Showing posts with label Toshihiko Izutsu. Show all posts
Showing posts with label Toshihiko Izutsu. Show all posts

2022/05/05

Wakamatsu on Izutsu's "Consciousness" and "Essence" 와카마츠 에이스케

Wakamatsu Eisuke 와카마츠 에이스케

Toshihiko Izutsu and the Philosophy of Word: In Search of the Spiritual Orient  

【목차】 
머리말 
제1장 『신비 철학』――시인 철학자의 탄생 
제2장 이슬람과의 邂逅 
제3장 러시아, 밤의 영성 
제4장 한 동시대인과 선지자 전
제5장 카톨리시즘
제6장 말과 코토바 
제7장 천계의 번역자 
제8장 엘라노스—그분에서의 대화 
제9장 <의식과 본질>
제10징 예지의 철학


Ch 9

Wakamatsu on 

Izutsu's "Consciousness" and "Essence"


sense Izutsu's audacity in tracing back the unbroken history of Western
philosophy to its starting point and attempting to break through
"synchronically" to that point in time.

Insofar as it grapples with problems not just in the present but sub
specie deternitatis, synchronic activity is never complete. As Izutsu him-
self stated in the preface to Ishiki to honshitsu, what he had undertaken
was only a "prolegomenon"; he understood from the outset that it would
be impossible to bring it to a successful conclusion.* 

What Izutsu wrote
may only have been a prolegomenon, but, as we frequently discover in
this outstanding work, it clearly states the basic issues.

"Consciousness" and "Essence"

In "Ishiki to honshitsu," the properties of the words "consciousness"
and "essence" themselves are different from the way we normally use
them. 

According to Izutsu, "consciousness" is inherently "ecstatic," a
comment he made in reference to a statement by Sartre in "Une idée
fondamentale de la phénoménologie de Husserl: l'intentionnalite"
(1939; "A Fundamental Idea of Husserl's Philosophy: Intentionality,'
2010). Izutsu never lost sight of the dictum that "consciousness is con-
sciousness of something.
* In the inseparability of ontology and theories of consciousness, Izutsu sees the contemporaneity and traditionalism of Sartre.

Datsuji (BA), a compound of characters that literally means "out
of oneself," is a key term for understanding "Ishiki to honshitsu." 
But if a reader were to keep on reading with only a superficial grasp of what
Izutsu means by "consciousness" and "essence," s/he will completely
lose the drift of Izutsu's argument when it begins to move dynamically.

"Consciousness," he writes, citing Sartre, is un glissement hors de soi,
"a sliding outside of itself."*? 
Awaiting "consciousness" on the outside is "essence": 
"consciousness" slides "outside of itself" toward "essence.

In this essay, neither "consciousness" nor "essence" is a static concept;
they both evolve "ecstatically."

Try looking up datsuji in a Japanese dictionary, and you won't find
it there. Although the first Japanese to use this word in a translation is
unknown, Shuzö Kuki used it at a very early date. 

We saw in Chapter Five that, inspired by Heidegger's Sein und Zeit (1927; Being and Time, 1962), he took note of ekstasis, the original meaning of datsuji, at quite an early date and developed it as part of his argument in his study of
time. After Propos sur le temps came out in France in 1928, he used
the espression datsuji in his essay "Keijijogakuteki jikan" (1931; Meta-
physical time), which was based on a lecture he gave on his return to
Japan.** Datsuji also appears in the first Japanese translation of Being
and Time, which was published in 1939.* and ever since then, it has
been accepted in Japanese philosophical circles as a technical term.
The role Kuki played in the development of Japanese philosophical
terminology and technical terms is worth noting. He was also the first
to use the expression jitsuzon (Jeff) for "existential."270

Izutsu began using the term datsuji regularly from the time of
Shimpi tetsugaku in 1949. It became a key word in that work along with
shinju (H *), which literally means "being filled with God," i.e. enthou-
siasmos. 
It is not certain, however, whether Izutsu used datsuji under
the influence of Heidegger. He was already reading Sartre by this time,
and his sense of datsuji seems nearer to Sartre's usage, i.e. as an expe-
rience in which language fails, which closely resembles the world of
Nausea. Sartre frequently deals with ek-stase in Being and Nothingness,
which Izutsu read after Naused. Being and Nothingness was written as
a response to Heidegger's Being and Time, and it was Kuki who made
Sartre aware of Heidegger's existence.

My aim in alluding to etymology here is not merely out of interest
in the associations connected with this word. The fact is that the philo-
sophical term datsuji term was born of, and fleshed out by, the "ecstatic
experiences of various thinkers and would become the impetus behind
the existential experiences of those who came after them. 

The words in the following sentences are Kuki's; they seem to describe what datsuji meant to him existentially.

 "Philosophy, I believe, is a primal understanding of existence in general." 
"We ought to feel surprise at the contingent fact itself that the real world exists. The abyss of some supersensible thing opens up there."* 

As we can see from these statements, the connection between Kuki and Izutsu goes beyond mere similarity.
In Shimpi tetsugaku, datsuji is acknowledged to be a translation of
the Greek word ekstasis. It signifies an existential experience in which
271

"the human self dies completely to its selfhood; the self is thoroughly
annihilated; the self is utterly destroyed until not even a single dust
mote of it remains."* If datsuji is "the annihilation of the relative self
as a sensible life principle." then shinja, which Izutsu annotates as
enthousiasmos, is "the occasion for a spiritual awakening of the abso-
lute self as a supersensible life principle" that accompanies eestasy
and occurs "immediately" with it.** Ekstasis is an instinctive breach-
ing of the restrictions of the phenomenal world such as self, time and
space, and an aspiration for the Other, eternity, a different dimension.
Enthousiasmos is the dispensation of Being, who reacts to it. There
is no interval between ekstasis and enthousiasmos. As Izutsu savs, the
experience of elstasis and enthousiasmos occurs on the same ontologi-
cal dimension as kensho (KLM), seeing one's true nature/self-awareness
in Buddhism, or to jan kuan l'ung (B*Fin), the enlightenment expe-
rience in Confucianism known as the "sudden breakthrough." Enthou-
siasmos, however, is not a special occurrence limited to mystics. Let
us, for convenience sake, call the one who does the filling up "God."
If enthousiasmos were an experience that occurs only under narrowly
prescribed conditions, it would fall under the vulgar definition of mys-
ticism, i.e. that the One who does the filling up only truly exists in a
chosen few. But "God" is omnipresent, or, rather, the Transcendent,
which is omnipresent, is "God." The way is open to all people.
If"consciousness" is "a sliding outside," "essence" is "a filling up.

The true nature of "essence" lies in giving fully and completely of
itself. It is the same as what the medieval Christian mustic Meister Eck-
hardt speaks of when he says that if one empties oneself and becomes
nothing, God will instantly fill that person up. If it were possible to
be truly "conscious" of "essence," it would be an experience of over-
flowing- even though we are profoundly incapable of recognizing this.
Likewise, "consciousness" always causes human beings to aspire to the
exact opposite of existential isolation.

