2023/04/25

Sen’s Capability Approach | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Sen’s Capability Approach | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Sen’s Capability Approach
Amartya SenThe Capability Approach is defined by its choice of focus upon the moral significance of individuals’ capability of achieving the kind of lives they have reason to value. This distinguishes it from more established approaches to ethical evaluation, such as utilitarianism or resourcism, which focus exclusively on subjective well-being or the availability of means to the good life, respectively. A person’s capability to live a good life is defined in terms of the set of valuable ‘beings and doings’ like being in good health or having loving relationships with others to which they have real access.

The Capability Approach was first articulated by the Indian economist and philosopher Amartya Sen in the 1980s, and remains most closely associated with him. It has been employed extensively in the context of human development, for example, by the United Nations Development Programme, as a broader, deeper alternative to narrowly economic metrics such as growth in GDP per capita. Here ‘poverty’ is understood as deprivation in the capability to live a good life, and ‘development’ is understood as capability expansion.

Within academic philosophy the novel focus of Capability Approach has attracted a number of scholars. It is seen to be relevant for the moral evaluation of social arrangements beyond the development context, for example, for considering gender justice. It is also seen as providing foundations for normative theorising, such as a capability theory of justice that would include an explicit ‘metric’ (that specifies which capabilities are valuable) and ‘rule’ (that specifies how the capabilities are to be distributed). The philosopher Martha Nussbaum has provided the most influential version of such a capability theory of justice, deriving from the requirements of human dignity a list of central capabilities to be incorporated into national constitutions and guaranteed to all up to a certain threshold.

This article focuses on the philosophical aspects of the Capability Approach and its foundations in the work of Amartya Sen. It discusses the development and structure of Sen’s account, how it relates to other ethical approaches, and its main contributions and criticisms. It also outlines various capability theories developed within the Capability Approach, with particular attention to that of Martha Nussbaum.

Table of Contents
The Development of Sen’s Capability Approach
Sen’s Background
Sen’s Concerns
Sen’s Critiques of Utilitarianism and Resourcism
Utilitarianism
Act-Consequentialism
Welfarism
Sum Ranking
Resourcism
Core Concepts and Structure of Sen’s Capability Approach
Functionings and Capability
Valuation: Which Functionings Matter for the Good Life?
Evaluation: What Capability do People Have to Live a Good Life?
Applying Sen’s Capability Approach
Criticisms of Sen’s Capability Approach
Illiberalism
Under-Theorisation
Individualism
Information Gaps
Theorising the Capability Approach
Generating Lists for Empirical Research in the Social Sciences (Ingrid Robeyns)
A Participatory Approach to Evaluating Capability Expansion (Sabina Alkire)
Justice as Equal Capability of Democratic Citizenship (Elizabeth Anderson)
Capability as Freedom from Domination (John Alexander)
Martha Nussbaum’s Capability Theory of Justice
Structure and Development of Nussbaum’s Capability Theory
Criticisms of Nussbaum’s Theory
Sen and Nussbaum
References and Further Reading
Primary Sources
Secondary Sources
1. The Development of Sen’s Capability Approach
a. Sen’s Background
Amartya Sen had an extensive background in development economics, social choice theory (for which he received the 1998 Nobel Prize in Economics), and philosophy before developing the Capability Approach during the 1980s. This background can be pertinent to understanding and assessing Sen’s Capability Approach because of the complementarity between Sen’s contributions to these different fields. Sen’s most influential and comprehensive account of his Capability Approach, Development as Freedom (Sen 1999), helpfully synthesizes in an accessible way many of these particular, and often quite technical, contributions.

Sen first introduced the concept of capability in his Tanner Lectures on Equality of What? (Sen 1979) and went on to elaborate it in subsequent publications during the 1980s and 1990s. Sen notes that his approach has strong conceptual connections with Aristotle’s understanding of human flourishing (this was the initial foundation for Nussbaum’s alternative Capability Theory); with Adam Smith, and with Karl Marx. Marx discussed the importance of functionings and capability for human well-being. For example, Sen often cites Smith’s analysis of relative poverty in The Wealth of Nation in terms of how a country’s wealth and different cultural norms affected which material goods were understood to be a ‘necessity’. Sen also cites Marx’s foundational concern with “replacing the domination of circumstances and chance over individuals by the domination of individuals over chance and circumstances”.

b. Sen’s Concerns
The Capability Approach attempts to address various concerns that Sen had about contemporary approaches to the evaluation of well-being, namely:

(1) Individuals can differ greatly in their abilities to convert the same resources into valuable functionings (‘beings’ and ‘doings’). For example, those with physical disabilities may need specific goods to achieve mobility, and pregnant women have specific nutritional requirements to achieve good health. Therefore, evaluation that focuses only on means, without considering what particular people can do with them, is insufficient.

(2) People can internalize the harshness of their circumstances so that they do not desire what they can never expect to achieve. This is the phenomenon of ‘adaptive preferences’ in which people who are objectively very sick may, for example, still declare, and believe, that their health is fine. Therefore, evaluation that focuses only on subjective mental metrics is insufficient without considering whether that matches with what a neutral observer would perceive as their objective circumstances,.

(3) Whether or not people take up the options they have, the fact that they do have valuable options is significant. For example, even if the nutritional state of people who are fasting and starving is the same, the fact that fasting is a choice not to eat should be recognized. Therefore evaluation must be sensitive to both actual achievements (‘functionings’) and effective freedom (‘capability’).

(4) Reality is complicated and evaluation should reflect that complexity rather than take a short-cut by excluding all sorts of information from consideration in advance. For example, although it may seem obvious that happiness matters for the evaluation of how well people are doing, it is not all obvious that it should be the only aspect that ever matters and so nothing else should be considered. Therefore, evaluation of how well people are doing must seek to be as open-minded as possible. (Note: This leads to the deliberate ‘under-theorization’ of the Capability Approach that has been the source of some criticism, and it motivated the development of Nussbaum’s alternative Capability Theory.)

2. Sen’s Critiques of Utilitarianism and Resourcism
An important part of Sen’s argument for the Capability Approach relates to his critique of alternative philosophical and economics accounts. In particular, he argues that, whatever their particular strengths, none of them provide an analysis of well-being that is suitable as a general concept; they are all focused on the wrong particular things (whether utility, liberty, commodities, or primary goods), and they are too narrowly focused (they exclude too many important aspects from evaluation). Sen’s criticisms of economic utilitarianism and John Rawls’ primary goods are particularly important in the evolution of his account and its reception.

a. Utilitarianism
Economics has a branch explicitly concerned with ethical analysis (‘Welfare Economics’). Sen’s systematic criticism of the form of utilitarianism behind welfare economics identifies and rejects each of its three pillars: act consequentialism, welfarism, and sum-ranking.

i. Act-Consequentialism
According to act consequentialism, actions should be assessed only in terms of the goodness or badness of their consequences. This excludes any consideration of the morality of the process by which consequences are brought about, for example, whether it respects principles of fairness or individual agency. Sen argues instead for a ‘comprehensive consequentialism’ which integrates the moral significance of both consequences and principles. For example, it matters not only whether people have an equal capability to live a long life, but how that equality is achieved. Under the same circumstances women generally live longer than men, for largely biological reasons. If the only thing that mattered was achieving equality in the capability to live a long life this fact suggests that health care provision should be biased in favor of men. However, as Sen argues, trying to achieve equality in this way would override important moral claims of fairness which should be included in a comprehensive evaluation.

ii. Welfarism
Welfarism is the view that goodness should be assessed only in terms of subjective utility. Sen argues that welfarism exhibits both ‘valuational neglect’ and ‘physical condition neglect’. First, although welfarism is centrally concerned with how people feel about their lives, it is only concerned with psychological states, not with people’s reflective valuations. Second, because it is concerned only with feelings it neglects information about physical health, though this would seem obviously relevant to assessing well-being. Not only does subjective welfare not reliably track people’s actual interests or even their urgent needs, it is also vulnerable to what Sen calls ‘adaptive preferences’. People can become so normalized to their conditions of material deprivation and social injustice that they may claim to be entirely satisfied. As Sen puts it,

Our mental reactions to what we actually get and what we can sensibly expect to get may frequently involve compromises with a harsh reality. The destitute thrown into beggary, the vulnerable landless labourer precariously surviving at the edge of subsistence, the overworked domestic servant working round the clock, the subdued and subjugated housewife reconciled to her role and her fate, all tend to come to terms with their respective predicaments. The deprivations are suppressed and muffled in the scale of utilities (reflected by desire-fulfilment and happiness) by the necessity of endurance in uneventful survival. (Sen 1985, 21-22)

iii. Sum Ranking
Sum-ranking focuses on maximizing the total amount of welfare in a society without regard for how it is distributed, although this is generally felt to be important by the individuals concerned. Sen argues, together with liberal philosophers such as Bernard Williams and John Rawls, that sum-ranking does not take seriously the distinction between persons. Sen also points out that individuals differ in their ability to convert resources such as income into welfare. For example, a disabled person may need expensive medical and transport equipment to achieve the same level of welfare. A society that tried to maximize the total amount of welfare would distribute resources so that the marginal increase in welfare from giving an extra dollar to any person would be the same. Resources would therefore be distributed away from the sick and disabled to people who are more efficient convertors of resources into utility.

b. Resourcism
Resourcism is defined by its neutrality about what constitutes the good life. It therefore assesses how well people are doing in terms of their possession of the general purpose resources necessary for the construction of any particular good life. Sen’s criticism of John Rawls’ influential account of the fair distribution of primary goods stands in for a criticism of resourcist approaches in general. Sen’s central argument is that resources should not be the exclusive focus of concern for a fairness-based theory of justice, even if, like Rawls’s primary goods, they are deliberately chosen for their general usefulness to a good life. The reason is that this focus excludes consideration of the variability in individuals’ actual abilities to convert resources into valuable outcomes. In other words, two people with the same vision of the good life and the same bundle of resources may not be equally able to achieve that life, and so resourcists’ neutrality about the use of resources is not as fair as they believe it is. More specifically, Sen disputes Rawls’ argument that the principles of justice should be worked out first for the ‘normal’ case, in terms of a social contract conceived as a rational scheme for mutually advantageous cooperation between people equally able to contribute to society, and only later extended to ‘hard’ cases, such as of disability. Sen believes such cases are far from abnormal and excluding them at the beginning risks building a structure that excludes them permanently. The general problem is that such accounts ‘fetishize’ resources as the embodiment of advantage, rather than focusing on the relationship between resources and people. Nevertheless Sen acknowledges that although the distribution of resources should not be the direct concern in evaluating how well people are doing, it is very relevant to considerations of procedural fairness.

