de l´histoire de l´humanité et des civilisations. Geneve: Imprimerie des Arts; 1960. p. 7.

27. Morin E. Introduction a une politique de l´homme. Paris: Seuil; 1969. p. 12.

28. Somit A, Peterson SA. Biopolitics in the Year 2000. In: Peterson SA, Somit A, editors. Evolutionary approaches in the behavioral sciences: toward a better understanding of human nature. Amsterdam: Elsevier; 2001.p. 181.

29. Foucault M. Palestra na Universidade do Rio de Janeiro (Uerj), 1974. Apud Esposito R. Op. cit.; 2010.

30. _________. Dits et écrits III. Paris: Gallimard; 1994. p. 818.

31. _________. Il faut défendre la sociéte. Paris: Seuil/Gallimard; 1997. p. 213-6.

32. Esposito R. Op. cit.; 2010; p. 29.

33. Foucault M. Op. cit.; 1976. p. 127.

34. _________. Op. cit.; 1976. p. 188.

35. Agamben G. L´ouvert. De l´homme et de l’ animal. Paris: Rivages; 2002b. p. 30-1. A bioética como forma de resistência a biopolítica e ao biopoder 535 36. _________. Op. cit.; 2002a. p. 12.

37. _________. Op. cit.; 2002a. p.16-7.

38. _________. Op. cit.; 2002a. p.14.

39. Esposito R. Op. cit.; 2010. p. 37.

40. _________. Op. cit.; 2010. p. 38.

41. _________. Op. cit.; 2010. p. 43-4.

42. _________. Op. cit.; 2010. p. 31.

43. Campbell T. Politica, immunita, vita: il pensiero di Roberto Esposito nel dibattito filosófico conteporaneo. In: Esposito R. Termini della politica: comunita, immunita, biopolitica. Milano: Mimesis; 2008. p. 9-61, p. 10.

44. Esposito R. Immunitas: protezione e negazione della vita. Torino: Einaudi; 2002.

45. _________. Op. cit.; 2010. p. 74.

46. Garrafa V, Porto D. Bioética de intervención. In: Tealdi JC, director. Diccionario latinoamericano de bioética. Bogotá: Unesco/Universidad Nacional de Colômbia; 2008. p. 161.

47. Schramm FR. A moralidade da biotecnociência: a bioética da proteçao pode dar conta do impacto real e potencial das biotecnologias sobre a vida e/ou a qualidade de vida das pessoas humanas? In: Schramm FR, Braz M, Palácios M, Rego S, organizadores. Bioética, riscos e proteção. 2a ed. Rio de Janeiro: Ed. UFRJ/Ed. Fiocruz; 2009b. p. 24-5.

48. Kottow M. Bioética: una disciplina en riesgo. Revista Redbioética/Unesco 2010;1(1):158.

49. Esposito R. Termini della politica: comunita, immunita, biopolitica. Milano:

Mimesis; 2008.p. 175.

50. _________. Op. cit.; 2008. p. 176. 51. _________. Op. cit.; 2008. p. 179. 52. _________. Op. cit.; 2008. p. 177. 53. _________. Op. cit.; 2008. p. 180.

54. _________. Op. cit.; 2008. p. 181.

55. Agamben G. Profanations. Paris: Payot & Rivages; 2005. p. 97.



Received: 5.29.2010 Approved:11.8.2010 Final approval: 11.10.2010


Contact



Fermin Roland Schramm - roland@ensp.fiocruz.br



Av. Augusto Severo 132/1201, Glória CEP 20021-040. Rio de Janeiro/RJ, Brazil.

EARTH MATTERS: THOMAS BERRY, ECOJUSTICE

 EARTH MATTERS: THOMAS BERRY, THE PACIFISM OF RELIGIOUS

COSMOLOGY AND THE NEED FOR ECOJUSTICE

Christopher Hrynkow and Dennis O'Hara

Abstract

This article begins by unfolding Thomas Berry's notion of Pax Gala, using the concept as a key to unlock cogent aspects of his geobiological thought. Then, suggesting an addition to John Howard Yoder's typologies, the authors argue that Berry's vision of the peace of the Earth can be categorized as a "the pacifism of religious cosmology?' Berry's cosmology of peace is then grounded with reference to concrete issues of ecojustice, with a particular focus on the interrelated concepts of "biocide" and "geocide." The article ends by highlighting the need for reinvention of the human, which emerges from the moral imperatives associated with the pacifism of religious cosmology.

"In the end, I suspect it will all come down to a decision of ethics—how we value the natural worlds in which we evolved and now, increasingly, how we regard our status as individuals?"

-E.O. Wilson (1999, 16).

"Every particular being has the universe for context. To challenge this principle by try­ing to establish humans as self-referent and other beings as human referent in their pri­mary value subverts the most basic principle of the universe. Once we accept that we exist as an integral member of this larger community of existence, we can begin to act in a more appropriate human way."

-Thomas Berry (2009, 138).

4 PEACE AND JUSTICE STUDIES

Thomas Berry's Peace of the Earth and a Geological View of Violence

In the closing chapter of The Dream of the Earth, North American historian of world religions and cultures Thomas Berry (1914-2009) lays out his vision for a cosmology of peace. Reflecting the principles of his Earth-centered focus, he argues for a peace beyond conceptions like Pax Romana or Pax Humana towards "Pax Gaia." Berry's chosen term signifies "the Peace of Earth [and is derived] from the ancient mythic name for the planet" (1990, 220). Berry identifies four characteristics of Pax Gaia, which rest on a recognition of: (1) the indivisibility of the Earth; (2) the dynamic nature of the Peace of the Earth; (3) a progressive dependence of human decision-making; and (4) the necessity of hopefulness (1990, 220-221). A more detailed exposition of each of these characteristics of Pax Gala will demonstrate how, from Berry's perspective, "Earth matters" if one desires a substantive peace and justice.

First, Berry identifies the need to recognize that "the earth is a single community composed of all its geological, biological and human components" (1990, 220). Earth and its inhabitants have emerged from a continuous evolutionary process that began with the birth of the universe 13.7 billion years ago. Following on this understanding, Berry declares "that the universe is a communion of subjects, not a collection of objects," since every player who has emerged within this epic of evolution has contributed in some way to the furtherance of this story (1999, 82). Within a reality of Pax Gala, every member of Earth's community, whether human or other, belongs and cannot be discounted. Berry's perspective echoes Irving Goldman's description of "consubstantiality" that typifies the unity of organic life in the Kwakiutl woridview (1975, 201). Building on the work of pioneering anthropologist Franz Boas, Goldman reports that the Kwakiutl people of north-eastern Vancouver Island, "as genuine naturalists. . . accept the parity and the indestructible uniqueness of all other members of the common universe. Kwakiutl religion represents the concern of the people to occupy their own proper place within the total system of life, and to act responsibly within it" (1975, 201).

In line with this principle of consubstantiality, Berry argues that the universe forms a single, integral community in which all Earth's inhabitants are interde­pendent subjects. As such, the level of analysis for decision-making becomes the entire planet (1999, 4). Whereas the realist school of international relations sees the nation-state as the most significant unit in world politics (Morgenthau 1978, 4-15), Berry holds up the entire Earth community as the referential unit. On this bio-global level, issues that negatively affect ecosystem health in one area of the

EARTH MATTERS 5

planet are seen as ultimately problematic for all life! Here, Berry is naming the crisis of relationship that occurs when the forces of greed and patriarchy damage human-Earth relationships (1990, 157). As such, Berry argues that it is not a United Nations that we need to carry us through the current planetary crisis, but rather, a "United Species" (1990, 161). Furthermore, Berry reminds us that the nations themselves are dependent on the Earth; without a viable planet, the nations would cease to exist. Indeed, because they have arisen on this Earth within the evolutionary processes of its geobiological history, Berry asserts that the nations also have a responsibility to allow for the continuance of the active functioning of diverse biosystems.

To save the earth is a necessity for every nation. No part of the earth in its essential func­tioning can be the exclusive possession or concern of any nation. The air cannot be nationalized or privatized; it must circulate everywhere on the planet to fulfill its life giving function anywhere on the planet. It must be available for the nonhuman as well as for the human lifeforms if it is to sustain life. So it is with the waters on the earth. They must circulate throughout the planet if they are to benefit any of the lifeforms on the planet (1990, 220).'

Secondly, Pax Gaia is "not some fixed condition, but a creative process activated by polarity tension requiring a high level of endurance" (1990, 220). Pax Gaia does not promote a static vision of peace. Rather, it recognizes that, just as a creative evolutionary disequilibrium has prompted Earth's transfor­mations to new levels of greater complexity and organization, any life-giving peace will necessarily emerge out of a similar creative tension (Berry 1999, 52). Sometimes the nature of this creative tension or conflict can be quite violent, such as the eruption of a volcano or the fury of a forest fire. Nonetheless, as Berry notes,

The Earth has found its way into being amid an amazing sequence of both destructive and creative experiences. A long sequence of cataclysmic events has shaped the conti­nents and the various forms of life have themselves engaged in a continuing struggle for survival (1999, 167).