What seems extremely important when reading "Ishiki to honshitsu'
is that Izutsu firmly roots, and develops the basis for, his speculations
in a sense of realism. He detested superficial views of mysticism. What
he asks of his readers is to observe in minute detail the commonsense
worldview that we experience every day and not to disavow it. 272 Rather, 
while leading his readers to the world's depths, he urges them to relurn
once again from this innermost region to the everyday world in which
we live. The following passage truly stales his intellectual attitude.
It is precisely in order to justify the coming into being of an
essence-free, articulated world that Buddhism sets forth the theory
of profitya-somutpada. But no matter how subtle this may be in
theor, in practice it is somehow not without its deficiencies. That is
because we have certain reactions to the things that we actually deal
with in the sensible world that cannot be explained br the theory of
pratitya-samutpada alone. 4

The meaning of the Buddhist theory of pratttva-samutpada (interdepen-
dent origination) is not the issue here. Where we ought to be looking
lies elsewhere. It is Izutsu's view that our starting point must never be
from theory; it is only through our "reactions" to the sensible world
that human beings can proceed to the depths of existence. He strongly
admonishes us against forgetting ordinary "emotional understandings
over specific ideologies or dogmas. Continning the previous sentence,
he writes, "Among the many schools of Mahayana Buddhism, it is
Zen, I believe, that in practice comes to grips with this issue head-on.
• Zen demands that each and every one of us confirms in practice
for ourselves that it is not an essence-initiated articulation of a solid
substance but an essence-free, Ruid, ontological articulation." Thie
point at which "each and every one of us confirms [this) in practice
for ourselves," Izutsu believes, is the starting point and also the goal of
ontological investigations.
All things are endowed with "essence" by "Being." the transcen-
dental Universal, and become "beings." What causes a cup to appear
before someone's eyes is the working of "Being," • but it is because that
person senses the "essence" of cup that s/he recognizes a "being" as a
cup. As we saw in the discussion of Nausea, "essence" is, as it were,
the covering that is indispensable for our understanding of "Being.
Rather than concealing something, it is the basic infrastructure that
makes human life what it is. Because "essences" exist. people are able
to recognize things, interact with other people and live their everyday
lives. "Essence" is the self-evident truth that "distinguishes a thing (a 
flower, for instance) from all other things and makes it what it indisput-
ably is."* Consequently, the same number of "essences" exist as there
are beings. Mountains, rivers, plants, flowers, valleys, lakes, oceans.
people-each has its own "essence." The world is partitioned off into
countless "essences." On the other hand. *essence" conforms to the
cultural framework within which it is generated; it is complexly inter-
twined with the multilayered consciousnesses of countless men and
women and precipitated out into history. A certain thing appears in
the sensible world as the result of the existential experience of a sage, a
mystic or a poet; it takes shape as art or philosophy or religion, etc., and
is passed on to other people.273

It is this unceasing activity of the human race that Toshihiko
Izutsu attempts to bring back to life in the present time through "syn-
chronic structuralization." This attempt is nothing less than laying the
groundwork for the self-manifestation of the Idea of Oriental spiritu-
ality, which has been dispersed among countless different cultures. It
resembles restoring a single book by bringing together scattered scraps
of paper. The "essence" that Izutsu is dealing with is not limited to
things; nor is it confined to visible, material existence. The principle
behind the generation of "essence" works the same way for invisible
concepts and spiritual realities. If it did not, "how could we explain
the overwhelming sense of reality in an esoteric Buddhist mandala,
which consists of images alone? Even the images that foat up in our
consciousness, Izutsu says, are "essences.

Although there have been many psychologists who have investi-
gated the reality of images, few have called them "essences" having
the same sense of reality as a single flower. If we regard the evil spirits
of mountains and rivers depicted in a mandala as nothing more than
symbols, Izutsu's study would probably make no sense. "It is, rather, the
things of what we call the real world that are merely shadow-like beings,
the shadows of shadows." he writes, referring to Suhrawardt's theory of
images. "The true weight of existence is in the 'metaphor.'* There
have been modern philosophers who treat images as real, but has there
ever been anyone like Izutsu who perceived them as "essences." the
ground of reality? In the view that the Tathagata and Bodhisattvas in
mandala are symbols and do not really exist, but are only "symbols."

CONSCIOUSNESS AND ESSENCE

Toshihiko Izutsu sees the embrittlement of the modern mind. A "sum-
bol., rather, is the passageway by which WORD manifests itself in the
phenomenal world. A "symbol" expressly indicates that behind it exists
an invisible something. It is the "metaphor" that is the reality, says
Izutsu. How is it possible to doubt the reality of Bodhisattvas? "They
materialize before our eyes and in the inner parts of ourselves. They
appear only to those who have eyes to see them."
After mandala, Izutsu deals with "archetypes. the world of images.
as part of his treatment of the reality of "essences."

" Though it is a study of archetypes, he does not discuss specific archetypes here such as what Jung calls anima, animus, the wise old man or the Great Mother.
Instead, the context in which Izutsu treats this technical term is the !
Ching. He sees that the process by which WORD expands itself and
gives birth to meaning is graphically found in the eight divination signs
of the I Ching, and notes that myths have been imprinted into each
of them. WORD is intrinsically latent in myth and poetry. Mythopoe-
sis, he argues, is not just a distinguishing feature of WORD, but rather
its fundamental characteristic and true nature. Myths are not merely
made-up stories. They are a form of self-manifestation by the Transcen.
dent. Human beings do not fabricate myths. Transcendental phenom-
ena choose the "archetypes" known as myths.

Archetypes are mental and spiritual patterns that, independently of
the individual unconscious, determine the ontological infrastructure of
a community or a culture. We can think of archetypes as analogous in
their function to what In 'Arab described as "permanent archetypes"
or "fixed entities" (a yan thabitah), which ontologically exist midway
between the Absolute and the world of sensible things." Izutsu counts
them as a kind of "essence" and recognizes their reality. Archetypes
are deeply connected to the "cultural framework" that fundamen-
tally ordains the depth structure of a person's consciousness, and they
achieve their unique development in a community. "In other words,
it is impossible for them [archetypes] to have universality in the sense
of surmounting regional and historical differences and being com-
mon to all ethnicities or to the human race as a whole."* "There is
no such thing as an "archetype endowed with a universality shared by
the entire human race. Both individual 'archetypes' and the systems in  
which they mutually materialize differ from culture to culture."* Ger-
shom Scholem once asked, "Why don't [Buddhists] see Christ or the
Madonna in their meditative visions?" Converscly, Izutsu asks, *
"Why don't images of Tathagata or Boddhisatvas or the various deities of the
Shingon mandala ever appear in the contemplative consciousness of
Christians?"* In contrast to the unity that, as we saw earlier, drew the
attention of the Traditionalist school, Izutsu tries to find meaning in
the differences among "essences.

In order to grasp the true nature of "consciousness," Izutsu believes,
"We must push on to the point at which consciousness goes beyond
the nature of consciousness, i.e. to the point at which consciousness
ceases to be consciousness."* The same logic is applied to the pursuit
of "essence."

* "Essence must be dealt with up to the point at which it separates from essentiality and ceases to be essence. At the instant that our "consciousness" perceives "essence,* * "Such and such a thing exists in it, a mountain or a river, for instance." Izutsu writes." If we accept this statement, then, if it were not for the fact that our depth consciousness grasps a thing, not only would we have no true sense of that thing's reality, the thing itself would not even exist. There are levels of consciousness. "Essence" changes shape depending on its position on the
ladder of consciousness. Or, it would be fair to say, Being appears in
response to consciousness.