3. Core Concepts and Structure of Sen’s Capability Approach
This section provides a technical overview of Sen’s account.

a. Functionings and Capability
When evaluating well-being, Sen argues, the most important thing is to consider what people are actually able to be and do. The commodities or wealth people have or their mental reactions (utility) are an inappropriate focus because they provide only limited or indirect information about how well a life is going. Sen illustrates his point with the example of a standard bicycle. This has the characteristics of ‘transportation’ but whether it will actually provide transportation will depend on the characteristics of those who try to use it. It might be considered a generally useful tool for most people to extend their mobility, but it obviously will not do that for a person without legs. Even if that person, by some quirk, finds the bicycle delightful, we should nevertheless be able to note within our evaluative system that she still lacks transportation. Nor does this mental reaction show that the same person would not appreciate transportation if it were really available to her.

The Capability Approach focuses directly on the quality of life that individuals are actually able to achieve. This quality of life is analyzed in terms of the core concepts of ‘functionings’ and ‘capability’.

Functionings are states of ‘being and doing’  such as being well-nourished, having shelter. They should be distinguished from the commodities employed to achieve them (as ‘bicycling’ is distinguishable from ‘possessing a bike’).
Capability refers to the set of valuable functionings that a person has effective access to. Thus, a person’s capability represents the effective freedom of an individual to choose between different functioning combinations – between different kinds of life – that she has reason to value. (In later work, Sen refers to ‘capabilities’ in the plural (or even ‘freedoms’) instead of a single capability set, and this is also common in the wider capability literature. This allows analysis to focus on sets of functionings related to particular aspects of life, for example, the capabilities of literacy, health, or political freedom.)


 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Figure 1. Outline of the core relationships in the Capability Approach

Figure 1 outlines the core relationships of the Capability Approach and how they relate to the main alternative approaches focused on resources and utility. Resources (such as a bicycle) are considered as an input, but their value depends upon individuals’ ability to convert them into valuable functionings (such as bicycling), which depends, for example, on their personal physiology (such as health), social norms, and physical environment (such as road quality). An individual’s capability set is the set of valuable functionings that an individual has real access to. Achieved functionings are those they actually select. For example, an individual’s capability set may include access to different functionings relating to mobility, such as walking, bicycling, taking a public bus, and so on. The functioning they actually select to get to work may be the public bus. Utility is considered both an output and a functioning. Utility is an output because what people choose to do and to be naturally has an effect on their sense of subjective well-being (for example, the pleasure of bicycling to work on a sunny day). However the Capability Approach also considers subjective well-being – feeling happy – as a valuable functioning in its own right and incorporates it into the capability framework.

b. Valuation: Which Functionings Matter for the Good Life?
Sen argues that the correct focus for evaluating how well off people are is their capability to live a life we have reason to value, not their resource wealth or subjective well-being. But in order to begin to evaluate how people are performing in terms of capability, we first need to determine which functionings matter for the good life and how much, or at least we need to specify a valuation procedure for determining this.

One way of addressing the problem is to specify a list of the constituents of the flourishing life, and do this on philosophical grounds (Martha Nussbaum does this for her Capability Theory of Justice). Sen rejects this approach because he argues that it denies the relevance of the values people may come to have and the role of democracy (Sen 2004b). Philosophers and social scientists may provide helpful ideas and arguments, but the legitimate source of decisions about the nature of the life we have reason to value must be the people concerned. Sen therefore proposes a social choice exercise requiring both public reasoning and democratic procedures of decision-making.

One reason that social scientists and philosophers are so keen to specify a list is that it can be used as an index: by ranking all the different constituents of the flourishing life with respect to each other it would allow easier evaluation of how well people are doing. Sen’s social choice exercise is unlikely to produce collective agreement on a complete ranking of different functionings, if only because of what Rawls called the ‘fact of reasonable disagreement’. But Sen argues that substantial action-guiding agreement is possible. First, different valuational perspectives may ‘intersect’ to reach similar judgments about some issues, though by way of different arguments. Second, such agreements may be extended by introducing ‘ranges’ of weights rather than cardinal numbers. For example, if there are four conflicting views about the relative weight to be attached to literacy vis-à-vis health, of ½, ⅓, ¼ and 1/5, that contains an implicit agreement that the relative weight on education should not exceed ½, nor fall below 1/5, so having one unit of literacy and two of health would be better than having two units of literacy and one of health.

Sen does suggest that in many cases a sub-set of crucially important capabilities associated with basic needs may be relatively easily identified and agreed upon as urgent moral and political priorities. These ‘basic capabilities’, such as education, health, nutrition, and shelter up to minimally adequate levels, do not exhaust the resources of the capability approach, only the easy agreement on what counts as being scandalously deprived. They may be particularly helpful in assessing the extent and nature of poverty in developing countries. However, taking a basic capability route has implications for how the exercise of evaluating individuals’ capability can proceed, since it can only evaluate how well people’s lives are going in terms of the basics.

c. Evaluation: What Capability do People Have to Live a Good Life?
Evaluating capability is a second order exercise concerned with mapping the set of valuable functionings people have real access to. Since it takes the value of functionings as given, its conclusions will reflect any ambiguity in the valuation stage.

Assessing capability is more informationally demanding than other accounts of advantage since it not only takes a much broader view of what well-being achievement consists in but also tries to assess the freedom people actually have to choose high quality options. This is not a purely procedural matter of adding up the number of options available, since the option to purchase a tenth brand of washing powder has a rather different significance than the option to vote in democratic elections. For example, Sen argues that the eradication of malaria from an area enhances the capability of individuals living there even though it doesn’t increase the number of options those individuals have (since they don’t have the ‘option’ to live in a malarial area anymore). Because the value of a capability set represents a person’s effective freedom to live a valuable life in terms of the value of the functionings available to that individual, when the available functionings are improved, so is the person’s effective freedom.

The capability approach in principle allows a very wide range of dimensions of advantage to be positively evaluated (‘what capabilities does this person have?’). This allows an open diagnostic approach to what is going well or badly in people’s lives that can be used to reveal unexpected shortfalls or successes in different dimensions, without aggregating them all together into one number. The informational focus can be tightened depending on the purpose of the evaluation exercise and relevant valuational and informational constraints. For example, if the approach is limited to considering ‘basic capabilities’ then the assessment is limited to a narrower range of dimensions and attempts to assess deprivation – the shortfall from the minimal thresholds of those capabilities – which will exclude evaluation of how well the lives of those above the threshold are going.

As well as being concerned with how well people’s lives are going, the Capability Approach can be used to examine the underlying determinants of the relationship between people and commodities, including the following (Sen 1999, 70-71):

(1)      Individual physiology, such as the variations associated with illnesses, disability, age, and gender. In order to achieve the same functionings, people may have particular needs for non-standard commodities – such as prosthetics for a disability – or they may need more of the standard commodities – such as additional food in the case of intestinal parasites. Note that some of these disadvantages, such as blindness, may not be fully ‘correctable’ even with tailored assistance.

(2)      Local environment diversities, such as climate, epidemiology, and pollution. These can impose particular costs such as more or less expensive heating or clothing requirements.

(3)      Variations in social conditions, such as the provision of public services such as education and security, and the nature of community relationships, such as across class or ethnic divisions.

(4)      Differences in relational perspectives. Conventions and customs determine the commodity requirements of expected standards of behaviour and consumption, so that relative income poverty in a rich community may translate into absolute poverty in the space of capability. For example, local requirements of ‘the ability to appear in public without shame’ in terms of acceptable clothing may vary widely.

(5)      Distribution within the family – distributional rules within a family determining, for example, the allocation of food and health-care between children and adults, males and females.


The diagnosis of capability failures, or significant interpersonal variations in capability, directs attention to the relevant causal pathways responsible. Note that many of these interpersonal variations will also influence individuals’ abilities to access resources to begin with. For example, the physically handicapped often have more expensive requirements to achieve the same capabilities, such as mobility, while at the same time they also have greater difficulty earning income in the first place.

4. Applying Sen’s Capability Approach
The concept of a capability has a global-local character in that its definition abstracts from particular circumstances, but its realization depends on specific local requirements. For example, the same capability to be well-nourished can be compared for different people although it may require different amounts and kinds of food depending on one’s age, state of health, and so on. This makes the Capability Approach applicable across political, economic, and cultural borders. For example, Sen points out that being relatively income poor in a wealthy society can entail absolute poverty in some important capabilities, because they may require more resources to achieve. For example, the capability for employment may require more years of education in a richer society

Many capabilities will have underlying requirements that vary strongly with social circumstances (although others, such as adequate nourishment, may vary less). For example, the ‘ability to appear in public without shame’ seems a capability that people might generally be said to have reason to value, but its requirements vary significantly according to cultural norms from society to society and for different groups within each society (such as by gender, class, and ethnicity). Presently in Saudi Arabia, for example, women must have the company of a close male relative to appear in public, and require a chauffeur and private car to move between private spaces (since they are not permitted to use public transport or drive a car themselves). Strictly speaking the Capability Approach leaves open whether such ‘expensive’ capabilities, if considered important enough to be guaranteed by society as a matter of justice, should be met by making more resources available to those who need them (subsidized cars and chauffeurs), or by revising the relevant social norms. The Capability Approach only identifies such capability failures and diagnoses their causes. However, if there is general agreement in the first place that such capabilities should be equally guaranteed for all, there is a clear basis for criticizing clearly unjust social norms as the source of relative deprivation and thus as inconsistent with the spirit of such a guarantee.

The capability approach takes a multi-dimensional approach to evaluation. Often it may seem that people are generally well-off, yet a closer analysis reveals that this ‘all-things-considered’ judgement conceals surprising shortfalls in particular capabilities, for example, the sporting icon who can’t read. Capability analysis rejects the presumption that unusual achievement in some dimensions compensates for shortfalls in others. From a justice perspective, the capability approach’s relevance here is to argue that if people are falling short on a particular capability that has been collectively agreed to be a significant one, then justice would require addressing the shortfall itself if at all possible, rather than offering compensation in some other form, such as increased income.