To grasp why Berry does not advocate static tranquility—a state that he describes as "bovine placidity"—in order to achieve peace, and why he favours creative tension in order to realize a "creative resolution of our present antagonisms' it is necessary to understand his perspective on the role of violence in the "long arc" of geobiological history (1999, 217-219). According to Berry, the creative conflict associated with natural antagonisms is beneficial

6 PEACE AND JUSTICE STUDIES

since it is within such a context that geobiological history evolves to greater levels of complexity and diversity. For example,

Many of the inventions of the natural world arose out of beings meeting the constraints of the universe with creative responses. Only by dealing with the difficulty does the creativ­ity come forth. The violence associated with the hawk starving to death or the vole being consumed are intrinsically tied to the creativity of each (Swimme and Berry 1992, 56).

Indeed, evolutionary history has many moments of supreme creativity fostered in a violent disruption of the status quo. Recognizing some of these innovative moments in planetary history, without embracing a methodology that would justify deliberate and oppressive (human) violence, is one of the crucial challenges of telling the universe story that Berry considers so central to his biocratic project. In telling that story, Berry and his colleague, mathematical cosmologist Brian Swimme, demonstrate how such moments of supreme creativity have emerged out of violent antagonisms at various moments in the epic of evolution. These instances of creative conflict have undeniably shaped both where the present Earth community has come from and where the universe is headed.

For example, the Pauli exclusion principle declares that two particles cannot occupy the same quantum state at the same time. In a universe comprised of distinct entities and not "an infinitely extended homogenous smudge" (Berry 1990, 106), these diverse entities will resist attempts to remove them from their existence, thereby maintaining both their unique identity, which has emerged through the creativity of cosmogenesis, as well as their creative contributions to that same continuing cosmogenesis. In this manner, the law of nature "in protecting the viability of the elementary particle, works to ensure the particle of its place, of its role in the unfolding story" (Swimme and Berry1992, 52). Through such means, these elementary particles emerge as the nexus for all creative antagonism in the universe.

Creativity, however, takes energy. In opposition to the notion of limitless growth, this cosmological perspective recognizes that an energy payment is necessary for any change of state (Swimme and Berry1992, 52). What we experience as beauty, good, and evil cannot come into being without energy expenditures. We humans (and indeed everything that exists) need a certain amount of energy in order to be molded into intelligible forms. How we seek and tap into that energy depends upon our inner nature—the dolphin needs to eat the fish; the female mosquito needs to find mammalian blood. Herein lays the origin of all violence in the universe: because energy is finite, conflict will necessarily

EARTH MATTERS 7

occur as every entity seeks the energy it requires to fuel its existence. This point is not meant to assert that life is a necessarily a zero-sum game but, rather, that the amount of energy in the cosmological system is finite, which in turn has important implications for conflict.

For instance, invoking Thomist and Marxist images, consider what happens when an acorn asserts its species-specific being and does its best to become an oak tree. Its creativity lies in getting itself implanted in the soil and reaching up and out with its shoots and young branches as well as deep and out with its roots. While doing so, the acorn limits the possibilities for other life around it. Even as it realizes its full potential, in responding creatively to its context, the acorn is in conflict with life forms seeking the same energy sources. Variations on this story are replicated over and over again in geobiological history. Creativity and conflict thus come to be viewed as inseparable from the universe story. It is from working within this very framework of creative antagonisms that the present diverse life community emerged.

Without such creative tension, the universe would have remained a single primal point, static and fixed. The almost incomprehensible violence of the "big bang" set everything in motion. Now that humans have begun to grasp the implication of an evolving universe, our retrospective assessment notes that a creatively turbulent cosmogenesis has made us who we are. However, according to Berry and Swimme, we are now forming pathological responses to the very dynamic processes that have created and sustained us. When humanity's awareness of the struggle and violence inherent in creation sparked feelings of terror, we did not limit our response to mere self-preservation. Forgetting our status as a member of the larger geobiological community, we used our increasing technological skills to manufacture a Saccharin world that would be as free as possible of the risks, dangers, and wants associated with life in the Earth community; we sought to control and tame nature in unsustainable ways (Swimme and Berry 1992, 56). In a twist of irony, human endeavors to avoid terror too often increased tenor, especially when the resultant efforts spurred on the current Western war against the rest of the natural world. Swimme and Berry further assert that it is the pathological woridview that all insecurity could be eliminated which has "eventuated racism, militarism, sexism and anthropocentrism., dysfunctional efforts of the human species to deal with what it regarded as the unacceptable aspects of the universe" (1992, 56). This point is not meant to assert that in place of our determined efforts to shield ourselves from life's struggles and violence we should seek out violence and pain for their own sake, since that too would

8 PEACE AND JUSTICE STUDIES

represent a similarly pathological response as maladaptive as the current mass effort to deny the costs and demands of existence.

According to Swimme and Berry's analysis, in contrast to both these forms of human pathology stands the life-giving tension of the natural world. For instance, reflect on the wonder-inspiring adaptation of cyano-bacterium to the concentration of oxygen on this planet, even as previous life forms were bursting into flames due to that element's very presence (Swimme and Berry 1992,  94­98). Or ponder the feat of ingenuity when eukaryotes invented meiotic sex and the Earth's diversity multiplied as two genetically different beings were able to "unite and fashion out of their genetic endowment a radically new being" (Swimme and Berry1992, 9). Or consider the manner in which a springbok grazes with its ears aloft, ready to dart off (when it perceives danger) in a stunning and speedy pattern that South Africa's very best rugby players can only dream of emulating.' When the option of total control over all the variables in life does not exist, a fear of death and violence can spawn remarkable innovation. Today, we can bear witness to a contextually significant alternative to disembodied escapism, one that is present in the powerful innovative tendencies that accompany the creative antagonisms all around us in the larger life community.

Given that the violence associated with natural rhythms can foster such life-enriching creativity, the main issue of the current Earth crisis is brought more clearly into view. The deep moral issue at hand becomes evident when we consider the possibility that we humans, in spite of our ability to image the future and our capacity for self-reflective consciousness, may be instrumental in shutting down the life-sustaining functions of this planet and causing ecological collapse. Thus, in addition to its acknowledgment of the indivisibility of the Earth and its identification of the dynamic nature of the Peace of the Earth, Pax Gala, thirdly, looks to the responsibility of humanity for both the institution and transformation of the ecological crisis. This recognizes the unique role of human agency in Earth history. Homo sapiens have now arrived at the point where we, a single species, are in a position to change the chemical and biological makeup of the world on a global scale (Wilson 1994, 5). No other species has ever had this ability. Currently, human violence directed towards the natural world is effecting change on a level that has not been witnessed since the constitutive period of planetary history (Berry 1990, 219).

In terms of the geobiological story, the present danger marks the first time that there has been "a conscious intrusion on this scale into the natural rhythms of Earth processes" (Berry 1999, 167). Yet, because humans have brought about

EARTH MATTERS 9

this crisis we (at least for now) still have the chance to avoid ecological collapse. Today, we can witness how this opportunity for creativity is arrived at when we use our very human ability to reason and reflect on the consequences of our way of being for the entire life community. Indeed, from a geobiological perspective, humans are the one member of the universe community known to fully possess the ability for self-reflective consciousness. Applied within the ecosphere, this ability allows us to see that we are members of the global life community and thus our fate is tied together with the fate of the rest of the natural world.

The pioneering conservationist Aldo Leopold (1887-1948) set the concomitant challenge more than a half-century ago. When considering possible responses to the ecological crisis, Leopold suggested that "a special nobility inherent in the human race—a special cosmic value, distinctive from and superior to all other life" (1997, 642) is only available to humans. As such, we can choose to be remembered either as

a society respectful of its own and all other life, capable of inhabiting the earth without defiling it or [as] a society like that of John Burroughs' potato bug, which exterminated the potato, and thereby exterminated itself. As one or the other, shall we be judged in 'the derisive silence of history' (Leopold 1997, 642).

Fourthly, in line with the positive option in Leopold's thought, Berry reminds us that Pax Gaia is representative of a deep hope (1990, 221). Such optimism is centered on the way geobiological history bears witness to the survival of the planet through previous violent crisis moments. For Berry, it is essential that we have hope. By not surrendering to despair, the vision of Pax Gaia and our ability to grasp the consequences of our actions in an integral manner may allow us to demonstrate our special cosmic value. In this manner, integral human knowing allows us to use our human agency to avoid a destructively violent rupture in Earth processes. Additionally, it provides for the continuance of homo sapiens as a species located within (and not somehow trying to establish itself as apart from) a diverse community of life. Otherwise, we risk a drift into a type of pathological disconnect from the universe that nurtures and sustains us. To avoid this danger, hope must be "grounded" in the sense that it serves to reconnect us with the Earth community.

Misappropriated hope is indeed a feature of our recent past. To counteract such misdirection, Berry's hope for a sustainable future is centered on multiple possibilities for the integration of a new story, informed by the principle that Earth matters and we are essentially located within the aforementioned communion of subjects. As Berry writes in partnership with Swimme, a

10 PEACE AND JUSTICE STUDIES

reconfiguration of our understanding of who or what constitutes the ethical community is increasingly necessary:

Without entrancement within this new context of existence it is unlikely that the human community will have the psychic energy needed for the renewal of the Earth. This entrancement comes from the immediate communion of the human with the natural world, a capacity to appreciate the ultimate subjectivity and spontaneities within every form of natural being (1992, 268).