The ultimate state of consciousness that Izutsu deals with here
is not the one that comprises the consciousness we personally expe-
rience, or the unconscious that psychoanalysis regards as a category.
Izutsu created the expression WORD (a * /S, kotoba) as a technical
term that transcends language and at times even signifies the Ultimate,
but, on one occasion only in "Ishiki to honshitsu." he wrote kokoro (a
a0, mind) as another name for it. "Used in this context, 'attachment'
(ushin, 18 0) and 'no-mind' (mushin, M0) are not synonyms. There is a
MIND in which 'attachment' and *no-mind each come into being on
different dimensions."* As this indicates, it is MIND that is the reality
in which "consciousness goes beyond the nature of consciousness," but
a full-scale treatment of this idea would have to await the discussion of
shin (C), the conscious Transcendent, in what would become his final 
book, Ishiki no keijijogaku: "Daijs kishinron" no tetsugaku (1903; Meta-
physics of consciousness: The philasophy of the Awakening of Faith in
the Mahayana)." "Being is WORD, Izutsu had said, summing up his
thought; he began to deal with the possibility that Being might also be
MIND.
276

In Oriental philesophy, cognition is a complex, multilayered inter-
weaving of consciousness and existence. Thus, in the process of pur-
suing the structure of this interweaving, human beings are inevitably
forced to confront the question of the reality of "essence."
This passage is found in what is virtually the last sentence of "Ishiki
to honshitsu." It is both a conclusion and a starting point. "Existence"
here is not "existents." It is another name for the absolutely Transcen-
dent, what In *Arabi calls "Being.

Izutsu was extremely cautious about using the technical term
"unconscious." which had rapidly become popular after the birth of
psychoanalysis. Or, rather, he seems to have regarded the careless use
of this word as almost taboo. It is not that he thought lightly of Freud
and Jung; indeed, he was someone who responded sensitively to the
contributions made by the founder of psychoanalysis and his heretical
successor and to the questions each had raised. But he had absolutely
no use for the false image of the "unconscious" that is prevalent today.
*Consciousness" is deep, broad and chaotic and defies theoretical con-
trol. All that human beings are permitted to do is to seriously observe
its dynamism and hypothesize about its structure; we experience only
a part of it. There should be no doubt about the reality of "conscious-
ness." but that does not mean there is a monster called the unconscious
lurking beneath it. The determinant "unconscious" is unnecessary:
"consciousness" is strange enough as it is.

Like a bottomless swamp, human consciousness is a weird thing, a
world where musterious matters dwell. No one really knows what lies
hidden in its depths. Nor can anvone predict what will suddenly rise
up from it 84

 
"Consciousness is assumed to have a two-layered structure, superficial
and deep." Izutsu writes.* but this distinction is merely for the sake of
convenience. It is not his intention to divide consciousness into two:
his aim is to endow the field that he calls the "middle space of con-
sciousness" - the "M-realm" or "M-region" - with structural reality.
Izutsu atterpts to lead the reader to this intermediary region that con
nects the surface-level of consciousness with its depths.

Diagram 1 is a structural model of consciousness in A
*Ishiki to honshitu.*** 


A is the surface consciousness; 
M, B and C indicate the realms of depth consciousness. 
The M of the M-realm is perhaps an abbreviation for "middle.'
or, considered as the field in which meaning is born,
it could conceivably stand for "meaning." This is also the location of the mundus
B imaginalis mentioned ear.

lier that Corbin described.
C
But, above all, we perhaps ought to detect the strong influence of Leo Weisger-
ber here. As we suw earlier, for Weisgerber, language
e
Diagrams: Structural model of consciousness
Source Ishiti to honshitu. IC6 1-4.

----

itself was nothing less than something situated "between" us and reality. Language determines the structure of culture. In other words, the sprachliche Zwischerwelt is also
a geistliche Zwischenwelt. Just as there are phenomena that exist only in
the mind, there are phenomena that exist only in particular languages,
as we saw in the case of the constellation Orion. For Japanese, a crow
is associated with ill-omened events, but, in the Old Testament, crows
are the companions of the prophet Elijah. Something similar probably
holds true for other symbols of good and bad fortune in everyday life.

But that does not mean that they ought to be regarded as nothing more
than symbolism. Conversely, since it is impossible for us to be free of
language and culture, we cannot readily escape from the world structure
they impose.278

Above and beyond being merely a theoretical hypothesis, the
M-realm was an existential region for Izutsu. "The theory of Ideas has
to be preceded by the experience of Ideas» -that statement in Shimpi
tetsugaku did not just apply to the true nature of Plato's Ideas alone:
it would be fair to think that this one sentence expressed Izutstt's own
article of faith: When dealing with basic issues, existential experience
always takes precedence. Indeed, it is a characteristic of Toshihiko
Izutsu that he would only delve deeply into what he had experienced
existentially.


The Mystic Philosophy of WORD

Even the word "meaning." when Toshihiko Izutsu uses it, becomes a
uniquely personal, technical term that is not limited to the denotative
content of a word, sentence or phenomena. "Meaning" is the appear-
ance of Being as it emerges from chaos; it is the "face" of beings. It is
individual entities, no two of which are alike.
Words are bodies of energy without any fixed form. It is not the case
that "meaning" is produced when a word comes into being; "mean-
ing" seeks words, Izutsu believes. In short, "meaning" is the matrix of
words, not the other way around. Izutsu perceives WORD as articu-
lating meaning. WORD is synonymous with "primal, absolute, unar-
ticulated reality,'
. the basis of all things.** In short, Izutsu believes that
WORD gives rise to all things. Our usual understanding is that a flower
exists, and so the word "Rower" is born. But Izutsu's statement con-
fronts us with a truth that is the exact opposite of this. If we take Izutsu
at his word, a flower is born after being formed in the "mold" of the
"meaning" of flower. In a world perceived by ordinary consciousness,
i.e. surface consciousness, things appear to be generated in the order
of phenomenon & word & meaning. A phenomenon comes first; words
and meaning follow. A word is a sign denoting a thing. Over time, the 
sign becomes endowed with meaning. If a phenomenon does not exist,
279


























2022/05/03

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism Directory

Directory of Draft Pages

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P3Part III - A Comparative Reflection

===
Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P2.Ch12XII Homo Politicus

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P2.Ch11XI The Perfect Man

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P2.Ch10X Absolute Reversai of Values

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P2.Ch09IX Determinism and Freedom

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P2.Ch08 VIII The Gateway of Myriad Wonders

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P2.Ch07 VII The Way

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P2.Ch06VI Against Essentialism

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P2.Ch05V The Birth of a New Ego

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P2.Ch04 IV Beyond This and That

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P2.Ch03III Dream and Reality

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P2.Ch02 II From Mythopoiesis to Metaphysics

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P2.Ch01 I Lao-Tzu and Chuang-Tzu

===

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch17XVII The Magical Power of the Perfect Man

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch16XVI Apostle, Prophet, and Saint

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch15XV The Perfect Man as an Individual

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch14 XIV Man as Microcosm

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch13 XIII Creation

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch12 XII Permanent Archetypes

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch11 XI The Self-manifestation of the Absolute

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch10 X The Water of Life

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch09 IX Ontological Mercy

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch08 VIII Allah and the Lord

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch07 VII The Divine Names

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch06 VI The Shadow of the Absolute

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch05 V Metaphysical Perplexity

Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P1.Ch04 IV Metaphysical Unification and Phenomenal Dispersion

===
Directory of Chapter Pages

====



Toshihiko Izutsu Sufism And Taoism P3Part III - A Comparative Reflection

SUFISM AND TAOISM: A Comparative Study of Key Philosophical Concepts

by Toshihiko Izutsu 1983

First published 1983 by Iwanami Shoten, Publishers, Tokyo
This edition is published by The University of California Press, 1984,
Rev. ed. of: A comparative study of the key philosophical concepts in Sufism and Taoism. 1966-67.