Capability evaluation is informationally demanding and its precision is limited by the level of agreement about which functionings are valuable. However, Sen has shown that even where only elementary evaluation of quite basic capabilities is possible (for example, life-expectancy or literacy outcomes), this can still provide much more, and more relevant, action-guiding information than the standard alternatives. In particular, by making perspicuous contrasts between successes and failures the capability approach can direct political and public attention to neglected dimensions of human well-being. For example, countries with similar levels of wealth can have dramatically different levels of aggregate achievement – and inequality – on such non-controversially important dimensions as longevity and literacy. And, vice versa, countries with very small economies can sometimes score as highly on these dimensions as the richest. This demonstrates both the limitations of relying exclusively on economic metrics for evaluating development, and the fact that national wealth does not pose a rigid constraint on such achievements (that GNP is not destiny). Such analyses are easily politicized in the form of the pointed question, Why can’t we do as well as them?

Philippines South Africa
Gross National Income per capita (ppp) $ 4,002 $9,812
Life expectancy (years) 72.3 52
Mean years of schooling 8.7 8.2
Figure 2. Perspicuous contrasts: The Philippines does more with less

(Data from the 2010 UNDP Human Development Report)

 

5. Criticisms of Sen’s Capability Approach
This section outlines important criticisms of Sen’s approach, together with his responses.

a. Illiberalism
Liberal critics of Sen often identify the focus of the Capability Approach – ‘the ability to achieve the kind of lives we have reason to value’ – as problematic because it appears to impose an external valuation of the good life, whatever people may actually value. Rawls, for example, notes that the reason for liberals to focus on the fair allocation of general purpose resources rather than achievement is that this best respects each individual’s fundamental right to pursue their own conception of the good life. This relates to Rawls’ conception of justice as political rather than metaphysical: it is not the task of justice to assess people’s achievements, but rather to ensure the fairness of the conditions of participation in a society. Justice should be neutral with regard to judging different people’s conceptions of the good. But this neutrality seems incompatible with the Capability Approach’s concern with assessing people’s achievements, which would seem to require a much more substantive view of what counts as a good life than one needs for assessing general purpose resources. Rawls suggests that this constitutes the privileging of a particular (non-political) comprehensive conception of rational advantage or the good.

In replying to this criticism, Sen particularly points to the heterogeneity (variability) in people’s abilities to convert the same bundle of resources into valuable functionings. Theories of justice that focus on the distribution of means implicitly assume that they will provide the same effective freedom to live the life one has reason to value to all, but this excludes relevant information about the relationship between particular people and resources. Even if one abstracts from existing social inequalities or the results of personal choices (‘option luck’), as many liberal theories of justice do, one will still find a substantial and pervasive variation in the abilities of different members of a society to utilize the same resources – whether of specific goods like education or general purpose goods like income. That means that even if it happened that everyone had the same conception of the good, and the same bundle of resources, the fact of heterogeneity would mean that people would have differential real capability to pursue the life they had reason to value. Therefore, Sen argues, a theory of justice based on fairness should be directly and deeply concerned with the effective freedom – capability – of actual people to achieve the lives they have reason to value.

b. Under-Theorisation
Both capability theorists and external critics express concern that the content and structure of Sen’s Capability Approach is under-theorised and this makes it unsuitable as a theory of justice. Sen does not say which capabilities are important or how they are to be distributed: he argues that those are political decisions for the society itself to decide. Many philosophers have argued that without an objectively justified list of valuable capabilities the nature of the life ‘we have reason to want’ is unclear and so it is hard to identify the goal that a just society should be aiming towards, to assess how well a society is doing, or to criticize particular shortfalls. Different capability theorists have taken different approaches to the valuation of capabilities, from procedural accounts to ones based on substantive understandings of human nature. There are related concerns about the institutional structure of the Capability Approach, for example, brought by the Rawlsian social justice theorist, Thomas Pogge (Pogge 2002). How should capabilities be weighted against each other and non-capability concerns? For example, should some basic capabilities be prioritized as more urgent? What does the Capability Approach imply for interpersonal equality? How should capability enhancement be paid for? How much responsibility should individuals take for the results of their own choices? What should be done about non-remediable deprivations, such as blindness?

Sen’s main response to such criticisms has been to admit that the Capability Approach is not a theory of justice but rather an approach to the evaluation of effective freedom.

c. Individualism
Sen’s emphasis on individual effective freedom as the focal concern of the Capability Approach has been criticized as excessively individualistic. There are several components to this family of criticisms. Some communitarians see Sen’s account as lacking interest in, and even sometimes overtly hostile to, communal values and ways of life because of an excessive focus on individuals. Charles Gore, for example, has argued that Sen’s approach only considers states of affairs and social arrangements in terms of how good or bad they are for an individual’s well-being and freedom (Gore 1997). But this excludes consideration of certain other goods which individuals may have reason to value which are ‘irreducibly social’ because they cannot be reduced to properties of individuals, such as a shared language, set of moral norms, or political structure. A related criticism argues that Sen’s emphasis on individual freedom is vague and fails to consider how one individual’s freedom may affect others. Martha Nussbaum, for example, points out that a just society requires balancing and even limiting certain freedoms, such as regarding the expression of racist views, and in order to do so must make commitments about which freedoms are good or bad, important or trivial (Nussbaum 2003).  Others have noted that ‘freedom’ though broad, is a poor way of conceptualizing certain inter-personal goods such as friendship, respect, and care. A third line of critique takes issue with Sen’s ‘thin’ agency based picture of persons as too abstract and rationalistic. It is said to be founded too closely in Sen’s personal dialectical relationship between economics and philosophy, and not enough in the perspectives and methods of anthropology, sociology, or psychology (see, for example, Giri 2000; Gasper 2002). As a result Sen’s account is said to have a poor grasp, for example, of the centrality and complexity of personal growth and development.

With regard to ‘irreducibly social goods’ like culture, Sen argues that they not only enter into the analysis instrumentally (such as in the requirements for appearing in public without shame) but also as part of the lives people have reason to value. Nevertheless Sen is clear in his view that the value of social goods is only derivative upon the reflective choices of those concerned (see, for example, Sen 2004a). So if people on reflection don’t value such social goods as the traditional religious institutions of their society or continuing to speak a minority language then that should trump the ‘right’ of those institutions to continue. With regard to freedom, Sen distinguishes the ability to choose between different options from the value of those options. These two together make up effective freedom or capability. Simple freedom to choose may be vulnerable to the objection that it is compatible with invidious freedoms, but the Capability Approach is concerned with people’s ability to live a life they have reason to value, which incorporates an ethical evaluation of the content of their options. It is not concerned only with increasing people’s freedom-as-power. Finally, Sen’s Capability Approach is particularly concerned with grasping the dimensions of human well-being and advantage missing from standard approaches. This relates to its concern with tracing the causal pathways of specific deprivations, with how exactly different people are able or unable to convert resources into valuable functionings. Although this remains somewhat abstractly presented in the formal structure of the Capability Approach, Sen’s analysis of, for example, adaptive preferences and intra-household distribution do go at least some way to a situated and sociological analysis.

d. Information Gaps
Sen’s Capability Approach is founded on the idea that much more information about the quality of human lives can and should be taken into account in evaluating them. The Human Development Index developed by Amartya Sen and the economist Mahbub ul Haq in 1990 for the United Nations Development Programme’s Human Development Reports is the most influential capability metric currently used. However it has been criticized for its crudeness. It contains only three dimensions – longevity, literacy (mean years of schooling), and Gross National Income per capita – which are weighted equally. The Capability Approach is supposed to be interested in assessing how people fare on many dimensions of life including some which seem very difficult to obtain information about, such as people’s real choice sets or such complicated capabilities as the ability to appear in public without shame or to form relationships with others. It also requires detailed information on the real inter-personal variations in translating commodities into functionings. It is not clear however that such informational ambitions could ever be realized. Furthermore even the effort of trying to collect such detailed information about people’s lives and their ‘real’ disabilities can be seen as invasive.

Sen was concerned about the crudeness of the Human Development Index (HDI) from the start, but was won over by Mahbub ul Haq’s argument for the rhetorical significance of a composite index of human well-being that could compete directly with the crude GDP per capita numbers that have been so influential in development thinking. Thus the HDI does not fully reflect the scope or methodology of the Capability Approach. Nevertheless it has succeeded in demonstrating that capability related information can be used systematically as a credible supplement to economic metrics. Sen accepts that some information about capabilities is easier to obtain than others. Firstly, he argues that we already have quite extensive information about some basic capabilities even for many quite poor countries, such as about health, that can and should be systematically assessed. There is therefore no need to limit our assessment to economic metrics which firstly count the wrong things (means) and secondly also come with significant measurement error despite their apparent numerical precision. Secondly, he argues that if researchers accept the capability space as the new priority for evaluation that will motivate the development of new data collection priorities and methods. As a result more information will become available about how people are faring on the currently ‘missing dimensions’ of the lives we have reason to value, for example, relating to employment or gender equality in domestic arrangements. Nevertheless, the Capability Approach is not concerned with information collection for its own sake, but rather with the appropriate use of information for assessment. It is therefore not committed to, nor does its effective use require, building a perfect information collection and assessment bureaucracy.

6. Theorising the Capability Approach
A number of philosophers sympathetic to Sen’s foundational concerns have nevertheless been dissatisfied with the vagueness and under-elaboration of the theoretical structure of his Capability Approach (although these features seem to be quite deliberate on Sen’s part). A number of theoretical accounts have been developed that seek to elaborate the Capability Approach more systematically and to address these philosophers’ particular concerns. Some theoretical accounts are primarily concerned with operationalising the evaluative dimension of the Capability Approach: the assessment of quality of life, well-being and human development. Others focus on developing a capability based ‘Theory of Justice’ in the spirit of its concerns. This section provides a brief outline of some of these.

a. Generating Lists for Empirical Research in the Social Sciences (Ingrid Robeyns)
Ingrid Robeyns argues that attempting to develop a single all-purpose list of capabilities would be incompatible with Sen’s concern with a general framework of evaluation. Instead she proposes a procedural approach to the selection of capabilities for particular purposes, such as the evaluation of gender inequality in terms of capabilities (Robeyns 2003). She claims that valuational procedures that meet her criteria provide epistemic, academic, and political legitimacy for empirically evaluating capability. Her five criteria are:

(1) Explicit formulation. All proposed list elements should be explicit, so they can be discussed and debated.