To realize such entrancement, an integration of the "new story" into our collective being is needed. At the very least, our responsibility to a lively future mandates the presence of something akin to the "new story" in our human cultures. Our ability to be self-creating allows for this possible future to be incarnated in a vital manner. It is well within the human potential to foster a future that is respectful and nourishing towards all life forms. Intervention in ecological violence on this level is at once simple and challenging: we need only to grasp the possibility of a future of mutually enhancing human-Earth community relationships and act to make it a reality. Yet, such a possible world seems too often to be beyond our grasp. In this regard Berry advocates a movement "beyond democracy to biocracy" (Berry 1990, xiii). In such a biocratic movement, the larger life community is factored into our human decision-making processes. Within this expanded context, human affairs gain their meaning through intercom-munion (Berry 1990, 136). When a biocratic reality has been fully realized, the value of all professions, occupations and activities will be determined by precisely to what degree they enhance and contribute to the larger life community. This formulation rings true, in Berry's estimation, because it is only when we take our cues "from the very structure and functioning of the universe [that] we can have confidence in the future that awaits the human venture" (Berry 1990, 137). In light of the magnitude of these proposed changes to human-Earth relationships, Pax Gaia's image of the moral community will also have important implications for the way we think about pacifism.

The Pacifism of Religious Cosmology—

Adding a New Variety to Yoder's Typologies

In his monograph., Nevertheless, Mennonite theological ethicist and former Notre Dame Professor John Howard Yoder (1927-1997) identifies and then comments on over twenty-five varieties of religious pacifism. Because it grows out of Berry's reflections on his Roman Catholic identity, Christian faith and his interactions with both Eastern religions and Indigenous spiritualities, it is not

EARTH MATTERS 11

surprising that Pax Gala displays certain characteristics identified in Yoder's typologies. For instance, in so much as Pax Gala holds a vision of a global community, it corresponds with aspects of what Yoder labels "the pacifism of Christian cosmopolitanism" Yoder, 2002, 19). Yet, on the whole, Yoder's criteria fail to adequately capture Berry's more biocentric form of religious pacifism since Yoder deals with relational categories that are mostly inter-human and transcendent (in the other worldly sense). Thus, Yoder's project does not take into account the mediating presence of the cosmos and the Earth community in these social and divine relationships. Therefore, in this contextual sense, it is appropriate to conclude that Berry's vision of Pax Gaia exposes the need to add another category to Yoder's typologies, namely a cosmological one. This conclusion is based on Yoder's recognition of categories like "the pacifism of honest study of cases" under which he included the exercise of Roman Catholic just war "pacifism" because such approaches are, according to Yoder's analysis, geared towards violence limitation. For instance, Yoder points out how the many thinkers employing the just war tradition have concluded, based on the realities of the "disproportionate destructiveness of uncontrolled high-tech weapons" (1992, 24), that mass military violence between two international actors is no longer morally tenable according to established ethical criteria. Further, contra the misconception that just war invokes a general support of war, he adds that as one of its central organizing principles a just war perspective "constitutes a denial that war can ever be generally justified" (Yoder, 1992, 25 [emphasis in the original]).

The very existence of such categories as the "pacifism of the honest study of cases" offers a response to an objection that Pax Gaia's notion of "creative antagonism" disqualifies the geobiological perspective from being authentically characterized as a form of pacifism in light of Yoder's typologies of religious peacebuilding. Additionally, as David Cortright (2008) argues, moving beyond naiveté, recovering a sense of "pacifism" as not solely a moral stance, and embracing a definition of the term that encompasses all those working on the problems of how to prevent war and build peace, can help overcome the utopianism associated with contemporary peace movements. In this light, the most effective excises of pacifism might well be contextual, in the sense of being grounded in the reality of the human and Earth communities.

Building on Yoder's work in this regard, it follows that a cosmology of religious pacifism can be described as centered on the idea that right relationship with the transcendent (i.e., Berry's "numinous presence") and among humans includes an aspect of right relationship with the natural world. From the human

12 PEACE AND JUSTICE STUDIES

perspective, our embodiment leads us towards seeing the value of this world, not only in terms of a testing ground for the afterlife, but as morally worthy in and of itself. This type of religious pacifism is not content with a single or static vision of conflict which pits peace and violence as opposites. Rather, it hopes to establish diverse ways of existing in life-giving creative tension amongst the transcendent, humanity, and the rest of the natural world.

This formulation of Pax Gaia challenges the norms of an absolute moral vision of peace as represented by the Quaker, Edward Hick's, famous series of paintings, The Peaceable Kingdom. In some sixty versions of The Peaceable Kingdom, the accord among the white settlers, William Penn and the Lenape (Delaware) people in the background is accompanied by the absence of any "red tooth and claw" as children, the lion and the lamb (amongst other representatives of the larger life community) literally lie down together in the foreground.' By rejecting such a vision of placidity, a perspective inspired by Berry's work is well-poised to discern the "spirals of violence" that oppress marginalized humans through poverty, inequity, injustice and militarism (Câmara 1971, 77) as well as other forces, such as patriarchy. In this sense, Berry's perspective returns to the essential commitments that lie at the heart of "the mission" of many nonviolent activists who struggle for social and political equity. The call by Pax Gaia for a comprehensive and profound reinvention of human structures and behaviors seeks a socially just peace. This confluence between many nonviolent activists and Pax Gaia can be found in the type of reflection encouraged by various Psalms, capturing what we might term the "unsustainability of repression." For instance, commenting on Jacqueline Osherow's poetic re-imaging of Psalm 37 at Auschwitz, Ellen Davies offers a poignant illustration of the type of hope, one with a deep ethical dimension, which emerges when one becomes cognizant of the unsustainable qualities of repressive systems:

In such a situation, hope cannot mean naive expectation of personal prosperity, nor even perhaps one's own survival. Rather, it means looking to the inevitable collapse of the system, with the visionary realism that often emerges amongst the oppressed, knowing that on the other side of destruction there may be within a radically different kind of social and economic system, one that might truly be called community (2009, 117).

Such powerful exegesis, a form that invokes longing for ethical interconnec-tivity, can serve to liberate all creation as emancipatory concerns for humans extend to the structural injustices that plague both human society and the rest of the natural world. Through such means, hope becomes centered not so much on the destruction of a repressive system, as Davies would shade it, but rather hope

EARTH MATTERS 13

begins to seek a positive transformation of relationships previously charac­terized by destructive conflict and oppression. This transformation is intimately connected to what is identified in this section as the pacifism of religious cosmology. Similar visions have been rhetorically extolled at the highest levels of social teaching in the Roman Catholic Church. For instance, in 1990, John Paul II's "World Peace Day" message highlighted the ecological crisis as a common responsibility for all humanity and situated "peace with God the creator [in] peace with all of creation" (#1). War, that more traditional "peace issue," is also classified in that same address as an environmental issue and as a waste of precious resources:

Today, any form of war on a global scale would lead to incalculable ecological damage. But even local or regional wars, however limited, not only destroy human life and social structures but also damage the land, ruining crops and vegetation as well as poisoning soil and water. The survivors of war are forced to begin a new life in very difficult envi­ronmental conditions, which in turn create situations of extreme social unrest, with fur­ther negative consequences for the environment (John Paul 111990, #13).

Given present lived realities, such as ecological degradation, the loss of biodiversity and the presence of landmines left over from conflicts, these words of John Paul II remain particularly poignant. They remind us of the value of cosmological pacifism for all members of the natural world, and they foreshadow the call of the United Nations each year, since 2001, to recognize November 6 as the "International Day for Preventing the Exploitation of the Environment in War and Armed Conflict."6

Recognizing this substantive value of cosmological pacifism, we consider a geobiological perspective to be helpful for addressing issues of structural violence and inequity in order to move toward a more substantively peaceful and just world. If embraced holistically, such deep green thought has the potential to correct injustice and effect healing relationships on many levels because it is representative of a dynamic life-enriching force. Nevertheless, incarnating this view in the lived reality of humans, when so much injustice, inequity and ecological degradation are present all around us, remains a pressing and complex contextual challenge.

Any movement toward such a dynamic peace would represent a contextually cogent application of the principles of Pax Gala. However, we must note a further characteristic of the type of relational social change that Berry is recommending. Berry is not engaged in prophetic or technological prediction, which, as highlighted by Karl Popper, can lead to a social-scientific

14 PEACE AND JUSTICE STUDIES

methodology for social change based on "engineering" (2007, 38). In contrast, Berry's approach to social change is based much more upon expanding ethical categories than social-scientific methodology. Indeed, because they have not corresponded to an integral worldview, he explicitly decries both prophetic and technological traditions of social change in his work. In their place, Berry suggests that what is needed to effectively address the current ecological and social crises is not a prophetic reply (the mode in which some have misinter­preted his work) but rather a shamanic response (1996a). Departing from normative anthropological renderings of the shaman (see Lessa and Vogt 1997, 301-302), Berry prefers the shamanic personality over the prophetic voice in our contemporary context because of the way the former

journeys into the far regions of the cosmic mystery and brings back the vision and power needed by the human community at the most elementary level. This shamanic person­ality speaks and best understands the language of the various creatures of the earth.... This shamanic insight is especially important just now when history is being made not primarily within nations or between nations, but between humans and the earth, with all its living creatures. In this context all our professions and institutions must be judged primarily by the extent to which they foster this mutually enhancing human-earth rela­tionship (Berry 1990, 211-212).

In this manner, Berry is asserting that the spirituality of the shaman represents "what is going forward" (Lonergan 1990, 189) for the human project. Berry further argues that, in the contemporary world: "Our spiritual guidance must now come from those who combine shamanic and scientific sensibilities" (1996a).