=====

Contents

Preface by T. Izutsu
Introduction

Part I - Ibn 'Arabi
1 Dream and Reality
II The Absolute in its Absoluteness
III The Self-knowledge of Man
IV Metaphysical Unification and Phenomenal Dispersion
V Metaphysical Perplexity
VI The Shadow of the Absolute
VII The Divine Nam es
VIII Allah and the Lord
IX Ontological Mercy
X The Water of Life
XI The Self-manifestation of the Absolute
XII Permanent Archetypes
XIII Creation
XIV Man as Microcosm
XV The Perfect Man as an Individual
XVI Apostle, Prophet, and Saint
XVII The Magical Power of the Perfect Man

Part II - Lao-Tzii & Chuang-Tzu

I Lao-Tzu and Chuang-Tzu
II From Mythopoiesis to Metaphysics
III Dream and Reality
IV Beyond This and That
V The Birth of a New Ego
VI Against Essentialism
VII The Way
VIII The Gateway of Myriad Wonders
IX Determinism and Freedom
X Absolute Reversai of Values
XI The Perfect Man
XII Homo Politicus

Part III - A Comparative Reflection 

I Methodological Preliminaries
II The Inner Transformation of Man
III The Multistratified Structure of Reality
IV Essence and Existence
V The Self-evolvement of Existence
===

Part 111
CONCLUSION
A Comparative Reflection

Methodological Preliminaries

As stated in the Introduction to Part One of this work, I started this

study prompted by the conviction that what Professor Henry Cor-
bin calls 'un dialogue dans la métahistoire' is something urgently

needed in the present world situation. For at no time in the history
of humanity has the need for mutual understanding among the
nations of the world been more keenly felt than in our days. 'Mutual
understanding' may be realizable - or at least conceivable - at a
number of different levels of life. The philosophical level is one of
the most important of them. And it is characteristic of the
philosophical level that, unlike other levels of human interest which
are more or less closely connected with the current situations and
actual conditions of the world, it provides or prepares a suitable
locus in which the 'mutual understanding' here in question could be

actualized in the form of a meta-historical dialogue. And meta-
historical dialogues, conducted methodically, will, I believe, event-
ually be crystallised into a philosophia perennis in the fullest sense

of the term. For the philosophical drive of the human Mind is,
regardless of ages, places and nations, ultimately and fundamentally
one.
I readily admit that the present work is far from even coming
close to this ideal. But at least such was the motive from which I
undertook this study. In the first Part, an attempt was made to lay
bare the fondamental philosophical structure of the world-view of
Ibn 'Arabi, one of the greatest mystic-philosophers. The analytic

work was done quite independently of any comparative considera-
tions. I simply tried to isolate and analyze as rigorously as possible

the major concepts that constitute the basis of Ibn 'Arabï' s

philosophical world-view in such a way that it might forma com-
pletely independent study.

The second Part dealing with Lao-tzii and Chaung-tzii is of a

slightly different nature. Of course it is in itself an equally indepen-
dent study of Taoist philosophy, which could very well be read as

such. But it is slightly different from the first Part in one point,
namely, that in isolating key-concepts and presenting them in a

470 Sufism and Taoism

systematic way, 1 already began preparations for the work of co-
ordination and comparison. By this 1 am not simply referring to the

fact that in the course of this work mention was made from time to
time of this or that part of Ibn' Arabi's thought. 1 am referring to
something more fondamental and of a more methodological nature.
1 have just spoken of the 'preparatory work for co-ordination and
comparison'. Concretely, this refers to the fact that 1 consciously
arranged and presented the whole matter in such a way that the very
analysis of the key-concepts of Taoism might bring to light the
common philosophical ground upon which the meta-historical
dialogue could become possible. Let this not be taken to mean that 1
modified the given material with a view to facilitating comparison,

let alone distorted the given facts, or forced something upon Lao-
tzu and Chuang-tzu for such a purpose. The fact is rather that an

objective analysis of Taoist key-terms naturally led me to the dis-
covery of a central idea which might work as the most basic connect-
ing link between the two systems of thought. The only arbitrary

thing 1 did - if 'arbitrary' it was - consisted in my having given a
philosophical 'name' to the central idea. The name is 'existence'.
And the name once established, 1 could characterize the guiding
spirit of the philosophical world-view of Lao-tzu and Chuang-tzu as

'existentialist' as opposed to the 'essentialist' tendency of the Con-
focian school.

1think1 have made it abundantly clear in the course of the second

Part that by understanding the philosophy of Lao-tzu and Chuang-
tzu in terms of 'existence', 1 have not arbitrarily forced upon them

anything alien to their thought. The only point is that the Taoist

sages themselves do not propose any definite 'name' for this particu-
lar idea, whereas Ibn 'Arabi has the word wujüd which is, histori-
cally as well as structurally, the exact Arabie expression for the same

idea. Certainly, Lao-tzu and Chuang-tzu do use the wordyu mean-
ing'being' or'existence' in contradistinction from wu 'non-beil)g' or

'non-existence'. But, as we have seen,yu in their system plays a very

special rôle which is different from that of 'existence' here in ques-
tion. The yu refers to a particular aspect or stage of the creative

activity of the Absolute, the stage at which the absolutely 'nameless'
Absolute definitely turns into the 'named' and begins to be
diversified into myriads of things.
Far better than yu in this respect is the word tao, the Way, which is
primarily an exact Taoist counterpart of the Islamic IJ,aqq, the Tru th
or Reality. But tao, to. begin with, is a word having an extremely
complex connotative structure. It covers an extensive semantic

field, ranging from the Mystery of Mysteries to the 'being-so-of-
itself' of all existents. Its meaning is, so to speak, tinged with

variegated nuances and charged with many associations. Certainly

Methodological Preliminaries 471
it does cover to a great extent the meaning of'existence'. But if used

as an equivalent of 'existence' it would inevitably add many ele-
ments to the basic meaning of 'existence'. The use of the term

'taoism', for example, instead of 'existentialism' in those contexts

where we want to bring out the radical contrast between the fonda-
mental position of Taoism and 'essentialism' - which by the way, is

an English equivalent chosen for the Confocian conception of
'names' (ming)-would make the whole situation more obscure and
confosing. In order to refer to the particular aspect of the tao in
which it is conceived as the actus purus, it is absolutely necessary

that we should have a far less 'colorfol' word than tao. And 'exist-
ence' is just the word for its purpose.