(2) Methodological justification. The method of generating the list should be made explicit so it can be scrutinized.

(3) Sensitivity to context. The level of abstraction of the list should be appropriate to its purposes, whether for philosophical, legal, political, or social discussion.

(4) Different levels of generality. If the list is intended for empirical application or public policy then it should be drawn up in two distinct stages, first an ideal stage and then a pragmatic one that reflects perhaps temporary feasibility constraints on information and resources.

(5) Exhaustion and non-reduction. The list should include all important elements and those elements should not be reducible to others (though they may overlap).

b. A Participatory Approach to Evaluating Capability Expansion (Sabina Alkire)
Sabina Alkire has developed a philosophically grounded framework for the participatory valuation and evaluation of development projects in terms of capability enhancement (Alkire 2005). This allows her to go beyond standard cost-benefit analyses of development projects in financial terms to investigate which capabilities that the people concerned have reason to value are enhanced and by how much.

Alkire’s approach has 2 stages of evaluation: i) a theoretical one-off stage in which ‘philosophers’ employ practical reason to reflexively identify the basic spheres or categories of value, and ii) a local participatory phase in which members of a social group deliberate, with the aid of a facilitator, about what their needs are and what, and how, they would like to do about them (with the basic categories employed as prompts to ensure that all main dimensions of value are discussed). For the first, philosophical, stage Alkire proposes an adaptation of the practical reasoning approach of John Finnis to identify the basic dimensions of human well-being by asking iteratively, ‘why do I/others do what we do?’ until one comes to recognize the basic reasons for which no further reasoned justification can be given. This method is intended to yield substantive and objective descriptions of the fundamental, non-hierarchically ordered, dimensions of human flourishing, while allowing the content and relative importance of these dimensions to be specified in a participatory process according to a particular group’s historical, cultural, and personal values. The intrinsically important dimensions identified by this method are: Life; Knowledge; Play; Aesthetic experience; Sociability; Practical reasonableness; Religion.

One of the advantages Alkire claims for her approach is its ability to elicit what the people whose lives are the subject of development projects really consider valuable, which may sometimes surprise external planners and observers. Her use of the participatory approach for assessing NGO fieldwork in Pakistan showed, for example, that even the very poor can and do reasonably value other things than material well-being, such as religion and social participation.

c. Justice as Equal Capability of Democratic Citizenship (Elizabeth Anderson)
Elizabeth Anderson has proposed a partial theory of justice based on equal capability of democratic citizenship (Anderson 1999). Anderson takes equality in social relationships as the focus for her egalitarian theory of justice and argues that one should analyze the requirements of such equality in terms of the social conditions supporting it as a capability. Although Anderson’s primary concern is for equality in the particular dimension of democratic citizenship, she suggests that this has extensive egalitarian implications for the nature of the society as a whole, because other capabilities – such as relating to health, education, personal autonomy and self-respect, and economic fairness – are required as supporting conditions to realize truly equal citizenship.  She argues that, “Negatively, people are entitled to whatever capabilities are necessary to enable them to avoid or escape entanglement in oppressive social relationships. Positively, they are entitled to whatever capabilities are necessary for functioning as an equal citizen in a democratic state (Anderson 1999, 317).”

d. Capability as Freedom from Domination (John Alexander)
John Alexander has proposed a capability theory based on a Republican understanding of the importance of freedom as non-domination (Alexander 2008). He argues that the Capability Approach’s concern with people’s ‘real freedom’ sets it outside and against the standard liberal egalitarian theory of justice framework which understands freedom as the absence of constraints. But he argues that the Capability Approach should go further to elaborate this commitment to real freedom in Republican terms. In this perspective it is not only important that one be able to achieve certain functionings, such as mobility, but whether one’s achievement of these are conditional on the favor or goodwill of other people or are independently guaranteed by one’s own rights and powers. Capability is standardly understood as mapping one’s range of choices over valuable functionings regardless of their content. For example, the ability of a physically disabled but socially well-connected person to travel outside whenever she wants by arranging the help of friends, family and voluntary organizations. In addition the Republican perspective requires that her capability for mobility should be independent of context. For example, in the form of a guaranteed legal right to government assistance on demand, or by the provision of her own specially adapted self-drive vehicle. Otherwise she may be said to be still deprived since her capability is not completely free.

Domination should also be integrated into capability evaluation because it will often be a cause of capability deprivation. It is no coincidence that the people who are most capability deprived are often the poorest and weakest in society, and as a result also vulnerable to yet further exploitation. This emphasis on freedom from domination also gives a strong normative orientation to the Capability Approach’s evaluation of the causes of capability failure: some causes are simply unacceptable, such as social norms restricting women’s freedom of movement and employment, and should be removed rather than mitigated.

7. Martha Nussbaum’s Capability Theory of Justice
This section outlines Martha Nussbaum’s work on the Capability Approach: its structure, criticisms, and relationship to Amartya Sen’s work.

a. Structure and Development of Nussbaum’s Capability Theory
Martha Nussbaum has developed the most systematic, extensive, and influential capability theory of justice to date. Nussbaum aims to provide a partial theory of justice (one that doesn’t exhaust the requirements of justice) based on dignity, a list of fundamental capabilities, and a threshold.

Nussbaum’s list of The Central Human Capabilities (Reproduced from Creating Capabilities 2011, 33-4)

1. Life. Being able to live to the end of a human life of normal length; not dying prematurely, or before one’s life is so reduced as to be not worth living.

2. Bodily Health. Being able to have good health, including reproductive health; to be adequately nourished; to have adequate shelter.

3. Bodily Integrity. Being able to move freely from place to place; to be secure against violent assault, including sexual assault and domestic violence; having opportunities for sexual satisfaction and for choice in matters of reproduction.

4. Senses, Imagination, and Thought. Being able to use the senses, to imagine, think, and reason – and to do these things in a ‘‘truly human’’ way, a way informed and cultivated by an adequate education, including, but by no means limited to, literacy and basic mathematical and scientific training. Being able to use imagination and thought in connection with experiencing and producing works and events of one’s own choice, religious, literary, musical, and so forth. Being able to use one’s mind in ways protected by guarantees of freedom of expression with respect to both political and artistic speech, and freedom of religious exercise. Being able to have pleasurable experiences and to avoid non-beneficial pain.

5. Emotions. Being able to have attachments to things and people outside ourselves; to love those who love and care for us, to grieve at their absence; in general, to love, to grieve, to experience longing, gratitude, and justified anger. Not having one’s emotional development blighted by fear and anxiety. (Supporting this capability means supporting forms of human association that can be shown to be crucial in their development.)

6. Practical Reason. Being able to form a conception of the good and to engage in critical reflection about the planning of one’s life. (This entails protection for the liberty of conscience and religious observance.)

7. Affiliation.

A. Being able to live with and toward others, to recognize and show concern for other human beings, to engage in various forms of social interaction; to be able to imagine the situation of another. (Protecting this capability means protecting institutions that constitute and nourish such forms of affiliation, and also protecting the freedom of assembly and political speech.)

B. Having the social bases of self-respect and nonhumiliation; being able to be treated as a dignified being whose worth is equal to that of others. This entails provisions of nondiscrimination on the basis of race, sex, sexual orientation, ethnicity, caste, religion, national origin.

8. Other Species. Being able to live with concern for and in relation to animals, plants, and the world of nature.

9. Play. Being able to laugh, to play, to enjoy recreational activities.

10. Control Over One’s Environment.

A. Political. Being able to participate effectively in political choices that govern one’s life; having the right of political participation, protections of free speech and association.

B. Material. Being able to hold property (both land and movable goods), and having property rights on an equal basis with others; having the right to seek employment on an equal basis with others; having the freedom from unwarranted search and seizure. In work, being able to work as a human being, exercising practical reason, and entering into meaningful relationships of mutual recognition with other workers.

In her early contributions to the capability approach, Nussbaum justified the composition of her list by explicitly Aristotelian argument about the perfectionist requirements of the truly human life (Nussbaum 1988). In the mid-1990s however she converted the structure of her account to a Rawlsian style ‘politically liberal’ account. This means that she now presents her list as a proposal that is neutral with respect to particular conceptions of the good, but can be endorsed by many different groups in a society through an overlapping consensus. However the list components themselves remain almost identical and retain a distinctively Aristotelian cast.

Nussbaum’s account is motivated by a concept of human dignity (in contrast to Sen’s emphasis on freedom), which she links to flourishing in the Aristotelian sense. She argues that her list of 10 fundamental capabilities follow from the requirements of dignity and have been tested and adapted over the course of an extensive cross-cultural dialogue she has carried out, particularly in India (as related in her book, Women and Human Development, 2001). The threshold is a ‘sufficientarian’ principle that specifies the minimum requirements of justice: everyone must be entitled to each capability at least to this degree by their governments and relevant international institutions. Access to these capabilities is required by human dignity, Nussbaum argues, but this does not mean that a life lacking in any of these, whether from external deprivation or individual choice, is a less than human life. Choice and deprivation are different however. If someone lacks access to these capabilities, for example, to be well-nourished (bodily health), that reflects a failure by society to respect her human dignity. If someone chooses not to take up her opportunities to certain capabilities, for example, to adopt an ascetic life-style and fast for religious reasons at the expense of her bodily health, respecting that choice is also an aspect of respecting her dignity.

Nussbaum suggests that her list, together with the precise location of the threshold, should be democratically debated and incorporated into national constitutional guarantees, international human rights legislation and international development policy. In keeping with its commitment to political liberalism, the components of Nussbaum’s list have a ‘thick-vague’ character in that while they have a universal claim to be of central importance to any human life, their definition is vague enough to allow their specification in multiple ways that reflect the values, histories, and special circumstances of particular political societies. For example, freedom of speech may be defined differently in law in the USA and Germany, because of their different histories, without endangering the fundamental capability. Nevertheless, because each capability is equally centrally important and a shortfall in any area is significant in itself, the scope for governments to make trade-offs between them, for example, on the basis of quantitative cost-benefit analysis, is limited.

b. Criticisms of Nussbaum’s Theory
Nussbaum’s capability theory of justice received quite intense criticism. Some have questioned the epistemological basis of her approach, finding it rather suspicious that after all her years of cross-cultural discussion her list remains basically the same rather ‘intellectualized’ Aristotelian one she had suggested in the first place (Okin 2003), and suggest that it rather reflects the values of a typical 21st century American liberal than a set of timeless universal values or a contemporary global overlapping consensus (Stewart 2001). Others have argued that her legal-moral-philosophical orientation is elitist and over-optimistic about what constitutions and governments are like and are capable of (Menon 2002); is over-specified and paternalistic yet still misses out important capabilities and is inappropriate for many uses, such as quality of life measurement or development fieldwork (Alkire 2005, 35-45).