Returning to the dangers that Popper associates with the social-scientific predictive methodology leading to social engineering (2007, 38), let us consider Berry's recommendations for the contemporary context. Berry writes that:

We need to move from a spirituality of alienation from the natural world to a spiritual­ity of intimacy with the natural world, from a spirituality of the divine as revealed in the written scriptures to a spirituality of the divine as revealed in the visible world about us, from a spirituality concerned with justice only for humans to a spirituality ofjustice for the devastated Earth community, from the spirituality of the prophet to the spirituality of the shaman (2009b).

With the emancipatory and justice-based ethical implications of this integral spirituality of the shaman in mind, we shall now move toward applying Berry's vision to concrete issues of substantive peace and justice in this world. In so doing, we will demonstrate how cosmological pacifism, if embraced holistically,

EARTH MATTERS 15

has the potential to heal and prevent even the most heinous acts of violence. The ecofeminist liberation theologian Heather Eaton adds that the response to the current global climate crisis needs to work more out of insight and less from a mere data-based perspective (2007b). In this spirit, we shall now ground Thomas Berry's thought with a focus on the urgent need for ecological justice.

The Need for Ecojustice:

An Appropriate Role for Humans in the Earth Community

Although our jurisprudence systems are relatively well equipped to deal with categories such as "suicide," "homicide," and even "genocide," we have no effective ethical or legal systems to deal with "biocide," the destruction of Earth's life systems,' or "geocide," the destruction of Earth's systems and therefore of the planet itself (See Berry 1996b). In light of the pacifism of religious cosmology, this is a major oversight requiring our attention. Similarly, in the West, we have fashioned ethical principles to guide human behavior. However, at their best, these systems mainly focus on conduct that will promote flourishing among humans within a human community. Such an anthropocentric focus on human well-being and personal behavior has detrimentally affected the well-being of the planet on which we depend for our survival. When the accompanying malaise of undervaluing the Earth's well-being is added to this anthropocentric mix, there emerge many ethical implications to the interrelated problems of biocide and genocide. To highlight some of the moral content of these problems and to ground our more theoretical reflections presented above, we will focus on two timely issues of ecojustice: species loss and climate justice.

Connecting these problems, Oberlin College Environmental Studies and Politics Professor David On posits that the whole Earth faces the prospect of ecological collapse, which would severely reduce biodiversity. He further asserts that this outcome has occurred because of human over-consumption and exploitation of the planet. On writes:

If today is a typical day on planet earth, we will lose 166 square miles of rain forest, or about an acre a second. We will lose another 72 square miles to encroaching deserts, the result of human mismanagement and overpopulation. We will lose 40 to 250 species, and no one knows whether the number is 40 or 250. Today the human population will increase by 250,000. And today we will add 2,700 tons of chlorofluorocarbons and 15 million tons of carbon dioxide to the atmosphere. Tonight the earth will be a little hot­ter, its waters more acidic and the fabric of life more threadbare.... [P]erhaps as much as 20% of the life forms extant on the planet in the year 1900... [are now] extinct (2004, 7).

16 PEACE AND JUSTICE STUDIES

With particular reference to species loss, some biologists rightly label this phenomenon the "biodiversity crisis" (Butler 2007). In terms relevant to this article, the existence of the biodiversity crisis and the accompanying moral phenomenon of biocide can be linked to a lack of a specific form of love: biophilia. Translated from Greek, the term biophilia is centered on human love for the biological world. Yet, the first popular use of the term went beyond this to encompass the deep biological need of humans for relationship. In 1984, the Harvard biologist, Edward Wilson, wrote Biophilia, in which he defined his main term as "the connections that human beings subconsciously seek with the rest of life" (1984, 350). He connects his love-based project to the biodiversity crisis and humanity's responsibility to future generations: "The one process now going on that will take millions of years to correct is the loss of genetic and species diversity by the destruction of natural habitats. This is the folly our descendants are least likely to forgive us" (Wilson 1984, 121).

Wilson was not, however, the first person to connect love with a solution to the biodiversity crisis. For example, in the late 1940s, Leopold argued that a key part of this new imaging of rights for the natural world would involve recognition by humans that the force of love should mediate relations with the land. He concluded that extending the moral community to cover the land could mean only one thing—that the force of love has a real presence. Leopold posits: "It is inconceivable ... that an ethical relation to land can... exist without love, respect, and admiration for land and a high regard for its value. By value, I of course mean something far broader than mere economic value; I mean value in the philosophical sense" (1997, 638).

Understood in this integrated sense, love represents a community-building force that necessarily accompanies any movement toward an integrated manner of imaging human-Earth relationships. Love, for the inter-layered community of the Earth, can be seen to have the power to solidify the connection among all members of the life community. Such a spiritual love comes into being when it is recognized that, "In the measure that the community becomes a community of love and so capable of making real and great sacrifices, in that measure it can wipe out grievances and correct the objective absurdities that its unauthenticity has brought about" (Lonergan quoted in Crowe 1992,34). To be an effective tool of community-building, this love requires looking beyond selfish and immediate concerns, instead moving toward the needs of the whole community and future generations. This shift is necessary for any diverse and compassionate society to come into being. Such a caring society would respect diverse forms of life on this planet, and its legal and ethical systems would foster a multi-species and

EARTH MATTERS 17

multi-generational form of respect. This is a vision of the future that is both biophiliC and biocratic.

A possible objection to the constitution of a biophilic future, where humans mediate a biocratic reality, is the notion that we are such selfish animals that it lies beyond our basic mammalian capability to work co-operatively with each other and the rest of the natural world in Order to avoid the pending biodiversity collapse. Certainly, Western civilization, in particular, provides far too much supporting evidence for the conclusion that humans are resolutely selfish animals. According to the joint analysis of Brian Swimme and Thomas Berry, this conclusion is particularly problematic because the growing Western influence in various cultures around the globe is generating an all-pervasive "addiction to commercial-industrial progress" (Swimme and Berry 1992, 254).

In terms of human justice, this "addiction" has been born out in a hugely unequal distribution of wealth and resources, so that today 97.5% of the world's eco-footprint is made by a mere 20% of the global population! This selfishness is particularly worrisome when the Earth's carrying capacity is finite, and we may be reaching the point where the collective impact of human lifestyles on the planet is unsustainable. At the present time, the Western vision of commercial consumption is being propagated around the world, and the "overshoot of the human economy" (Wackernagel et. al. 2002, 9266) is already placing multiple stressors on the continuance of diverse life in many bioregions. From the perspective of the pacifism of religious cosmology, it would be highly problematic if humans have evolved to be so selfish as to be pathologically incapable of steering a course that prevents the collapse of the biologically diverse world that has nurtured and sustained us. Unfortunately, such a negative outcome is implied by Oxford ethologist Richard Dawkins' rereading of Darwin. Dawkins famously concludes that evolution, especially amongst larger animals, has advantaged selfishness as a behavioral trait (Dawkins 1989, 47).

This new shading of competitive advantage is not as highly individualist as it may seem on the surface because even Dawkins recognizes that the more complex animals are themselves examples of cooperation amongst both genes (2004, 433) and cells (1989, 258). He further contends that "nice guys can finish first" even if the rules of the game of life are essentially governed by selfishness (Dawkins 1989, 202). According to Dawkins' reading of Darwinian theory, "nice guys" are those who behave in such ways that that they act unselfishly so that others from their species may continue. Dawkins sees such a being as destined to die a Darwinian death. He does, however, concede the possibility

18 PEACE AND JUSTICE STUDIES

that a sort of symbiotic "reciprocal altruism" may be evolutionarily advantageous even across species (Dawkins 1989, 202).

In recognizing the ethical tensions associated with anthropocentrism, it is possible to envision individuals whose entire being is connected to an integrated epistemology of biodiversity. These people would take the opening conceded by Dawkins for "nice guys" and remove many speciesist tendencies from this sphere of action. Their orientation would be so total in this regard that they would enter into a symbiotic and solidarity-driven relationship with the entire life community.9 Such individuals would think, act and love in ways that support the continuance of diverse life of this planet. This does not mean that they would always be successful in achieving these goals. Nonetheless, these people would endeavor with the spirit of love, in their thoughts and in their actions, to counteract the negative effects of the biodiversity crisis and act in ways that are mutually enhancing for all humanity and the rest of the ecosystem (Berry 1990, 80).

Unless this all sound overly utopian, it should be remembered that we can bear witness to people who are able to transcend human selfishness and live in this integrated fashion today. A prime example of such integrated living is found in the community of Dominican Sisters of Blairstown, New Jersey and other "Green Sisters" who commit their lives in services to the poor, the Earth, and God in the spirit of "engaged monasticism" (McFarland Taylor, 124). At Blairstown, inspired and nourished by Berry's thought, their entire vocation is lived out intellectually, morally, and religiously in line with biocratic principles (see Dominican Sisters of Blairstown 2010). Other poignant examples include the Jain who lives all of her life doing as little harm as possible to other members of the natural world," the native leader in the Chiapas who seeks to keep his people outside of the money economy so that they may live in harmony with the forest ecosystem (see Action for Community and Ecology in the Region of Central America 1998), and the ecofeminist who, through a special expression of embodied knowing, ties her being and liberationist project to the plight of the Earth." In responding to the ecological crisis in a manner which is authentic in relation to their own being (Knitter 2000, 366), such individuals can be understood as holders of a woridview which is supportive of the pacifism of religious cosmology.