These considerations would seem to lead us to a very important
methodological problem regarding the possibility of meta-historical
dialogues. The problem concerns the need of a common linguistic
system. This is only natural because the very concept of 'dialogue'
presupposes the existence of a common language between two
interlocutors.
When our intention happens to be to establish a philosophical
dialogue between two thinkers belonging to one and the same
cultural and historical background, Plato and Aristotle, for
instance, or Thomas Aquinas and Duns Scotus, Kant and Hegel,
etc., the problem of the necessity of a common language does not of
course arise. The problem begins to make itself felt when we pickup
within a cultural tradition two thinkers separated one from the
other by a number of factors, like Aristotle and Kant, for example.
Each of them philosophized in a language which is different from
that of the other. There is, in this sense, no common language
between them. But in a broad sense, we can still say that there is a
common philosophical language between the two, because of the
strong tie of a common philosophical tradition that bind them

together inseparably. lt is, in fact, hardly imaginable that any key-
term of primary importance in Greek should not find its equivalent

in German.
The linguistic distance naturally becomes more conspicuous

when we want to establish a dialogue between two thinkers belong-
ing to two different cultural traditions, Avicenna and Thomas

Aquinas, for example. But even here we are still justified in recog-
nizing the existence of a common philosophical language in view of

the fact that in the last analysis they represent but two varieties of
scholastic philosophy, both of which ultimately go back to one and
the same Greek source. The concept of 'existence', for instance -in
the linguistic form of wujüd in Arabie and in that of existentia in
Latin - appears with the same basic connotation in both the Eastern

472 Sufism and Taoism
and Western scholastic traditions. Thus the problem of a common
language does not arise in a very acute form.

The problem does arise with real acuity where there is no histori-
cal connection in any sense whatsoever between the two thinkers.

And this is precisely the case with Ibn 'Arabï and Lao-tzii or
Chuang-tzu. In such a case, if there happens to be a central concept
active in both systems, but having its linguistic counterpart only in
one of the systems, we have to pinpoint the concept in the system in
which it is in astate of non-linguistic ftuidity or amorphousness, and
then stabilize it with a definite 'name'. The 'name' may be borrowed
from the other system, if the term actually in use in it happens to be a
really appropriate one. Or some other word may be chosen for the
purpose. In our particular case, Ibn' Arabï off ers the word wujüd,
which, in its translated form, 'existence' serves exactly our purpose,
because it does express the concept to be expressed in as simple a

manner as possible, that is, without 'coloring' it with special conno-
tations. The word remains connotatively colorless mainly due to the

fact that Ibn 'Arabi uses by preference a variety of other terms, like
tajallï, fay<J,, ral)mah, nafas, etc., in order to describe the same
concept with special connotations.

That we are not doing any injustice to the reality of the world-
view of the Taoist sages by applying the word 'existence' to the

central idea of their thought will be clear if one takes the trouble of
re-examining Chuang-tzii's description of the Cosmic Wind
together with the analytic interpretation of it which has been given
in Chapter VI.
However this may be, with the establishment of 'existence' as the
central concept of both systems, we are now in possession of a

common philosophical ground on which to establish a meta-
historical dialogue between Ibn' Arabï on the one hand and Lao-tzii

and Chuang-tzu on the other. With this in mind, let us review the
main points of the two philosophical systems which we have already
analyzed in detail in the preceding pages.
1 would like to point out at the outset that the philosophical
structure of both systems as a whole is dominated by the concept of
the Unity of Existence. This concept is expressed in Arabie by

wal)dah al-wujüd, literally the 'one-ness of existence'. For expres-
sing the same basic concept, Chuang-tzii, uses words like t'ien ni

'Heavenly Levelling' and t'ien chün 'Heavenly Equalization'.
The very words 'levelling' and equalization' clearly suggest that
the 'unity' in question is nota simple 'unity', but a 'unity' formed by
many different things. The idea, in brief, is this. There are actually

different things, but they are 'equalized' with each other, or 'level-
led down' to the state of 'unity', losing all their ontological distinc-
l' ' ' M ethodological Preliminaries 473 tions in the midst of the original metaphysical Chaos. More briefly stated, the 'unity' in question is a 'unity' of 'multiplicity'. The same is true of the 'wa}:tdah' of Ibn 'Arabï. In both these systems, the whole world of Being is represented as a kind of ontological tension between Unity and Multiplicity. Unity in the world-view of Ibn' Arabï is represented by }:taqq, 'Tru th' or 'Reality' while in that of Taoism it is represented by the tao, 'Way'. And Multiplicity is for Ibn' Arabi the mumkiniit 'possible beings', and for Lao-tzu and Chuang-tzu the wan wu, 'ten thousand things'. tajallï }:taqq mumkiniit shêng' tao wan wu And the relation between the two terms of the ontological tension is that of Unity. lt is a Unity because all the things that constitute Multiplicity are, after all, so many different phenomenal forms assumed by the Absolute (the Truth and the Way respectively). The phenomenal process by which the original One diversifies itself into Many is considered by Ibn' Arabi as the tajallï, 'self-manifestation' of the One, and by Lao-tzu and Chuang-tzu as shëng 'producing'. And Chuang-tzu, in particular, further elaborates this idea into that of the universal Transmutation, wu hua, lit. 'things-transforming'. Such is the broad conceptual framework which is shared by the world-views of Ibn' Arabi and the Taoist sages. The framework is in its entirety constructed on the most basic concept of 'existence'. In what follows we shall examine in terms of this framework and in tenns of this basic concept the major points of emphasis which characterize the two philosophical systems. Note 1. 1:., shêng: 'produces' or 'brings into existence'.

11 The lnner Transformation of Man

The philosophical world-view of the 'Unity of Multiplicity',
whether in the form of the 'Unity of Existence' or in the form of

'Heavenly Equalization', is an unusual - to say the least - world-
view. lt is an extraordinary world-view because it is a product of an

extraordinary vision of Existence as experienced by an extraordi-
nary man. The most characteristic point about this type of philos-
ophy is that philosophizing act starts from an immediate intuitive

grasp of Existence at its metaphysical depth, at the level of its being
the 'absolu te' Absolu te.
Existence - which has always and everywhere been the central
theme for innumerable philosophers - can be approached and
grasped at a number of different levels. The Aristotelian attitude
represents in this respect the exact opposite of the position taken by
the philosophers of Taoism and Sufism. For an Aristotle, Existence
means primarily the existence of individual 'things' on the concrete
lev el of phenomenal 'reality'. And his philosophizing starts from the
ordinary experience of Existence shared by all men on the level of
common sense. For an Ibn' Arabi or Chuang-tzu, however, these
'things' as experienced by an ordinary mind on the physical level are
nothing but a dream, or of a dreamlike nature. From their point of
view, the 'things' grasped on that level - although ultimately they
are but so many phenomenal forms of the Absolute, and are, as
such, no other than Existence - do not reveal the real metaphysical
depth of Existence. And an ontology based on such an experience
touches only shallowly the surface of the 'things'; it is not in a
position to account for the structure of the 'things' in terms of the
very ground of their Existence. A philosopher of this type is a man
standing on the level of the 'worldly mode of being' (nash'ah
dunyawïyah), in the terminology of Ibn Arabi. Such a man lacks the
'spiritual eyesight' ('ayn al-ba$ïrah) - or 'illuminating light' (ming)
as Chuang-tzu calls it - which is absolutely necessary for a deeper
penetration into the mystery of Existence. In order to obtain such

an eyesight, man must experience a spiritual rebirth and be trans-
ferred from the 'worldly mode of being' to the 'otherworldly mode

of being' (nash'ah ukhrawiyah ).