In response to such criticisms, Nussbaum has defended the contents of her list as having cross-cultural credibility, but also emphasised that she is not trying to impose a definitive capability theory on everyone. She makes a clear and explicit distinction between the dimensions of justification (why her theory is best) and implementation (its more humble meta-status as an object for democratic deliberation and decision by those concerned) (Nussbaum 2004).

c. Sen and Nussbaum
Nussbaum and Sen collaborated in the late 1980s and early 1990s and since they are the most high-profile writers in the Capability Approach their accounts are often elided, despite significant differences. When they are distinguished, Nussbaum’s account is often seen as the more ‘philosophical’ because she has developed the Capability Approach in a more orthodox philosophical way, for example, by focusing on theoretical rigor, coherence and completeness. As a result, Sen’s approach is sometimes perceived merely as a predecessor to Nussbaum’s more developed second generation account, and therefore of primarily historical interest to understanding the Capability Approach rather than a parallel account in its own right.

The accounts of Sen and Nussbaum differ significantly in ways that relate to their different concerns and backgrounds. In particular:

Nussbaum is concerned to produce a philosophically coherent normative (partial) theory of justice; Sen is concerned with producing a general framework for evaluating the quality of lives people can lead that can incorporate the very diverse concerns and dimensions that may be applicable.
While Sen’s approach is founded on enhancing individual freedom, Nussbaum’s theory is founded on respecting human dignity.
Sen’s comprehensive consequentialism makes room for incorporating empirical information about feasibility and instrumental relationships between capabilities when considering policies; Nussbaum largely rejects such instrumental analysis because she is wary of its ‘Utilitarian associations’.
Sen’s Capability Approach in its normative ‘developmental’ aspect, is mainly concerned with practical incremental improvements; Nussbaum’s approach is rather more utopian in that it demands the full implementation of minimal justice (achievement of the minimum thresholds of all fundamental capabilities) for all, and this is specified so demandingly that no country yet meets it (though she has suggested that Finland may be close).
8. References and Further Reading
a. Primary Sources
John M. Alexander 2008. Capabilities and Social Justice. Ashgate Publishing, Ltd.
Introduction to the Capability Approach, with attention to Sen’s, Nussbaum’s, and Anderson’s accounts and a development of his own Republican account in the final chapter.
Sabina Alkire. 2005. Valuing Freedoms. Oxford University Press.
First half of the book develops a procedure for operationalizing the Capability Approach for participatory development; second half applies this to the evaluation of development projects.
Elizabeth Anderson. 1999. “What Is the Point of Equality?” Ethics 109 (2): 287-337.
Critique of luck egalitarianism and outline of a capability theory of justice based on the capability for equal democratic citizenship.
Martha Nussbaum. 1988. Nature, Function, and Capability: Aristotle on Political Distribution. In Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
Martha Nussbaum’s first contribution to the capability approach, based on a reading of Aristotle’s politics and ethics.
Martha Nussbaum. 2001. Women and Human Development (Cambridge University Press,).
Key text in Nussbaum’s second stage – political – development of a capability theory of justice.
Martha Nussbaum. 2004. “On Hearing Women’s Voices: A Reply to Susan Okin.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 32 (2): 193-205.
Nussbaum replies to criticisms of the methodology and legitimacy of her list.
Martha Nussbaum. 2011. Creating Capabilities: The Human Development Approach (Harvard University Press).
Non-technical introduction to the capability approach and Nussbaum’s capability theory of justice intended for university undergraduates.
Ingrid Robeyns. 2003. “Sen’s Capability Approach and Gender Inequality: selecting relevant capabilities.” Feminist Economics 9 (2): 61-92.
Robeyns outlines her procedure for choosing capabilities and applies it to the case of gender equality.
Amartya Sen. 1979. Equality of What? Stanford University: Tanner Lectures on Human Values (Available from the Tanner Lectures website)
Amartya Sen’s first publication on the capability approach, particularly focused on criticizing utilitarian and Rawlsian perspectives on well-being.
Amartya Sen. 1985. Commodities and Capabilities. North-Holland.
The most formal (technical) elaboration of Sen’s capability approach.
Amartya Sen. 1989. “Development as Capability Expansion,” Journal of Development Planning 19: 41–58.
An especially accessible and succinct account of the capability approach to human development.
Amartya Sen. 1999. Development as Freedom. Oxford University Press.
Important and influential synthesis of Sen’s work on human development and the Capability Approach.
Amartya Sen. 2004a. UN Human Development Report 2004: Chapter 1 Cultural Liberty and Human Development. UN Human Development Reports. United Nations Development Programme. (Available from the UNDP website).
Strong argument by Sen that cultural rights should be derivative upon individuals’ freedom to choose.
Amartya Sen. 2004b. “Capabilities, Lists, and Public Reason: Continuing the Conversation,” Feminist Economics 10, no. 3: 77-80.
An interview with Amartya Sen in which he elaborates on his rejection of a fixed list of capabilities (frequently cited).
b. Secondary Sources
Des Gasper. 2002. “Is Sen’s Capability Approach an Adequate Basis for Considering Human Development?” Review of Political Economy 14 (4): 435-461.
Thorough analysis of Sen’s account, including a critique of its excessive abstraction.
Ananta Kumar Giri. 2000. “Rethinking Human Well-being: A Dialogue with Amartya Sen.” Journal of International Development 12 (7): 1003-1018.
Critique of Sen’s neglect of personal development.
Charles Gore. 1997. “Irreducibly Social Goods and the Informational Basis of Amartya Sen’s Capability Approach.” Journal of International Development 9 (2): 235-250.
Critique of Sen’s neglect of social values.
Susan Moller Okin. 2003. “Poverty, Well-Being, and Gender: What Counts, Who’s Heard?” Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (3): 280-316.
Feminist critique of Nussbaum’s theory
Nivedita Menon. 2002. “Universalism without Foundations?” Economy and Society 31 (1): 152.
Critique of the political philosophy in Nussbaum’s theory.
Martha Nussbaum. 2003. “Capabilities as Fundamental Entitlements: Sen and Social Justice.” Feminist Economics 9 (2): 33.
Critique of Sen’s Capability Approach as too vaguely specified to support normative judgments.
Thomas Pogge. 2002. “Can the Capability Approach Be Justified?” Philosophical Topics 30 (2): 167–228.
Important Rawlsian critique of Sen’s account, frequently cited.
Frances Stewart. 2001. Book Review “Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach, by Martha Nussbaum” Journal of International Development 13 (8): 1191-1192.
Short but powerful critique of Nussbaum’s capability theory from a leading human development scholar.
 

Author Information
Thomas Wells
Email: t.r.wellsdunelm.org.uk
Erasmus University Rotterdam
The Netherlands

Empty Boat - Chuang Tzu & Thomas Merton - Stillness Speaks

Empty Boat - Chuang Tzu & Thomas Merton - Stillness Speaks

Empty Boat – Chuang Tzu & Thomas Merton
May 26, 2021

empty boat: “… Yet if the boat were empty. He would not be shouting, and not angry …”  … and …  “… This is perfect Tao. Wise men find here their resting place. Resting, they are empty …”  ~ Chuang Tzu

empty boat sunset batam island chuang tzu merton
Ah! … navigating the tricky (some might say treacherous?) waters of life … especially human emotions (e.g., anger and the like) …

Much has been written throughout the ages about navigating such waters …

One of the most gratifying joys of Stillness Speaks is the ongoing discovery of the delightful interconnectedness of traditions  … so it was no surprise to find Chuang Tzu in a recent encounter with Thomas Merton’s Silence, Joy! … which led to further explorations of Merton on this Taoist philosopher via Merton’s  The Way of Chuang Tzu …

Chuang Tzu, of course, is credited with writing the Zhuangzi one of the foundational texts of Taoism. Chuang’s The Empty Boat is a well known classic in the Taoist world … and is a great metaphor for charting these waters of life …

And here’s Merton on Chuang Tzu: “… His philosophical temper is, I believe, profoundly original and sane … it is basically simple and direct. It seeks, as does all the greatest philosophical thought, to go immediately to the heart of things. Chuang Tzu is not concerned with words and formulas about reality, but with the direct existential grasp of reality in itself …”

Merton adds: “… The whole Chuang Tzu book is an anthology of the thought, the humor, the gossip, and the irony that were current in Taoist circles in the best period, the 4th and 3rd centuries B.C. But the whole teaching, the “way” contained in these anecdotes, poems, and meditations, is characteristic of a certain mentality found everywhere in the world, a certain taste for simplicity, for humility, self-effacement, silence, and in general a refusal to take seriously the aggressivity, the ambition, the push, and the self-importance which one must display in order to get along in society …”

What is interesting about this Empty Boat  find  is that it magically (maybe even synchronistically) revealed itself after this “gem” from Merton: “… Solitude is not found so much by looking outside the boundaries of your dwelling, as by staying within. Solitude is not something you must hope for in the future. Rather, it is a deepening of the present, and unless you look for it in the present you will never find it …” … as an exquisite underscoring of the real treasures that lie “within” … and that they are invariably, if not inevitably, found in solitude … when the depth of the “present” reveals itself endlessly …

The gifts of solitude are mysterious indeed! …

solitude present chuang tzu merton
In the spirit of that magic, today we offer the gifts that can be found – some claim are inherent – in Chuang Tzu’s “Empty Boat” … so, pause … take a moment … read … reflect … pause again .. and see what is revealed 🙂

Empty Boat: The “Gateway” to “Perfection” ?
. . .
The way to get clear of confusion
And free of sorrow
Is to live with Tao
In the land of the great Void.