Applied to the problems of the climate justice, this worldview exposes significant moral dimensions that relate to any movement towards geocide. For instance, consider a reading of the following passage, informed by an understanding of Pax Gaia:

EARTH MATTERS 19

The issue of the environment, now so crucial, ties us to one another as never before. Selfishness is no longer merely immoral, it is becoming suicidal. ...[I]t is impossible to protect the environment if entire areas of continents continue to live in misery. Many of our brothers and sisters are forced into a way of life that is unacceptable and unworthy of their human condition. We are more aware of this than ever, but we behave as if we were blind, deaf and insensible (The Social Affairs Commission of the Canadian Conference of Catholic Bishops 2008, 5).

Building on such statements, a perspective in accord with the pacifism of religious cosmology would note that it is not just an act of suicide that we are committing as we use up the Earth's resources, but also an act of homicide. The truth of this somewhat provocative statement is manifested by those human beings on the periphery of both global and local societies who pay the ultimate price for our military industrial model of consumption and its manifestations in climate and ecological crises. In this sense, Dom Helder Câmara was correct to speak of poverty as a horrible form of violence akin to a bomb (1971, 29). It understandable, therefore, that in continuing Câmara's legacy of praxis-based work with the poor in Northeastern Brazil, ecofeminist liberation theologian, Ivone Gebara, connects the suffering of the poor with the suffering of the Earth community, despite the resistance of the current bishop." This link between ecology, poverty, and violence is all around us. Hence, the importance of the vision of the future that Arthur Walker-Jones has discerned as operative in the spiritual tradition of the Psalms in which "social justice is interrelated with the well-being of Earth" (2009, 65).

Despite such a vision of integral justice, under present conditions, we are left with inequality for the Earth and its human inhabitants when market morality is made normative. Environmental harms are distributed unequally in the present context, raising important ecojustice issues about the health and well-being of both people and the planet (Deane-Drummond 2008, 27). In terms of human justice, developing countries and those with access to the fewest resources are bearing the greatest cost of the present climate crisis. Regrettably, in our present circumstances, those who have contributed the most to climate change are those who are the least vulnerable and the best able to adapt to the impacts of shifting weather patterns (with, for example, heating and air conditioning, dikes, irrigation, increased health care). At the same time those who have contributed the least are the most vulnerable and the least able to adapt to the consequences of shifting climatic conditions, which result in drought, desertification, flooding and extreme weather patterns (Stern 2009, 37). In this regard, when focusing on climate justice, the pacifism of religious cosmology recognizes the moral

20 PEACE AND JUSTICE STUDIES

problems inherent in our current way of being. But even societies with a high capacity for adaptability are vulnerable to climate-related events, such as the 2003 heat wave in Europe and Hurricane Katrina in the USA (Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change 2007, 56). Climate change not only threatens each person's fundamental and inalienable "right to life, liberty, and personal security" as guaranteed by the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948, article 3), it is also already responsible for considerable death and enormous hardship. In one snapshot of this problem, the World Health Organization concluded that in the year 2000 climate change caused the deaths of approxi­mately 150,000 people and resulted in the loss of about 5.5 million Disability Adjusted Life Years" (2003, 31). Further, adding to the issues of genocide, biocide and homicide, there is a sense in which climate change can be connected to cultural genocide as members of societies whose cultures are intimately connected to specific bioregions are forced to migrate away from their traditional lands. This point has even been made by The Australian Human Rights Commission's Aboriginal and Tones Strait Islander Social Justice Commissioner's Office in their 2008 Native Title Report. During their discussion of the impacts of climate change on indigenous Australians, the report's authors noted that one of the challenges that Aboriginal and Tones Strait Islanders "will" face is

people being forced to leave their lands particularly in coastal areas. Dispossession and a loss of access to traditional lands, waters, and natural resources may be described as cul­tural genocide; a loss of our ancestral, spiritual, totemic and language connections to lands and associated areas (Human Rights and Equal Opportunity Commission 2009, 117).

It follows that the factors that cause climate change and the efforts to both mitigate and adapt to climate change are moral issues that require an ethical response.

In addition to concerns for social justice, the IPCC report also lends statistical support to moral vision of connectivity mentioned above by demonstrating that not only will poorer human communities, and particularly those in high risk areas, be especially vulnerable as a result of the impacts of future anthropogenic climate change (IPCC 2007, 48) but simultaneously, the report notes,

approximately 20 to 30% of plant and animal species assessed so far are likely to be at increased risk of extinction if increases in global average temperature exceed 1.5 to 2.5°C over 1980-1999 levels. Confidence has increased that a Ito 2°C increase in glob­al mean temperature above 1990 levels (about 1.5 to 2.5°C above pre-industrial) poses significant risks to many unique and threatened systems including many biodiversity hotspots. Corals are vulnerable to thermal stress and have low adaptive capacity.

EARTH MATTERS 21

Increases in sea surface temperature of about I to 3°C are projected to result in more frequent coral bleaching events and widespread mortality, unless there is thermal adap­tation or acclimatization by corals. Increasing vulnerability of Arctic indigenous com­munities and small island communities to warming is projected (IPCC 2007, 56).

These negative effects on the larger, life community are additional reasons for speaking of climate change as a moral crisis. In the spirit of liberation theologians who called to our attention the need for a preferential option for the poor in order to overcome social injustice, and given the current effects of the climate crisis, we might also now speak of the need for a preferential option for the earth made poorer by human abuse (The Social Affairs Commission of the Canadian Conference of Catholic Bishops 2003, #7).

Conclusion: Moving Forward as One Earth Community

It follows from the perspective of the pacifism of religious cosmology and indeed most other ethical systems, that when we know that our actions are causing the death of others but we persist in those actions, we are contributing to a moral problem. As part of his favored "historical-cosmological approach to such problems" (Berry 2009a, 24), Berry encourages us to see that this present moment has required billions of years to come into being. 14 Change any part of the Universe story during those 137 billion years, and the current context would be different. As cosmological processes have unfolded, we have been formed by and remain dependent upon our irreducible location as part of the universe and its story. On the planetary level, like everything else in Earth's community, we are the way we are because of our interactions with the other members of that community. Today, as part of our responsibility to where we have come from and to where we are going as a communion of subjects, there emerges duties in relation to the other actors in the universe story. From the perspective of the pacifism of religious cosmology, a zone of respect among all life forms needs to be fostered by humans not only because of the inherent rights of other members of the Earth community, but because to do less imperils the essential human qualities of our existence. Just as we resist the notion of another part of the brger life community extinguishing our lives—we would likely strive to prevent a lion from eating our child or our self—so should we resist any actions that would extinguish other life forms unnecessarily since they too are an integral part of this one biodynamic community. It follows that the pacifism of religious cosmology holds that other-than-human creatures and the natural systems of Earth need to be respected, valued and considered in decision-making for the 21st century and beyond. In integral terms, concern for sustainability includes both humans and the rest of

22 PEACE AND JUSTICE STUDIES

Earth community. Given the present realties of the interrelated ecological and social crises, the road toward human flourishing will be constituted in proper relationships with each other and the rest of the natural world.

Mindsets that choose to flee the world, to ignore the moral problems associated with ecojustice, or to subdue the natural world solely or primarily to meet human needs are not representative of ways of being that will guide humanity to live on Earth in a manner that is mutually enhancing for us and the rest of the Earth's ecosystems. In ethical and legal terms, the anthropocentric exaltation of the human that has informed Christianity and Western humanism will not adequately address our current state of affairs. As Berry summarizes, 'O'we begin to realize that the devastation taking place cannot be critiqued effectively from within the traditional religions or humanist ethics. Nor can it be dealt with from within the perspectives of the industrial society that brought it about" (Berry 1996b).

When considering the ecological updating of the human project proposed by a pacifism of religious cosmology, it is important to note the inclusion of a sufficient focus on basic human needs because meeting such needs is a necessary precondition for our survival and our flourishing in proper relationships within a communion of subjects. Simultaneously, Berry's geobio-logical perspective demonstrates that a focus on the human that excludes the survival and flourishing of the rest of the ecosystem is a narcissism which previews our demise. For Berry, we require a more functional cosmology to underlie all religions and ethics, a woridview which firmly situates humanity within the universe story. As Berry writes, "[t]he basic ethical norm is the well­being of the comprehensive community, and the attainment of human well-being within this comprehensive community. The Earth is not part of the human story, the human story is part of the Earth story" (1996b). In short, to fully recognize that Earth matters and to deal with a crisis that affects the entire planet, we will need to embrace the reinvention of the human. Such reinvention will be fostered by a vision and inspiration of comparable magnitude. Happily, as evidenced by our framing of the pacifism of religious cosmology, humanity has within its traditions the resources that can inform a contextually appropriate reinvention of the human. Such an integral orientation to the problems of ecojustice can provide a vital source of hope for a vibrant and just future.

EARTH MATTERS 23

================

WORKS CITED

Action for Community and Ecology in the Region of Central America. 1998. Lacandona: The Zapatistas and the Rainforest of Chiapas, Mexico. New York: Media Rights.

Addison, Keith. 2007. Eco-footprint (2007).

www.journeytoforever.org/edu_footprint.html. Accessed November 18, 2007.