1 . . 1 .· The Inner Transformation of Man 475
Since the former is the way the majority of men naturally are,
men of the 'otherwordly mode of being' must necessarily appear as
'abnormal' men. The world-view of Taoism and Sufism represents
in this sense a vision of Existence peculiar to 'abnormal' men.

It is significant that the process by which this spiritual transforma-
tion occurs in man is described by Ibn' Arabi and Chuang-tzu, in

such a way that it discloses in both cases exactly the same basic
structure. Ibn 'Arabi describes it in terms of 'self-annihilation'
(fana'), and Chuang-tzu in terms of 'sitting in oblivion' (tso wang).
The very words used: 'annihilation' and 'forgeüing', clearly point to
one and the same conception. And the same underlying conception
is the 'purification of the Mind', or as Chuang-tzu calls it, the
spiritual 'fasting'.
As to what actually occurs in the process of 'purification', details
have been given in the first and second Parts of this book. And it
would be pointless to repeat the description here. The 'purification'
in both Taoism and Sufism consists, in brief, the man's purifying
himself of all desires as well as of the activity of Reason. lt consists,

in other words, in a complete nullification of the 'ego' as the empiri-
cal subject of all activities of Reason and desires. The nullification of

the empirical ego results in the actualization of a new Ego, the
Cosmic Ego, which, in the case of Taoism, is considered to be
completely at one with the Absolu te in its creative activity, and, in
the case of Ibn 'Arabi, is said to be unified with the Absolu te to the
utmost limit of possibility.
Perhaps the most interesting point concerning this topic from the

viewpoint of comparison is the problem of the 'stages' of the 'puri-
A comparative consideration is here the more interesting

because both Ibn' Arabi and Chuang-tzu distinguish in the process
three basic stages. The two systems differ from each other in details,
but agree with each other in the main.

Let us begin by recapitulating the thesis put forward by Chuang-
tzu. The first stage, according to him, consists in 'putting the world

outside the Mind', that is to say, forgetting the existence of the
objective world. The world as something 'objective' being by nature
relatively far from the Mind from the very beginning, it is relatively
easy for man to erase it from his consciousness through
contemplation.
The second stage consists in 'putting the things outside the Mind',
that is, erasing from consciousness the familiar things that surround
man in his daily life. At this stage, the external world completely
disappears from his consciousness.
The third stage is said to consist in man's forgetting Life, that is,
his own life or his persona! existence. The 'ego' is thereby corn-

476 Sufism and Taoism

pletely destroyed, and the world, both external and internai, disap-
pears from the consciousness. And as the 'ego' is nullified, the inner

eye of the man is opened and the light of 'illumination' suddenly
breaks through the darkness of spiritual night. This marks the birth
of a new Ego in man. He now finds himself in the Eternal Now,
beyond all limitation of time and space. He is also 'beyond Life and
Death', that is, he is 'one' with all things, and all things are unified
into 'one' in his 'no-consciousness'. In this spiritual state, an unusual
Tranquillity or Calmness reigns over everything. And in this cosmic
Tranquillity, away from the turmoil and agitation of the sensible
world, man enjoys being unified and identified with the very process
of the universal Transmutation of the ten thousand things.
Ibn 'Arabi who, as 1 have just said, also <livides the process into

three stages, provides a markedly Islamic version of spiritual 'puri-
fication'. The first stage is the' annihilation of the attributes'. At this

stage man has all his 'human' attributes nullified, and in their place
he assumes as his own the Divine Attributes.
The second stage consists in that man has his own persona!
'essence' nullified and realizes in himself his being one with the
Divine Essence. This is the completion of the phenomenon of

'self-annihilation' in the proper sense of the word. This stage cor-
responds to the first half of the third stage of Chuang-tzü, in which

the man is said to abandon his old 'ego'.
The third stage, according to Ibn' Arabi, is the stage at which man
regains his 'self' which he has 'annihilated' at the previous stage.
Only he does not regain his 'self' under the same conditions as
before, but rather in the very midst of the Divine Essence. This is
evidently but another way of saying that having abandoned his old
'ego' he has obtained a new Ego. Having lost his life, he has found a
new Life in being unified with the Divine Reality. In the technical
terminology of the Sufism, this is known as 'self-subsistence' (baqà').
This third stage corresponds to the latter half of the third stage

according to Chuang-tzü' s division of the process. Now man witnes-
ses all phenomenal things mingling with each other and merging

into the boundless ocean of Divine Life. His consciousness - or, to
be more exact, supra-consciousness -is in the utmost propinquity to
the Divine Consciousness in an ontological stage previous to its
actual splitting into an infinity of determinations and particular

forms. Naturally he falls into profound Silence, and an extraordi-
nary Tranquillity reigns over his concentrated Mind.

There is another important point to be mentioned in connection
with the problem of the 'purification' of the Mind. It concerns the

centripetal direction of the 'purification'. The process of 'self-
annihilation' or 'self-purification', if it is to succeed, must definitely

l ' ' '
,,
The Inner Transformation of Man 477

be turned and directed toward the innermost core of human exist-
ence. This direction clearly goes against the ordinary movements of

the Mind. The activity of the mind is usually characterized by its
centrifugai tendency. The Mind has a very marked natural tendency
to 'go out' toward the external world, attracted by, and in pursuit of,
external abjects. For the sake of 'purification', this natural tendency

must be curbed and turned to the opposite direction. The 'puri-
fication' is realizable only by man's 'turning into himself. This is

expressed by Ibn 'Arabi through the famous Tradition: 'He who
knows himself knows his Lord.' To this corresponds on the side of
Taoism the dictum of Lao-tzü: 'He who knows others (i.e., external
abjects) is a "clever" man, but he who knows himself is an
"illumined" man.' In reference to the same situation, Lao-tzü also
speaks of' closing up all the openings and doors'. 'Closing up all the
openings and doors' means obstructing all the possible outlets for
the centrifugai activity of the mind. What is aimed at thereby is
man's going down deep into his own mind until he cornes into direct
touch with the existential core of himself.
The reason why this point must be mentioned as being of special
importance is that such a thesis would appear at first sight to
contradict the more fondamental thesis of the Unity of Existence.
For in the world-view of both Ibn 'Arabi and the Taoist sages, not
only ourselves but all things in the world, without a single exception,
are phenomenal forms of the Absolute. And as such, there can be
no basic difference between them. All existents equally manifest,
each in its particular way and particular form, the Absolute. Why,
then, are the external things to be considered detrimental to the
subjective actualization of the Unity of Existence?
The answer is not far to seek. Although external things are so

many forms of the Absolute, and although we know this intellec-
tually, we cannot penetrate into them and experience from the

inside the palpitating Life of the Absolute as it is actively working
within them. Ali we are able to dois look at them from the outside.
Only in the case of our own selves, can each of us go into his 'inside'
and in-tuit the Absolute as something constantly at work within
himself. Only in this way can we subjectively participate in the
Mystery of Existence.