If a man is crossing a river
And an empty boat collides with his own skiff,
Even though he be a bad-tempered man
He will not become very angry.
But if he sees a man in the boat,
He will shout at him to steer clear.
If the shout is not heard, he will shout again,
And yet again, and begin cursing.
And all because there is somebody in the boat.
Yet if the boat were empty.
He would not be shouting, and not angry.

If you can empty your own boat
Crossing the river of the world,
No one will oppose you,
No one will seek to harm you.
. . .

“… Such is the perfect man: His boat is empty …”

empty boat chuang tzu merton
. . .
Who can free himself from achievement
And from fame, descend and be lost
Amid the masses of men?
He will flow like Tao, unseen,
He will go about like Life itself
With no name and no home.
Simple is he, without distinction.

To all appearances he is a fool.
His steps leave no trace. He has no power.
He … has no reputation.
Since he judges no one
No one judges him.
Such is the perfect man:
His boat is empty.

~ Chuang Tzu (via The Way of Chuang Tzu by Thomas Merton)

=== ==== ===

빈배가 되라

빈배가 되라


마음을 찾아서
빈배가 되라by 문촌수기 2013. 1. 1.


"배를 타고 강을 건너는데 빈 배가 떠내려와서 부딪치면 비록 속좁은 사람일지라도 화를 내지 않는다. 그러나 그 배 위에 사람이 있으면 비키라며 소리친다. 소리쳐도 듣지 않으면, 다시 부르고 또 듣지 않으면,세 번 소리친다. 그런즉 욕설이 나오기 마련이다. 아까는 화내지 않고 지금은 화를 내는 까닭은, 아까는 빈배였고 지금은 사람이 타고 있기 때문이다. 사람이 자기를 비우고 세상을 살아간다면 누가 그를 해칠 수 있겠는가?" - <장자>, 산목편

方舟而濟於河, 有虛船來觸舟, 雖有?心之人不怒., 有一人在其上, 則呼張?之., 一呼而不聞, 再呼而不聞, 於是三呼邪, 則必以惡聲隨之. 向也不怒而今也怒, 向也虛而今也實. 人能虛己以遊世, 其孰能害之!


===

나는 살아오면서 남과 부딪치기를 두려워했다. 부딪치면 내가 상할까 두려워서였다. 싸울 줄도 모른다. 어릴 때부터 어머니가 말씀하셨다. “지는 것이 이기는 것이다.” 그 가르침을 명심하고 복종했기 보다 그 가르침을 핑계와 위안으로 삼아 시비꺼리를 피하며 살려 했다. 그러나 늘 그랬던 것은 아니다. 내가 강을 건너려 할 때 나의 흐름을 가로막는 배가 있으면 속이 상하고, 참다못해 그냥 콱 부딪쳐버리고 싶었다. 얕은 자존심으로 나중에 후회할 말은 내뱉어 상대의 마음을 상하게도 했다. 돌아서서는 다시는 그러지 말아야지 자책하기도 했다. 그런데 그게 잘 되지 않았다.

내 자신이 빈 배(虛船)가 된다는 것. 자기를 비운다는 것(虛己).
그것은 무엇일까? 마음에 걱정도 없고 격정도 없고 미움도 없고 욕망도 없는 ‘아파테이아(apatheia)’의 상태를 말하는 건가? 아님, 자존과 아집을 비운다는 건가?
나를 비울 때 이웃을 담을 수 있고 나그네를 실어 나를 수 있는 포용과 사랑을 실천할 수 있을터인데 어느 만큼 수양되어야 그렇게 될까? 적어도 나의 얕은 자존심으로 먼저 남을 상하게 하지 말아야겠다. 그저 바라는 것이 있다면 허물이 적고자 할 따름이다.


몇 해전 수업시간이다. 동양윤리사상 ‘장자(莊子)’를 학습하는 시간에 ‘제물론’과 ‘물아일체’를 학습하고 나아가 ‘호접지몽(호랑나비 꿈)’이며, ‘무용지용(無用之用)’을 덧붙이고 ‘빈배가 되라’는 이야기로 끝을 맺었다. 평소 밥 많이 먹는 예쁜 꽃분이는 수업 중에 잠들어 있었다. 깨워 물었다.

“ ‘빈 배가 되라’했는데 이게 무슨 말이고?”

잠시 생각에 잠겼다가 쑥스러운 작은 목소리로 꽃분이는 답한다.

“밥, 적게 먹어라?........”


사랑스럽고 귀여운 제자다. 지금은 멋진 아가씨가 되었을 것이다.

The Empty Boat (1): Talks on the Sayings of Chuang Tzu

Amazon.com: Customer reviews: The Empty Boat: Talks on the Sayings of Chuang Tzu



The Empty Boat: Talks on the Sayings of Chuang Tzu 
Hardcover – January 1, 1995
by Osho (Author), K. Prabhu (Editor)
5.0 out of 5 stars (5.0) 4 ratings

Hardcover
$37.57
10 Used from $25.361 New from $50.001 Collectible from $86.75


Print length

318 pages

Product details
Publisher ‏ : ‎ Rajneesh Foundation Intl; 2nd edition (January 1, 1995)
Language ‏ : ‎ English
Hardcover ‏ : ‎ 318 pages






The Empty Boat: Talks on the Sayings of Chuang Tzu›Customer reviews
Customer reviews
5.0 out of 5 stars


4 total ratings, 3 with reviews
From the United States
Lillian Yam
5.0 out of 5 stars The Empty Boat -- Leads a journey to purified mind
Reviewed in the United States on January 15, 2000
Since the first time I read books on the sayings of Chuang Tzu, its philosophy has amused me. But not until I read this book, I find the way to practice it in everyday's life. It is a guideline for dealing with daily chores in my life, for searching the soul, and reminds me the essential object of my pursuit--to live, to love, and go back to my nature and to be myself. Easily getting lost in illusions of the material world, it is a book that helps me to understand the true happiness in life. I hope others will enjoy and benefit from reading this book too.
12 people found this helpful
Helpful
Report
D. Lane
5.0 out of 5 stars A practical and thoroughly inspiring account
Reviewed in the United States on June 17, 1999
This book delights in every possible way, it should not be a book to rest on the shelves gathering dust, but one to be perused through as the mood fits. This book inspired me greatly and I have the utmost respect for the authors understanding and commentary on the text. Beautifully demonstrative of the problems mankind faces in a world of stress and worry, Osho presents pearls of wisdom to delight the experienced reader and inexperienced alike. This book should seriously be considered by all especially as it has been out of print for some time, now just recently been reprinted.
14 people found this helpful
Helpful
Report
From other countries
Shammi
5.0 out of 5 stars Fantastic book
Reviewed in the United Kingdom on August 31, 2018
Verified Purchase
Absolutely stunning on every page. This book should be required reading at school.
Report

Sponsored 
Need customer service? Click here
‹ See all details 
===





The Empty Boat: Talks on the Sayings of Chuang Tzu


Osho, K. Prabhu (Editor)

4.16
465 ratings39 reviews


Rate this book
How can words convey a message which is wordless? What can be said about an enlightened master? The essence of the message beyond words is paradox, and Osho and Chuang Tzu ask us to accept paradox, set aside mind and logic, and become empty. Only when empty of our conditionings, ideas and expectations - our egos - can their enlightenment become our own. Chuang Tzu millennia ago, and Osho today, conspire to make us nobodies, empty vessels who can receive the wordless, the eternal, which they embody. In these discourses Osho makes obvious that in our present state of being/doing, there is no room for the wordless to enter us and rest. It is there waiting for empty space in us; preoccupations, plans, close the door and we miss it But any effort to attain this emptiness reveals the paradox—effort and ambitions build ego and doom us to ultimate failure. So what can we do? Osho tells us there is nothing to be done, all doing is of the ego. But we can be in a state of receptivity, we can be open and accepting of existence. Bypass the critical mind and his words sink into us, deep into us, and we become like empty boats. To ponder over the words, their meanings, is the road to confusion. Osho uses contradiction as a technique and through it addresses all types of personality. He knows every quirk and twist of the ego, every trick of the mind; he is many jumps ahead. Osho is not trying to turn us into slaves of his rules, he is not our enemy. He has so much love for our monkeyish nature that his whole effort is to help us to become aware of our enslavements, not more adjusted to them. He shocks, jolts us from our comfortable cages, so that through understanding and awareness we can transcend them.

GenresSpiritualityPhilosophyNonfictionTaoism



318 pages, Hardcover


First published January 1, 2013
Book details & editions


Osho3,181 books6,011 followers

Follow



Rajneesh (born Chandra Mohan Jain, 11 December 1931 – 19 January 1990) and latter rebranded as Osho was leader of the Rajneesh movement. During his lifetime he was viewed as a controversial new religious movement leader and mystic.

In the 1960s he traveled throughout India as a public speaker and was a vocal critic of socialism, Mahatma Gandhi, and Hindu religious orthodoxy.

Rajneesh emphasized the importance of meditation, mindfulness, love, celebration, courage, creativity and humor—qualities that he viewed as being suppressed by adherence to static belief systems, religious tradition and socialization.

In advocating a more open attitude to human sexuality he caused controversy in India during the late 1960s and became known as "the sex guru".

In 1970, Rajneesh spent time in Mumbai initiating followers known as "neo-sannyasins". During this period he expanded his spiritual teachings and commented extensively in discourses on the writings of religious traditions, mystics, and philosophers from around the world. In 1974 Rajneesh relocated to Pune, where an ashram was established and a variety of therapies, incorporating methods first developed by the Human Potential Movement, were offered to a growing Western following. By the late 1970s, the tension between the ruling Janata Party government of Morarji Desai and the movement led to a curbing of the ashram's development and a back taxes claim estimated at $5 million.

In 1981, the Rajneesh movement's efforts refocused on activities in the United States and Rajneesh relocated to a facility known as Rajneeshpuram in Wasco County, Oregon. Almost immediately the movement ran into conflict with county residents and the state government, and a succession of legal battles concerning the ashram's construction and continued development curtailed its success.