Baer, P, J Harte, and et al. 2000. Equity and Greenhouse Gas Responsibility. Science 289 (5488):2287.

Berry, Thomas. 1990. The Dream of the Earth. San Francisco: Sierra Club Books.

----.1996a. An Ecologically Sensitive Spirituality. http://www.csco.caldocuments/ cotent_91.doc. Accessed March 23, 2010.

1999. The Great Work: Our Way into the Future. New York: Bell Tower.

2009a The Christian Future and the Fate of the Earth. Maiyknoll, NY: Orbis Books.

2009b. The Sacred Universe: Earth Spirituality and Religion in the Twenty First Century. New York Columbia University Press.

Binz, Stephen J. 2007. Threshold Bible Study: Stewardship of the Earth. New London, CT: Twenty-Third Publications.

Burland, Cottie. 1973. Eskimo Art. Toronto: Hamlyn.

Butler, Rhett A. 2007. Just How Bad is The Biodiversity Extinction Crisis? A Debate Erupts in the Halls of Conservation Science. (February 6, 2007). http://news.mongabay.comI2007/0206-biodiversity.html. Accessed March 23, 2010.

Câmara, (Dom) Hélder. 1971. The Spiral of Holence. Denville: Dimension Books.

Dominican Sisters of Blairstown, New Jersey. 2010. Genesis Farm: A Learning Center for Earth Studies. www.genesisfarm.org. Accessed March 23, 2010.

Carlin, John. 2008. Playing the Enemy: Nelson Mandela and the Game that Made a Nation. New York: The Penguin Press.

Cortright, David. 2008. Peace: A History of Movements and Ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008.

Crowe, Frederick E. 1992. Bernard Lonergan and the Community of Canadians: An Essay in Aid of Canadian Identity. Toronto: Lonergan Research Institute and Canadian Institute of Jesuit Studies.

Davies, Helen. 2009. Scripture, Culture and Agriculture. An Agrarian Reading of the Bible. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Dawkins, Richard. 1989. The Selfish Gene. Toronto: Oxford.

2004. The Ancestor's Tale: A Pilgrimage to the Dawn of Evolution. Boston: Mariner.

Eaton, Heather. 2007a. The Revolution of Evolution. Worldviews 11: 6-31.

Responding to Climate Change: Scientific Realities, Spiritual Imperatives. (October 2007). http://tyne.caJief2007/uploads/Heather_Eaton.doc. Accessed March 23, 2010.

Deane-Drummond, Celia. 2008. Eco-Theology. Winona, MN: Saint Mary's Press.

Diamond, Jared F. 2005. Collapse: How Societies Choose to Fail or Succeed. Toronto: Viking.

Gebara, Ivone. 2000. Eco-Feminism: An Ethics of Life. In Sacred Earth, Sacred Community: Jubilee, Ecology and Aboriginal Peoples, edited by John Mihevc. 29­46. Toronto: Canadian Ecumenical Justice Initiative.

2009."What do we Mean by Change: Conflict Arising from a Feminist Ethical Perspective?' Catholic Network for Women's Equality Conference Lecture, Saint Paul University. Ottawa, June 13, 2009.

Goldman, Irving. 1975. The Mouth of Heaven: An Introduction to Kwakiutl Religious Thought. Toronto: John Wiley and Sons.

Hathaway, Mark and Leonardo Boff. 2009. The Tao of Liberation. Maryknoll, NY: Orbis.

Human Rights and Equal Opportunity Commission. 2009. 2008 Native Title Report. Sydney: Australian Human Rights Commission.

IPPC (The Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change). 2007. Climate Change 2007: Synthesis Report. (Valencia, Spain, 12-17 November 2007). Available from http://www.ipcc.ch/pdf/assessment-reportlar4/syr/ar4_syr.pdf. Accessed March 23, 2010.

John Paul 11. "The Ecological Crisis A Common Responsibility: Message of His Holiness for the celebration of the World Day of Peace, January 1, 19901" www.ewtn.com/library/PAPALDOC/JP9001 0 I .htm. (1 Jan. 1990). Accessed March 23, 2010.

Klein, Ernest. 1966. A Comprehensive Etymological Dictionary of the English Language. New York: Elsevier Publishing Company.

Knitter, Paul F. 2000. Deep Ecumenicity versus Incommensurability: Finding

Common Ground on a Common Earth. In Christianity & Ecology, edited by Dieter T. Hessel and Rosemary Radford Ruether. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Leopold, Aldo. 1997. The Land Ethic. In Ethics in Practice: An Anthology, edited by E.H. LaFollete. Oxford: Blackwell.

Lessa, William A. and Evon Z. Vogt. 1997. The Purposes of Shamanism. In Reader in Comparative Religion: An Anthropological Approach, 4th ed, edited by William A. Lessa and Evon Z. Vogt. New York: Allyn & Bacon.

Lonergan, Bernard. 1985. A Third Collection: Papers by Bernard JR Lonergan, S.J. New York: Paulist Press.

Lonergan, Bernard. 1990. Method in Theology. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

Mann, Richard. 1995. Dom Helder Camara: Les Puissants et Les Pauvres. Paris: Les Editions De L'Atelier, 1995.

Popper, Karl. 2007. The Poverty of Historicism. New York: Routledge.

McFarland Taylor, Sarah. 2007. Green Sisters: A Spiritual Ecology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Morgenthau, Hans J. 1978. Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

On, David W. 2004. Earth in Mind: On Education, Environment and the Human Prospect. Washington, DC: First Island Press.

Prashad, Sital. 1995. A Comparative Study of Jainism and Buddhism. Delhi: Indian Book Centre.

Radford Ruether, Rosemary. 1999. "On the Front Lines of Faith," Sojourners, 28, no. 6.

The Social Affairs Commission of the Canadian Conference of Catholic Bishops. You love all that exists... .all thing are Yours, God lover of Life: A Pastoral Letter on the Christian Ecological Imperative. Ottawa: Canadian Conference of Catholic

Bishops.

26 PEACE AND JUSTICE STUDIES

Our Relationship with the Environment: A Need for Conversion. Ottawa: Canadian Conference of Catholic Bishops.

Stern, Nicholas. 2009. Action and Ambition for a Global Deal in Copenhagen. Centre for Climate Change Economics and Policy; Grantham Research Institute for Climate Change and the Environment; In collaboration with the United Nations Environment Programme. (December 6, 2009). http://www.unep.org/pdf/cIimatechange/ ActionAndAmbitionForGlobalDeallnCopenhagen.pdf. Accessed Jauary 30, 2010.

Swimme, Brian and Thomas Berry. 1992. The Universe Story. New York: HarperCollins.

Tucker, Mary Evelyn and John Grim. 2009. Introduction. In Thomas Berry, The Christian Future and the Fate of the Earth. Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books.

United Nations General Assembly. 1948. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights. Available from http://www.un.org/en/documents/udhr/index.shtml. Accessed March 23, 2010.

Wackemagel, Mathis et. al. 2002. Tracking The Ecological Overshoot of the Human Economy" In The Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States ofAmerica (July 2002), 9266-71.

Walker-Jones, Arthur. 2009. The Green Psalter: Resources for an Ecological Spirituality. Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press.

Wilson, Edward 0.. 1984. Biophilia. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

1989. The Current State of Biological Diversity. In Biodiversity, ed. E. 0. Wilson

National Academy Press, 1989.

"Biodiversity: Challenge, Science, Opportunity." American Zoologist 34, no. 1 (1994): 5-11.

World Health Organization. 2003 Climate Change and Human Health: Risks and Responses. Geneva: World Health Organization.

Wright, Christopher J. H. 2004. Old Testament Ethics for the People of God. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.

Yoder, John Howard. 1992. Nevertheless: Varieties of Religious Pacifism. Waterloo, Ontario: Abington Press.

-----------------------

ENDNOTES

'Berry described himself as a "geologian" (i.e., an earth-thinker), a label that denotes Berry's deep commitment to discerning humanity's proper place within Earth's evolu­tion and the integral ecological ethics that result. For a comment on the origins of Berry's self-identification as a geologian, see Tucker and Grim (2009, xxvi).

2As Swimme and Berry write, "Earth cannot survive in fragments.... The well-being of the planet is a condition for the well-being of any of the component members of the

planetary community. To preserve the economic viability of the planet must be the first law of economics. ...The well-being of the Earth is primary. Human well-being is deriv­ative" (1992, 243).

'Berry's discussion of the atmosphere and seas being held in common anticipates cli­mate change debates on the atmospheric commons. See: P. Baer, J Harte, and et al. 2000. Equity and greenhouse gas responsibility. Science 289 (5488):2287.

4The South African national Rugby team is known as the Springboks. For an inter­esting comment on the rehabilitation of this symbol in post-Apartheid South Africa see Carlin (2008).

'See, for example, The Worcester Art Museum's 1833 version of Edward Hicks The Peaceable Kingdom at http://www.worcesterart.org/Co1lection1American11934.65.html.

6See: United Nations "International Day for Preventing the Exploitation of the Environment in War and Armed Conflict." http:llwww.un.orglenlevents/environment-conflictday/. Accessed April 2, 2011.

'Other ecological thinkers have commented on ecocide's moral significance. For instance, Mark Hathaway and Leonardo Boff recently wrote that "the threat of eco­cide. . . [is]. . .the key ethical challenge of our day" (Hathaway and Boff 2009, 348).