Besides, the centrifugai tendency of the mind is directly con-
nected with the discriminating activity of Reason. And Reason

cannot subsist without taking an 'essentialist' position. For where
there are no conceptual boundaries neatly established Reason is
utterly powerless. In the view of Reason, 'reality' consists of various
'things' and' qualities', each having what is called 'essence' by which
it is distinguished from the rest. These 'things' and 'qualities' are in
truth nothing but so many forms in which the Absolute manifests

478 Sufism and Taoism
itself. But in so far as they are self-subsistent entities, they conceal
the Absolute behind their solid 'essential' veils. They intervene
between our sight and the Absolute, and make our direct view of
Reality impossible. The majority of men are those whose eyesight is
obstructed in this way by the thick curtain of 'things'. They have
their counterpart in Taoism in those people who, unable to
'chaotify' the 'things', cannot interpret reality except in terms of
'this'-or-'that', 'good'-or-'bad', 'right'-or-'wrong', etc.
When the 'purification' of the Mind is completed, and when man has
tumed into a metaphysical Void, forgetting both the inside and the
outside of himself, he is allowed to experience what the Taoist sages
call 'illumination' (ming) and what Ibn 'Arabi calls 'unveiling'
(kashfl or 'immediate tasting' (dhawq). It is characteristic of both
'illumination' and 'unveiling' (or 'tasting') that this ultimate stage
once fully actualized, the 'things' that have been eliminated in the
process of 'purification' from the consciousness all corne back once
again, totally transformed, to his Mind which is now a well-polished
spotless mirror - the Mysterious Mirror, 1 as Lao-tzu calls it. Thus it
cornes about that the highest stage of metaphysical intuition is not
that of those who witness only the Absolute, wholly oblivious of
its phenomenal aspect. The highest 'unveiling', according to
Ibn 'Arabi, is of th ose who witness both the creatures and the
Absolu te as two aspects of one Reality, or rather, who witness the
whole as one Reality diversifying itself constantly and incessantly
according to various aspects and relations, being 'one' in Essence,
and 'all' with regard to the Names.
Likewise, the Perfect Man of Taoism does perceive infinitely
variegated things on the phenomenal level of Existence, and the
spotless surface of his Mysterious Mirror reflects all of them as they
appear and disappear. But this kaleidoscope of ever shifting forms
does not perturb the cosmic Tranquillity of the Mind, because
behind these variegated veils of the phenomenal world, he intuits
the metaphysical 'One'. He himself is one with the constant flux of
Transmutation, and being one therewith, he is one with the 'One'.
The philosophical world-view of an Ibn' Arabi, a Lao-tzu and a
Chuang-tzu is a product of such an 'abnormal' spiritual state. Itis an
ontology, because it is a philosophized vision of Existence. But it is

an extraordinary ontology, because the underlying vision of Exist-
ence is far from being an ordinary one.

Note
1. :tl'., Hsüan fan, X.

r
,

111 The Multistratified Structure of
Reality

In terms of historical origin there is obviously no connection at all
between Sufism and Taoism. Historically speaking, the former goes
back to a particular form of Semi tic monotheism, while the latter -if
the hypothesis which I have put forward at the outset of this study is
correct - is a philosophical elaboration of the Far Eastern type of
shamanism.
It is highly significant that, in spite of this wide historico-cultural
distance that separates the two, they share, on the philosophical
level, the same ground. They agree with each other, to begin with, in

that both base their philosophical thinking on a very peculiar con-
ception of Existence which is fundamentally identical, though dif-
fering from one another in details and on secondary matters.

They further agree with one another in that philosophizing in
both cases has its ultimate origin not in reasoning about Existence

but in experiencing Existence. Furthermore, 'experiencing' Exist-
ence in this particular case consists in experiencing it not on the

ordinary level of sense perception, but on the level (or levels) of
supra-sensible intuition.
Existence or Reality as 'experienced' on supra-sensible levels
reveals itself as of a multistratified structure. The Reality which one

observes in this kind of metaphysical intuition is not of a uni-
stratum structure. And the vision of Reality thus obtained is totally

different from the ordinary view of 'reality' which is shared by the
common people.
It is extremely interesting that both Ibn' Arabi and Chuang-tzu
begin by giving a rude shock to common sense by flatly refusing to
admit any reality to so-called 'reality', saying that the latter is
nothing but a dream. Quoting the famous Tradition: 'All men are
asleep; only when they die, do they wake up', Ibn' Arabi says: 'The
world is an illusion; it has no real existence .... Know that you
yourself are an imagination. And everything that you perceive and
say to yourself, "this is not me", is also an imagination.' In an
exactly similar way Chuang-tzu remarks: 'Suppose you dream that
you are a bird. (In that state) you soar up into the sky. Suppose you

480 Sufism and Taoism
dream that you are a fish; you go down deep into the pool. (While
you are experiencing all this in your dream, what you experience is
your "reality" .) Judging by this, nobody can be sure whether we -
you and I, who are actually engaged in conversation in this way- are
awake of just dreaming.' Thus we see so-called 'reality' being all of
a sudden transformed and reduced to something dreamlike and
unreal.
Far more remarkable, however, is the fact that for both Ibn
'Arabi and Chuang-tzii the dictum: 'All is a dream' has a very
positive metaphysical meaning. It is not in any way an emotive
statement to the effect, for instance, that the world we live in is like a
dream, that everything in this world is tragically ephemeral and
transient. It is, on the contrary, a definite ontological statement
recognizing the existence of a higher ontological level where all
things are deprived of their seemingly solid essential boundaries
and disclose their natural amorphousness. And paradoxically
enough, this 'dreamlike' lev el of Existence is, in the view of both Ibn
'Arabi and Chuang-tzii, far more 'real' than so-called 'reality'.
This dreamlike level of Existence is in the ontological system of
Ibn' Arabi what he calls the 'world of similitudes and Imagination',
while in that of Chuang-tzii it is the Chaos.
Thus the basic proposition that all is a dream does not mean that
so-called 'reality' is a vain and groundless thing. Instead of meaning
simply that the physical world is a sheer illusion, the proposition
indicates that the world which we experience on the sensible level is
nota self-subsistent reality, but is a Symbol - an ayah (pl. ayat), or
'indicator' as Ibn 'Arabi calls it, using the Quranic term - vaguely
and indistinctively painting to 'Something beyond'. The sensible
things, thus interpreted, are phenomenal forms of the Absolute
itself, and as such, they are 'real' in a particular way.