In 1985, in the wake of a series of serious crimes by his followers, including a mass food poisoning attack with Salmonella bacteria and an aborted assassination plot to murder U.S. Attorney Charles H. Turner, Rajneesh alleged that his personal secretary Ma Anand Sheela and her close supporters had been responsible. He was later deported from the United States in accordance with an Alford plea bargain.[

After his deportation, 21 countries denied him entry. He ultimately returned to India and a revived Pune ashram, where he died in 1990. Rajneesh's ashram, now known as OSHO International Meditation Resort and all associated intellectual property, is managed by the Zurich registered Osho International Foundation (formerly Rajneesh International Foundation). Rajneesh's teachings have had a notable impact on Western New Age thought, and their popularity has increased markedly since his death.




Community Reviews

4.16
465 ratings39 reviews
5 stars

228 (49%)
4 stars

134 (28%)
3 stars

67 (14%)
2 stars

23 (4%)
1 star

13 (2%)
Search review text

Filters

Displaying 1 - 10 of 39 reviews


Waleed bin Khamis
53 reviews · 12 followers

Follow
August 23, 2014
I have read a lot of Osho's name on the Internet and on the shelves of libraries, but I have never read anything about him or about him. This is the first time that I got to know him and his philosophy and principles, so I can say that I started reading the book "The Empty Boat" without prejudice, neither about the book nor And God knows that while I was reading the book, I tried to remain open to his ideas as much as I could and not to judge until I finished reading. As for having finished reading the book, I can say with a clear conscience that this book is a bit of wisdom and a lot of empty talk.

The book is divided into 11 chapters in which Osho explains the sayings of "Zhiguan Tzi" or "Lao-tse", who is one of the wise men of the Taoist faith in China. I do not agree with many of the ideas included in the book, but I find them a pure invitation to madness. Osho says in the first chapter of his book, “Be nobody so that you can enjoy spiritual happiness.” This is the main idea around which the book revolves, but when I am nobody, what is the meaning of happiness ? How can I be happy when I am nobody? Moreover, we did not only create spirits, and this contradiction between the spirit that yearns for the sky and the body clinging to the earth is what makes man a human being, and the human ability to balance between them is true happiness. I'm not totally against spiritual sciences, but I don't like this exaggeration in dealing with them, just as I don't like their antithesis, "material philosophy."

11 likes
Like
Comment




sanjay gautam
222 reviews · 441 followers

Follow
August 5, 2014
Its a sequel (i.e volume 2) to the book 'when the shoe fits foot is forgotten'.
Its one of the best books by osho. Its philosophy is life changing and is very simple. Worth a read.


8 likes
1 comment
Like
Comment



Mannwy
107 reviews · 5 followers

Follow
May 26, 2014
The book is about the sayings of the wise Chagwan Tszi
interpreted and explained by Osho.
It revolves around the aiju and how to get rid of

the sayings. If I collect them, they will come to three pages with a lot. They explained them in three and sixty pages. His
explanation is spiritual, very beautiful.

I wish he was a Muslim and interpreted the Qur’an

5 likes
Like
Comment



Keyur
2 reviews

Follow
December 7, 2009
Read it long back. The most impressive lesson I remember from this book is

“If a man is crossing a river and an empty boat collides with his own skiff, even though he be a bad-tempered man he will not become very angry. But if he sees a man in the boat, he will shout at him to steer clear. If the shout is not heard, he will shout again, and yet again, and begin cursing. And all because there is somebody in the boat. Yet if the boat were empty, he would not be shouting, and not angry. If you can empty your own boat crossing the river of the world, no one will oppose you, no one will seek to harm you…. Who can free himself from achievement, and from fame, descend and be lost amid the masses of men? He will flow like Tao, unseen, he will go about like Life itself with no name and no home. Simple is he, without distinction. To all appearances he is a fool. His steps leave no trace. He has no power. He achieves nothing, has no reputation. Since he judges no one, no one judges him. Such is the perfect man: His boat is empty.”

4 likes
Like
Comment



Luji
2 reviews · 3 followers

Follow
June 2, 2017
The empty boat is a journey that you must make sure that you are fully prepared before embarking on it.
The book is very deep..to the extent that I spent nearly a month on it.
Each chapter has to sit after a contemplative session to realize how very real
Osho is. I talked about him, and talking about him became like talking about forbidden things,
but when I sat with him.. In every chapter, I was impressed by his difference and the depth of his faith, so that the reader would imagine at first sight that he was crazy. In
the book, Osho talked about the Rubaiyat of the mystic Omar Khayyam, and how he was accused of immorality when he talked about drunkenness and love But what he meant when he talked about intoxication is the divine intoxication and the eternal embrace with God,
and Osho talked about Lao Tsri and Tshuan Tzi and how they made their lives pure consciousness when they got rid of all material things and decided with courage to be useless
Osho speaks in the language of light and gratitude..Listen to what is behind the phrases and words.
Do not take them literally..because you will drown.
I knew that the Illuminati talk about embracing and love as an expression of their love for God.
They talk about intoxication..not the intoxication of wine, but the divine intoxication and eternal embrace with God.
Osho clearly True religiosity begins when you listen well..when you decide to get rid of all materialism and apparent turmoil.
Osho explains that there is no prayer in the presence of words.
We are full of chatter.
When you listen well and thoughts stop and become filled with you, you will pray the first real prayer
. In philosophy and everything that the father of philosophers Socrates
Osho says, he sees that philosophers and rationalists are the ones who made us live in illusion and miss the aesthetics of life.
When we ask about everything, we lose pleasure and faith.
Osho teaches us how to find God within us and not in temples.
How do we live spontaneously .. How everything is perfect and should go in the way that
Osho is going to call for a return to instinct, love and tolerance
Osho is very honest, I am not impressed by the misunderstanding of many and their arguments about him
because his honesty is contagious as soon as you read it until it is filled with light and you look For life with a new perspective
and get rid of deceiving yourself for yourself and for life
Osho invites you to get rid of everything that is fake and unreal.
Osho calls for unconditional love.. to get rid of formalities in relationships
for free love and get rid of restrictions


. I repeat, do not read the book if you are not ready,
and I repeat, read behind Phrases and words and do not take them literally


3 likes
Like
Comment




dr. Kashmira Gohil
3 books · 19 followers

Follow
August 3, 2020
This is one of the gems from Osho, on saying of Ancient Mystic, Chuang Tzu, explaining beautifully, the importance of 'just being' without harbouring any attachments under happiness, sadness, anger, greed or such. The actual Life is in this present moment, not in past or future, was stated beautifully with various epitaphs as 'The toast is burnt', 'the empty boat', 'when Fish is caught, the trap is forgotten' and such. When you read Osho, it's mostly 4 or 5, nothing less; from one of the greatest mystic who walked on this earth in 90s. His talks are relevant even today & I think, it would be in any future. When you read his thoughts as transcribed in his books, you can't but agree to his thoughts, reflections and visions, such is the power of his talks.4 stars.

2 likes
3 comments
Like
Comment



Bhakta Kishor
286 reviews · 37 followers

Follow
November 29, 2020
Nothingness is the fragrance of the beyond. It is the opening of the heart to the transcendental. It is the unfoldment of the one-thousand-petaled lotus. It is man’s destiny. Man is complete only when he has come to this fragrance, when he has come to this absolute nothingness inside his being, when this nothingness has spread all over him, when he is just a pure sky, unclouded.

This nothingness is what Buddha calls nirvana. First we have to understand what this nothingness actually is, because it is not just empty – it is full, it is overflowing. Never for a single moment think that nothingness is a negative state, an absence, no. Nothingness is simply no-thingness. Things disappear, only the ultimate substance remains. Forms disappear, only the formless remains. Definitions disappear, the undefined remains.

So, nothingness is not as if there is nothing. It simply means there is no possibility of defining what is there. It is as if you move all the furniture from your house outside. Somebody comes in and he says, “Now, here is nothing.” He had seen the furniture before; now the furniture is missing and he says, “Here there is no longer anything. Nothing is.” His statement is valid only to a certain extent. In fact, when you remove the furniture, you simply remove obstructions in the space of the house. Now, only pure space exists, now nothing obstructs. Now there is no cloud roaming in the sky; it is just a sky. It is not just nothing, it is purity. It is not only absence, it is a presence.

Have you ever been in an absolutely empty house? You will find that emptiness has a presence; it is very tangible, you can almost touch it. That’s the beauty of a temple or a church or a mosque – pure nothing, just empty. When you go into a temple, what surrounds you is nothingness. It is empty of everything, but not just empty. In that emptiness something is present – but only present for those who can feel it, who are sensitive enough to feel it, who are aware enough to see it. Those who can see only things will say, “What is there? Nothing.” Those who can see nothing will say, “All is here, because nothing is here.”

The identity of “yes” and “no” is the secret of nothingness. Let me repeat it; it is very basic to Buddha’s approach: nothingness is not identical with no, nothingness is the identity of yes and no, where polarities are no longer polarities, where opposites are no longer opposites.

☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸☸
osho spiritual
2 likes
Like
Comment



Huyen Trang
155 reviews · 51 followers

Follow
Currently readingFebruary 17, 2021
Reading this book made me fall asleep easily. Therefore, the book is thin, but I can't finish reading it. After reading a bit, I fell asleep

1 like
Like
Comment



Edward III
22 reviews · 2 followers

Follow
August 17, 2013
Taoism from the perspective of a Buddhist.

Well, he is not strictly a Buddhist, but that is the impression I got while reading. I just finished this book yesterday and I thought it was good, but not amazing. This is a transcription of talks given by the author in 1974, and in giving his talks he does provide some genuinely valuable insights in to the parables of Chuang Tzu, Taoism and life in general. I found the 8th chapter ("The Useless") to be excellent, describing what might be called "existence-in-contradistinction", or the idea that for anything to exist, it must be set in opposition to or against something else.

However throughout this book I couldn't help but feel that what we get is not wholly in the spirit of Taoism, but rather what the author selectively wants to impart from Taoism, to the exclusion of other things. This world is often deprecated as being unreal, secondary or of no real importance; a sentiment not to be found in great degree in the primary sources of Taoism. The self takes a serious beating as well... but then again the title of the book is "The Empty Boat", named after a Chuang Tzu story which suggests that the source of blame is personal identity. Lastly the author fictionalizes stories about historical figures (as an avid student of the ancient Cynics of Greece, I can tell you that most details he gives about the meeting of Alexander and Diogenes of Sinope are patently false) in order to reinforce his point.

Perhaps I am being overly critical. This book is worth reading, for there are many gems of philosophical insight to be found within it, but just make sure you have read Chuang Tzu for yourself before approaching it. Reading this book I felt like looking at a picture of "The Vinegar Tasters" and seeing the words of Lao Tzu coming out of Buddha's mouth.