'For an explanation of the concept of eco-footprint (and the source of this statistic) see Addison (2007).

91n Judeo-Christian terms, this solidarity could be supported by "the good news that Creator and creation are bound together in a relationship that is trustworthy but at the same time delicate" (Binz 2007, 61).

'°Sital Prashad offers a good description of the efforts of Jams to live holistic lives that are respectful of the entire life community (1995).

"It follows from this tying together of the plight of women and the plight of the Earth based in a realization of the interlocking patterns of oppression that the emancipatory

project of feminism would be included in the ecological project and vice versa so that various expression of the women's movement can seek inspiration and nourishment from an identification with the diverse natural world (Gebera 2000, 29-46).

"2Câmara's successor, Bishop José Cardoso, thought that the pastoral work in the dio­cese had been too focussed on social questions, to the point that "spiritual matters" had

been severely neglected (Marin 1995, 325). Hence, many of the reforms Câmara insti‑

tuted in the diocese of Recife were reversed. Cardoso's actions included the closing of

of‑

28 PEACE AND JUSTICE STUDIES

the praxis-based seminary where Ivone Gebara was employed (Radford Ruether 1999, 24). Cardoso even tried to silence Gebara by bringing the full weight of Vatican disci­pline down upon her (Gebara 2009).

'A disability adjusted life year is a measure of the number of years lost over a per­son's life span due to ill-effects of disease and environmental factors.

"For a discussion of the importance of cosmological consciousness for contempo­rary spirituality and ethical practice, see Eaton (2007a, 6-31).


Life after Biopolitics biocracy

 Sara Guyer and Richard C. Keller

The South Atlantic Quarterly 115:2, April 2016  Duke University Press

Life after Biopolitics

 For a critical frame that has been with us for decades, biopolitics has proven extraordinarily resilient. Writings about human life on almost any scale—from the molecule to the species, from pharmacological development to the stewardship of life, from the rhetoric and poetics of animacy to the logic of genocide—draw deeply from the wells of biopower. The keyword biopolitics is vastly inclusive. Yet the philosopher Michel Foucault’s outline of a theory of biopolitics in the mid-1970s (which many consider the foundation of the concept) was also oddly specific. Foucault wrote of a new form of sovereignty that emerged in the waning days of absolute monarchy, one drawing on nascent principles of public health and hygiene, ideas about individual and social development, novel and increasingly expansive knowledges about sexuality, and overlapping forms of law and science to shape life at the levels of both individual and society. Although Foucault saw how such mechanisms might operate in totalitarian regimes— indeed, the specters of Nazism and Stalinism haunt his essays and lectures—his principal concern was the operation of such discourses toward the shaping of population health and vitality in liberal democracies. This scene of emergence raises a series of questions: does a context of global citizenship and global flows of capital, commerce, information, goods, and populations disrupt the links between a biopolitical and a bourgeois order? In other words, in a deterritorialized world that is both riven and linked by differential flows of ideas, capital, peoples, and technologies, is the biopolitical model too irrevocably linked to the nation-state to be of much use anymore? Are there better ways to think about life in the twenty-first century?

We are convinced that biopolitics has not outlived its usefulness. Hailing from the fields of literary criticism and history, we find a number of ways in which the biopolitical is an important frame with an enduring influence. Yet the study of life in the humanities and the qualitative social sciences has developed such that biopolitics alone is no longer sufficient. As the essays in this issue demonstrate, we live and think in an era that is after biopolitics: one in which the idea of biopolitics will remain a part of meditations about life, but which will call for other frames for conceptualizing life. To capture this understanding, we want to suggest that biopolitics not only survives these shifts but also that survival inheres in biopolitics, that there is no concept of life in biopolitics that is not, at the same time, a notion of survival. For this reason, among others, the “after” of this volume’s title can be heard to resonate with the sur of survival and the history of thinking about living as living on among those who have and have not reflected on biopolitics by name.

Foucault’s description of a bio-power of populations—in which a sovereign state would deploy scientific knowledge toward the end of broadly influencing life on a grand scale—emerged in a moment of fascination about human rights. With roots in Hannah Arendt’s reflections on the place of humanity in the aftermath of totalitarianism, Foucault’s thought—and, later, that of Giorgio Agamben, Roberto Esposito, and others—engaged with the affiliation of citizenship to human rights, the relationship between the individual and the state, the role of dignity as both a legal and a rhetorical concept in the making of the human, and the resilience of fictional biologies, marked at the intersection of the human sciences and the administration of populations. These were long-term historical developments, beginning by some accounts at the foundation of a Western legal tradition in the classical world, by others in the late nineteenth century. But even the terms of this frame long predate Foucault, with the French psychiatrist Edouard Toulouse (1929: 13) advocating the development of a “biocracy,” or “a state that would be directed by the life sciences,” as early as 1929. Several essays in this issue engage directly with this conceptualization of biopolitics, while linking its historical development to contemporary concerns. Invoking the development of an organicist social science at the foundation of the modern humanist disciplines, the place of dignity in the determination of citizenship, and the links between individual illness and social pathology, these essays address how a biopolitical frame continues to offer important lessons for the history of science, the legal paradoxes of the republic, and the writing of inequality on the contemporary body.

Yet, far from a “politics of life itself,” this imagining of biopolitics has profound limitations: in most scholarship, the biopolitical has remained an extraordinarily human-centered endeavor. We now live in an era marked by emergent rights discourses that extend far beyond the human, even though humans are thoroughly implicated in their articulation. One productive site for expanding these boundaries of a human biopolitics is the notion of the Anthropocene. Unknown fifteen years ago, the concept has become unavoidable in the physical, social, and human sciences. As defined by the atmospheric chemist Paul Crutzen (2002: 23), the Anthropocene is a descriptor of a new geological era in which humans have become the primary force shaping the earth’s geophysical, atmospheric, and ecological conditions. As such, it is a logical space of inquiry for exploring the overlaps between the political science of population and environmental change. Three of the essays in this issue operate at this intersection, or, as Joshua Clover and Juliana Spahr might argue, this ecotone. Where does the “natural” end, and where does the “human” begin? How can we imagine the coupling of human and natural systems as a site for exploring those categories that are fundamental to the development of the modern political subject, including global capitalism, gender distinction, an entropic understanding of human social evolution, and the transition of the natural world from a repository of fear to a space of domination? Animal sovereignty is another critical space for evaluating the limits and promise of biopolitics. Can a theoretical frame designed for exploring the modern state apply to “a state of nature”? Is there such a thing as a possible politics of animal life itself, and if so, what resemblances might it share with a human-centric biopolitics?

This issue forces both a conversation about such possibilities and a clearer articulation of what biopolitics can do. It engages broad questions about the history of the concept and mobilization of life toward the ends of the state; about the operation and place of life across political, social, cultural, and aesthetic discourses; and about links among discourses of life, the human, the animal, and the ecological, as well as the political or ethical subject. In a political context in which a differential value of life—black, queer, female, human, animal, fetal—remains fundamental, and in which the future of life itself is in question, the concepts and forms through which we imagine life are more important than ever. After biopolitics is the moment at which these questions of living, far from exhausted, linger. After biopolitics, we continue to engage with the complexities and potential of this critical frame, even in all of its limitations.

Note

Nearly all of the authors in this volume presented earlier versions of their essays as part of a 2011–13 John E. Sawyer Seminar on “Life in Past and Present.” We are grateful to the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation for generous support of this project and Megan Massino for offering crucial assistance throughout. The seminar’s postdoctoral fellow, Amanda Jo Goldstein, graduate fellows Bradley Matthys Moore, Michelle Nieman, and Stephanie Youngblood, and faculty participants Katarzyna Beilin, Helen M. Kinsella, Jimmy Casas Klausen, and Mario Ortiz-Robles, made valuable contributions to our thinking. Finally, we would like to acknowledge the vibrant thought of all of those colleagues who shared their work with us during the seminar in addition to those whose work appears in this volume: Andrew Aisenberg, Timothy Campbell, Stephen J. Collier, Joseph Dumit, Kim Fortun, Michael Hardt, Donna V. Jones, Ranjana Khanna, Jake Kosek, Jacques Lezra, Stephanie Lloyd, Becky Mansfield, Lee Medevoi, Natania Meeker, Gregg Mitman, Timothy Morton, Helmut Müller-Sievers, Susan Oyama, Peter Redfield, Eric L. Santner, Kavita Sivaramakrishnan, Jason E. Smith, and Roland Végső.

References

Crutzen, Paul. “Geology of Mankind.” Nature 415, no. 6867: 23.

Toulouse, Edouard. 1929. Le problème de la prophylaxie mentale. Paris: Imprimerie Chaix.


'지구의 사랑받을 권리' 생태도시포럼에서 배워요! | 서울시 - 내 손안에 서울

'지구의 사랑받을 권리' 생태도시포럼에서 배워요! | 서울시 - 내 손안에 서울
'지구의 사랑받을 권리' 생태도시포럼에서 배워요!


대학생기자 송수아

발행일 2020.09.22 10:43
수정일 2020.09.22 15:48


기후변화와 팬데믹 상황이 인류와 넓게는 지구를 위협하고 있는 가운데 지난 9월 17일, 서울시는 ‘생태문명과 지구법’이라는 주제로 생태도시포럼을 개최했다.



서울시가 언택트 방식으로 2020년 제 1차 생태도시포럼을 개최했다. ©서울시

생태도시포럼은 1998년 민간단체 ‘경제정의실천시민연합(경실련)’의 전문가들을 중심으로 발족된 생태도시에 관한 연구모임이다. 지속 가능한 생태도시를 위해 시민, 전문가, 공무원 등 누구나 참여 가능한 열린 형식의 포럼으로, 올해는 코로나19로 인해 언택트 방식으로 진행됐다. 시민들은 유튜브 생중계를 보며 채팅을 통해 의견을 나눌 수 있었다.

이번 생태도시포럼에서는 “기후변화와 팬데믹에 대응하기 위해 법이 지구와 지구공동체 모든 성원의 안녕을 보장해야 한다”는 새로운 철학인 ‘지구법’을 소개했다.



토마스 베리의 우주론에 대한 설명 ©서울시 유튜브

발제자로 나선 강원대 박태현 교수는 지구법학과 토마스 베리를 소개하며 말문을 열었다. 토마스 베리는 한마디로 ‘기능적 우주론’을 주장했는데, 우주를 주체들의 지속적인 상호작용으로 이뤄지는 전개과정이라고 말했다. 우주를 물리적, 물질적 실재이자 정신적, 영적 실재로 바라보는 것이다. 사진 예시처럼 우주에서의 진화과정(왼쪽)을, 지구의 생명 진화과정(오른쪽)을 통해 모두 하나의 공통된 무언가로부터 시작해 확장하고 가지를 쳐 나가는 과정을 설명했다.

특히 토마스 베리는 우주의 12원칙을 제시했다고 한다. 그 중 우주의 기본법칙으로 3가지를 주장했는데, 바로 주체성의 원칙, 분화의 원칙, 친교의 원칙 등이다.



레오폴드의 대지윤리 설명 ©서울시 유튜브

정리하자면, 인간은 자연을 자원으로 보고 이를 이용하기 위해 자원을 보존한다고 생각하는데, 토마스 베리는 인간과 자연을 주체간의 상호작용, 공동체로 보고 있다는 점이 결정적으로 다르다. 서로 상호이익을 증진하는 관계로 설정하고 이해를 해야 한다는 것이다. 토마스 베리의 법률론에 따르면 “최우선으로 간주해야 하는 공동체는 인간 공동체가 아닌 지구 공동체가 우선해야 한다. 이에 기초한 관리체제와 법률이 긴급하게 필요하다”며 인간중심에서 생명중심, 지구중심적으로 전환해야 한다고 주장했다.

이러한 토마스 베리의 지구법학이 나오기까기 영향을 미친 세 가지 주장이 있다. 그 첫 번째가 레오폴드의 대지윤리이다. 대지윤리의 핵심은 “인간을 대지의 정복자가 아닌 생명 공동체의 한 성원으로 바라보고, 윤리적 고려를 인간뿐만 아니라 토양, 물, 동식물 등 전체 생태계로 확장해야 한다”는 것이다. 생명 공동체의 통합성, 안정성, 아름다움을 지키고자 한 것이 레오폴드의 대지윤리이다.



네스와 세션스의 심층생태론 설명 ©서울시 유튜브

두 번째 사상은 ‘네스와 세션스의 심층생태론’이다. 여기에는 피상적 생태운동과 심층적 생태운동이 있는데, 피상적 생태론은 오늘날 환경운동이라고 말하는 오염과 같은 자연고갈에만 관심을 둔 것이고, 심층적 생태론은 인간을 자연으로부터 독립되어 있는 사고를 거부하고 전체 존재의 장 안에서 바라보고자 하는 것이다. 즉, 인간과 비인간적인 영역의 이분법을 강력하게 거부하고 궁극적으로 “생태계에 존재하는 모든 것은 살고 번성할 평등한 권리를 가지며 자아 실현을 할 동등한 권리가 있다”고 네스와 세션스는 주장했다.



크리스토퍼 스톤의 자연물 권리론에 대한 설명 ©서울시 유튜브

마지막으로 지구법학의 영향을 준 것이 크리스토퍼 스톤의 자연물의 권리론이다. 스톤 교수의 ‘나무도 원고적격을 가져야 하는가?(Should Trees Have Standing?)’ 논문에서는 자연물이 권리를 가져야 한다는 파격적인 주장이 담겨 있다. 하지만 논문이 발표된 70년대 당시에는 많은 사람들에게 조롱을 받았다고 한다. 이 내용은 아직까지도 논란이 되고 있는 주제이지만, 베리가 자연물이 법적 권리를 가져야 한다는 주장에 큰 영감을 주었다.



토마스 베리의 지구법학, 자연의 자유와 권리를 어디까지 부여해야 하는지에 대한 내용을 담고 있다. ©서울시 유튜브

이 세가지 이론의 공통점은 “모두 자연물에게도 권리를 부여해야 한다”는 점이다. 토마스 베리는 지구법학을 통해 “우주의 모든 성원은 다 권리를 가진 주체이며, 주체들 간의 친교(상호작용)가 우주다”라고 주장했다. 이러한 자유를 가질 자격으로서 권리는 인간법학에 의해 창설되는 게 아니라 궁극적으로 ‘우주’에서 기원한다고 덧붙였다.

지구법학의 주요 내용은 존재할 권리, 서식지를 가질 권리, 지구공동체 안에서 자신을 재생하는 과정에서 자기의 역할과 기능을 수행할 수 있는 권리 등이다. 한마디로 지구법학이란 “자연을 지구 공동체의 한 성원으로 보고 인간의 권리에 대한 절대성을 부정한다”는 것을 알 수 있었다.

박 교수는 자연의 관리를 최초로 헌법에 담은 에콰도로와 뉴질랜드의 입법사례도 소개했다. 에콰도르는 “자연과 조화하면서 자연의 권리를 인정하는 방식으로 시민의 웰빙을 추구하는 삶의 방식이 좋은 삶의 방식이다”라는 자연 권리 조항을 도입했으며, 뉴질랜드도 산림과 강에 법인격을 부여한 법률을 제정했다.

이와 함께 박교수는 ‘도시생태현황도(비오톱)’에 대해서도 소개했다. 비오톱(BIOTOPE)은 생명(BIO)과 장소(TOPES)의 합성어로서 도심에 존재하는 생물 서식공간을 지칭한다. 이는 “비오톱 평가 1등급으로 지정된 곳은 보존해야 한다”는 개발행위 기준이 되고 있다. 이와 관련해 토지 소유자들의 재산권 주장 소송도 이어지고 있다고 한다. 판례에 따르면 헌법재판소는 비오톱 1등급으로 지정된 토지는 생태환경 보전이라는 공익을 위해 수인해야 하는 사회적 제약 범주에 속한다고 판단했다.



비오톱은 생명과 장소의 합성어로 생물 서식공간을 지칭한다. ©서울시 유튜브

발제에 이어 아주대 오동석 교수와 생태보존시민모임의 민성환 대표의 지정토론이 진행됐다.

오 교수는 지구법학이 가진 고민과 한계에 대해 피력했다. 지구의 위기 문제의 원인이 된 서구 자본주의 심화와 경제 성장에 대한 욕구 등 자연 파괴에 대한 반성과 성찰이 함께 이루어져야 한다고 말했다. 그는 자연의 권리를 인정하자는 가치 주장만으로는 법 체계 운영에서 한계가 있다고 했다. 생태 문제는 소유권과 재산권의 문제와 부딪힐 수 밖에 없어 양립하기 어렵고 더욱이 이 문제는 민주주의 관점으로만 해결할 수도 없기 때문이다.

이에 대해 오 교수는 기존의 법리에 갇혀있기보다는 새로운 관점으로 전환하면 현재 우리가 가지고 있는 법으로도 다소 해결이 가능할 것이라고 말했다. 그는 “헌법 전문에 인류공영에 이바지 해야한다는 내용이 나오는데 이를 인간과 함께 살아가는 다른 생명체나 지구 전체 관점을 끌어낼 수 있을 것”이라며 “경제 개발과 토지 보존의 문제도 숙의민주주의 같은 절차를 추진해내는데 어려움은 있겠지만 정책이나 법률에 실제 반영이 되도록 해야 한다”고 강조했다.



생태도시포럼에 참가한 시민들의 질문 ©서울시 유튜브

이번 생태도시포럼은 언택트 방식으로 진행된 만큼 채팅창을 통한 시민들의 참여도 중요했다. 포럼을 관람한 시민들은 궁금한 내용을 채팅창에 남겼고, 패널들은 이에 대한 대답을 하는 시간을 가졌다. 이번 포럼을 준비하면서 서울시가 쌍방향 소통을 위해 많은 노력을 기울였다는 것을 느낄 수 있었다. 필자는 이번 포럼에서 비오톱이라는 용어를 처음 알게 되었는데, 자연에 조금 더 관심을 가져야겠다는 생각을 하게 되었다.

2020년 제 1차 생태도시포럼 다시보기 : https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Q5O62dtwaHo

▶ ‘내 손안에 서울’ 앱으로 받아보기
▶ '코로나19 서울생활정보' 한눈에 보기
▶ 내게 맞는 '코로나19 경제지원정책' 찾아보기

기사 관련 태그

태그#서울 #서울시 #포럼 #도시 #비오톱 #자연 #생태 #권리 #2020 #생태도시포럼 #토마스 베리 #이론 #지구법 #도시생태