1 like
Like
Comment




Tareq Ghanem
177 reviews · 13 followers

Follow
August 24, 2014
Osho is a Hindu thinker who became famous, especially in European circles in our time. The book is written in a smooth style, the ideas are clear, and the multiplicity of stories in it increases the pleasure of reading and reduces the dryness of philosophy. Why, if I rate the book with one star? For the thought of the book and the writer with whom I cannot approach or be satisfied. With some of its content, the idea of ​​the book is an embodiment of the Hindu religion that does not believe in heaven, fire, judgment, or a day of religion, even if it believes in a God who is the creator of the universe. Salvation in the Christian faith is by believing that God sacrificed his son to atone for Adam’s sin. Salvation in Judaism is only for the Jews of God’s children. Salvation is in Islam by following what the Prophet Muhammad came with. The three religions make there a day of judgment. Either bliss is in heaven or hell in hell. As for what Osho philosophizes for us about his Hindu faith, your salvation will only be if you melt yourself and unite in the divine self, and that is by your fading away. About yourself by devoting yourself, stop. The last phrase of self-dedication does not mean asceticism, for example!!!No, then a thousand no, so your asceticism is existence, and what you strive for is annihilation. In short, you see yourself. Excuse me. You see yourself, that is, that you do not become anything, that is, that you perish in the Divine Self, and thus your salvation is achieved through Nirvana.

1 like
2 comments
Like
Comment

Show previous reviews
Profile Image for Khalid.
Khalid
11 reviews


Follow
March 22, 2016
I used to feel sad when I was about to finish it,
and I used to get high with happiness after every reading session


1 like


2 comments


Like


Comment




Profile Image for Mariam Zaman.
Mariam Zaman
10 reviews · 20 followers


Follow
February 28, 2020
It was a required read, not a fan of Osho


1 like


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Abdullah Al-Masry.
Abdullah Al-Masry
44 reviews · 22 followers


Follow
March 26, 2020
The second book Osho! ⁣
Is
he a human demon? I don't know, maybe since watching part of his episodes on the netflix platform, the wild wild west program, I hated him, even though I know the extent of his influence on people. For him, I read a book for him called (The Empty Boat) before I got into the idea of ​​the book as a specialist in neuro-linguistic programming. I found that it is the way Osho talks and his books use methods and tricks to convince people, including that it hurts that I was like you and I was lost to build intellectual cohesion and broadcast his ideas to them. He spoke with this book that
we We should not be anyone!
Meaning, as soon as we prove ourselves and show the world who we are or what we have, we fall into problems like all prophets, thinkers, and philosophers, meaning that we should not be present too much, because if we exist, we will cause anxiety or feelings of jealousy for those around us. ⁣
_
He attacked philosophy, knowing that he has a master’s degree in philosophy, where he says that philosophy begins with the question (why) and here the problem begins. He also attacked thinking that it has no benefit. We must enjoy the present moment only and move away from planning. ⁣ He talked about the importance of honesty and love in
relationships
without Masks, and attacked development professors that they teach people to lie to gain friends and benefit instead of the true feeling of love to win friends. ⁣

Attack the old habits and thought, where the glory of living in the present moment and indifference ⁣


From my point of view, it is like a snake, but it is full of poison!⁣


Like


Comment


Profile Image for X.
X
1 review


Follow
Read
October 6, 2019
No, it is not a call to be nothing, but rather a call to be everything.
No, you are not required to leave your life, but rather you are required to leave your idea of ​​this life.


Osho, as I read it, invites us to leave the prison of the mind and ideas, because they always falsify what we live in terms of love, friendship, and condemnation, because when we are actually present at the present moment for these things, we do not think about them or spoil them with interpretations, and because when we stop worshiping heaven and hell, Our worship is no longer politics, and because when we are in the middle, we are more real. The middle is beautiful. The middle means not taking sides with only one of you.
And because when you really love, you are inside the subject of love and not outside it, you look at it and think about it, and the same is true with life. We will not get it once in its entirety inside our heads, and for this we stopped thinking about it and its possibilities. Living it really means that it really exists.


I am not saying that everything Osho said here must be acted upon, but it crushes meditation, rather it is an invitation to meditation. 💡


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Doctor.
Doctor
82 reviews


Follow
December 16, 2022
Good leisure time reading, when you are utterly depressed and your mind feels numb. If you want to feel something, this book is for you, or the whole work of Osho is available for you.


There are lots of sermons in way of jokes, anecdotes, philosophy and facts. The language is so simple that your mind will do only one thing: read. Without getting troubled with comprehension or difficult words. All is simple and plain. Perfect for reading when you are depressed. As Osho says over and over, don't read to acquire, just read for the joy of reading.
osho


Like


Comment




Profile Image for Annetlvre.
Annetlvre
1 review


Follow
November 14, 2021
To be honest, I was expecting something completely different.
I can neither call it bad nor good, because it totally depends on your personality and thoughts.


Well, reading books like these certainly help you understand different life perspectives, but in my opinion you become more uncertain about yourself and your actions.


The author warns us that we will be lost and transformed into nothingness, but perhaps that is what became the beginning of everything.


In the end, I am satisfied.


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Cian Kenshin.
Cian Kenshin
22 reviews · 14 followers


Follow
February 1, 2018
He deciphers the cryptic Tao. What is the meaning of a boat being empty? Every page is filled with little stories and metaphors used to conceptualize the non-conceptual. It's very accessible for beginners as well as has hidden gems for the more advanced.


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Abdullah Almuslem.
Abdullah Almuslem
393 reviews · 39 followers


Follow
March 18, 2018
The eastern philosophy that came from this Indian man is strange and naive at times.. I did not understand how this man had so many followers... I do
not think that what came in this book represents eastern philosophy!!


I do not recommend the book!


Like


Comment


Nsns2hotmail.com
13 reviews


Follow
July 17, 2017
One of the best Osho books I've read


Like


Comment




Profile Image for Sushanti Madkaikar.
Sushant Madkaikar
19 reviews


Follow
December 4, 2017
nice.. part 2 of shoe fits


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Nicemon Joseph.
Nicemon Joseph
1 review


Follow
December 9, 2017
Worth reading, surely the best work of Osho


Like


Comment


You can escape
2 reviews


Follow
January 12, 2019
One of the books that changed your outlook on life


Like


Comment


Francis
4 reviews


Follow
May 1, 2020
Very deep book, a great philosophy of life, for those who follow the real path to enlighment.


Like


Comment


Davit Berishvili
20 reviews · 1 follower


Follow
March 4, 2021
You are not because no one needs you and no one needs you, you are an empty boat and you go with the flow.


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Norah Alohali.
Norah Alohali
126 reviews · 52 followers


Follow
December 26, 2021
The empty book


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Ngocblack.
Ngocblack
8 reviews


Follow
February 15, 2023
I am so lucky to have read this book.


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Samar al-Qalb.
Samar heart
66 reviews · 3 followers


Follow
April 10, 2023
I think the book is a brain storm that conveys to you the idea that you do not choose, even if you choose one outcome, and that you exhaust yourself by thinking and planning for me. There are
many objections to some of what it says due to the difference in belief.


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Mihai Pintilie.
Mihai Pintilie
77 reviews · 17 followers


Follow
Read
June 9, 2016
- Tai's notes


Procrastinating stems for fear


Understand that the world doesn't care about your embarrassment the only person is you


The sea is merciless like the world


The posted 92 tips on improving your social skills
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=S6heT...


The more you manifest an emotion say worry or success the more you will train ur mind that its rare and you will not feel worthy of it - de la Claudiu


People have stupid fears don t carry fears like embarrassment and stuff like that cheating.. Someone will cheat.. The real fears are time, death, a world war, someone dying


Only learn how to think from expert the very best
The regret minimization technique


Show more
1-b-mindset


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Dhivya Sridharan.
Dhivya Sridharan
11 reviews


Follow
June 2, 2021
The toast is not burnt..
The Empty boat - Perception changing book. Neither good nor bad is our doing for the boat is empty. If we don't hold too much on ourselves, we can take things on a lighter note.
Chuang Tzu's stories guide us through - to live without choices, how faith and trust are beyond self, goodness of uselessness to list a few. Big book good read.


Like


Comment


Denise Seifert
3 reviews · 4 followers


Follow
February 25, 2019
I expected more, maybe the book didn't talk directly to me and that's why it didn't make as much sense to me, or maybe it's not as good as others I've read, but I really expected more.


Like


Comment


@KawtharSalman_
26 reviews · 3 followers


Follow
October 1, 2019
Love exists, but lovers do not exist. In true love, love remains and lovers disappear, but thinking appears to say “I am in love, I love you.” When the “ego” appears, suspicion begins to influence, divisions are born, and love disappears.


Like


Comment


Raghad Amir
20 reviews · 22 followers


Follow
May 7, 2022
I think Osho is morally wronged for two reasons. The first is that everything he wrote is translated, and translation may often lack meaning. The other reason is that what he says is not science! And our world now only understands science and logic..
As for Osho, his goal is only to show you what is beyond logic and beyond science. So enjoy and listen if you want


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Sarah-jane Lowes.
Sarah-jane Lowes
16 reviews · 3 followers


Follow
October 7, 2012
wow


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Fauzia Rizvi.
Fauzia Rizvi
19 reviews · 1 follower


Follow
Read
May 11, 2013
Currently reading it now .... Loving every word!!


Like


Comment


Zahraa
157 reviews · 14 followers


Follow
Read
October 30, 2013
The translation to Arabic lost a lot of value of the book
:"(


Like


Comment


Profile Image for ....
...
103 reviews · 22 followers


Follow
December 5, 2014
I think that every person looking for something in himself and always wondering will find great benefit in Osho's writings


Like


Comment


Ihsan Almesber
1 review · 1 follower


Follow
Read
January 23, 2016
I would love to read this book and the books you offer, and I do not know how to carry the book. Please help


1 comment


Like


Comment


Profile Image for Samarth Yadav.
Samarth Yadav
3 reviews


Follow
June 17, 2021
Great Read.


Must read for meditators.


Like


Comment


Well
17 reviews · 14 followers


Follow
September 12, 2008
title


Like


Comment


39 results