However, this again is a matter of immediate intuitive experi-
ence. The metaphysical fact that behind and beyond so-called 'real-
ity', which is apparently a colorful fa bric of fantasy and imagination,

there lies hidden the 'real' Reality, does not become clear except to
those who have learnt how to 'interpret' rightly- as Ibn' Arabi says

- the infinitely variegated forms and properties as so many manifes-
tations of Reality. This is what is meant by Ibn 'Arabi when he says

that one has to 'die and wake up'. 'The only "reality" (in the true
sense of the term) is the Absolu te revealing itself as it really is in the

sensible forms which are nothing but the loci of its self-
manifestation. This point becomes understandable only when one

wakes up from the present life - which is a sleep of forgetfulness -
after one dies to this world through self-annihilation in God.'
Chuang-tzii, likewise, speaks of the need of experiencing a Great
I_
The Multistratified structure of Reality 481
Awakening. 'Only when one experiences a Great Awakening does
one realize that "reality" is but a Big Dream. But the stupid imagine

that they are actually awake .... How deep-rooted and irremedi-
able their stupidity is!'

In the eye of those who have experienced this spiritual Awaken-
ing, all things, each in its own form and on its own level, manifest the

presence of 'Something beyond'. And that 'Something beyond' is
ultimately the haqq of Ibn 'Arabi and the tao of Lao-tzii and
Chuang-tzii - the Absolute. Both Ibn 'Arabi and the Taoist sages
distinguish in the process of the self-revealing evolvement of the
Absolute several degrees or stages. Ontologically speaking this
would mean that Existence is of a multistratified structure.
The strata, according to Ibn' Arabi, are:
(1) The stage of the Essence (the absolute Mystery, abysmal
Darkness);
(2) The stage of the Divine Attributes and Names (the stage
of Divinity);
(3) The stage of the Divine Actions (the stage of Lordship);
( 4) The stage of Images and Similitudes;
( 5) The sensible world.
And according to Lao-tzii:
(1) Mystery of Mysteries;
(2) Non-Being (Nothing, or Nameless);
(3) One;
( 4) Being (Heaven and Earth);
( 5) The ten thousand things.
The two systems agree with each other in that (I) they regard the
first stage as an absolute Mystery, that is, something _absolutely

unknown-unknowable, transcending all distinctions and all limita-
tions, even the limitation of 'not being limited'; and that (2) they

regard the four remaining stages as so many various forms assumed by
this absolute Mystery in the process of its ontological evolvement,
so that all are, in this sense, 'one'. This latter point, namely, the
problem of U nity, will be further discussed in the following chapter.

IV Essence and Existence

As we have seen above, both Chuang-tzu's 'Heavenly Levelling'
and Ibn' Arabi's 'Unity of Existence' are based on the idea that all
things are ultimately reducible to the original Unity of the Absolu te
in its absoluteness, that is, the 'Essence at the level of Unity
(al}adïyah )'.

It is to be remarked that the Essence in the Unity of its uncondi-
tional simplicity is, in Ibn 'Arabi' s view, nothing other than pure

Existence, there being here not even the slightest discrepancy be-
tween 'essence' (i.e., 'quiddity') and 'existence'. In other words, the

Absolu te is actus purus, the act itself of 'existing'. The Absolute is
not a 'thing' in the sense of a 'substance'.
As Qâshâni says: 'The Reality called the" Essence at the lev el of
Unity" in its true nature is nothing other than Existence pure and
simple in so far as it is Existence. It is conditioned neither by
non-determination nor by determination, for in itself it is too sacred
to be qualified by any property and any name. It bas no quality, no
delimitation; there is not even a shadow of Multiplicity in it. It is not
a substance ... , for a substance must have an 'essence' other than
"existence", a "quiddity" by which it is a substance as differentiated
from all others.'
The conception of the Absolute being conditioned neither by
determination nor by non-determination is more tersely expressed
by Lao-tzu through single words like 'Nothing' and 'Nameless', and
by Chuang-tzu through the expression No-[No Non-Being]. The
last expression, No-[No Non-Being], indicates analytically the
stages in the logical process by which one arrives at the realization of
the Absolute transcending all determinations. First, the idea that
the Absolute is Being, i.e., 'existence' as ordinarily understood, is
negated. The concept of Non-Being is thus posited. Then, this

concept of Non-Being is eliminated, because, being a simple nega-
tion of Being, it is but a relative Non-Being. Thus the concept of.

No-Non-Being is obtained. This concept stands on the negation of
both Being and Non-Being, and as such it still keeps in itself a trace

or reftection of the opposition which exists between the contradic-
Essence and Existence 483 tories. In order to eliminate· even this faint trace of relativity, one bas to negate the No-Non-Being itself. Thus finally the concept of No-[No Non-Being] is established, as 'Nothing' in its absolutely unconditional transcendence. And Chuang-tzu clarifies through the admirable symbol of the Cosmic Wind that this transcendent Nothing is nota purely negative 'nothing' in the usual sense of the word; that, on the contrary, it is a supra-plenitude of Existence as the ultimate ontological ground of everything, as Something that lies at the very source of all existents and makes them exist. 'lt would seem', Chuang-tzu says, 'that there is some real Ruler. It is impossible for us to see Him in a concrete form. He is acting - there can be no doubt aboutit; but we cannot see His form. He does show His activity, but He has no sensible form.' This simply means that the No-[No Non-Being] - or theo- logically, the real Ruler of the world- is actus, creative energy, nota substance. The Cosmic Wind in itself is invisible and impalpable - because it is nota substance - but we know its presence through its ontological activity, through the ten thousand 'hales' and 'hollows' producing each its peculiar sound as the Wind blows upon them. The basic idea underlying the use of the symbol of the Wind is comparable with Ibn 'Arabi's favorite image of the 'ftowing' of Existence (sarayim al-wujüd). 'The secret of Life (i.e., Existence) lies in the act of ftowing peculiar to water.' The 'water' of Existence is eternally flowing through all things. It 'spreads" throughout the universe, permeating and pervading everything. It is significant that both Chuang-tzu and Ibn 'Abrabi represent Existence as something moving: 'blowing', 'ftowing', 'spreading', 'permeating', etc. This is a definite proof that Existence as they have corne to know it through 'immediate tasting' is in reality actus, nothing else. Existence which is actus, th us spreading itself out far and wide, goes on producing the ten thousand things. The latter, as 1 have repeatedly pointed out, are various forms in which Existence (or the Absolu te) manifests itself. And in this sense, all are Existence, nothing but Existence. And there is nothing but Existence. Viewed from this angle, the whole world of Being is one. On the other band, however, it is also an undeniable fact that we actually see with our own eyes an infinity of infinitely variegated 'things' which are different from one another. 'lt is evident', Ibn 'Arabi says, 'that this is different from that . .. And in the Divine world, however wide it is, nothing repeats itself. This is a truly fondamental fact.' From this po:nt: of view, there is nota single thing that is the same as any other thing. Even 'one and the same thing' is in reality not exactly the same in two successive moments.

484 Sufism and Taoism
These individually different things, on a more universal level of
Existence, still retain their mutual differences and distinctions, not
'individually' this time, but in terms of 'essences'. And these
ontological differences and distinctions which the 'things' manifest
on this level are far more solid and unalterable because they are
based on, and fixed by, their 'essences'. The latter provide the

'things' with an 'essential' fixity which ensures them from disinte-
gration. A 'horse' is a 'horse' by its 'essence'; it can never be a '<log'.

A '<log' is 'essentially' a '<log', nothing else. It goes without saying
that this is the very basis on which stands the 'essentialist' type of
ontology.
How could we account for the apparent contradiction between
the above-mentioned absolute Unity of Existence, Unity of all
things, and the undeniable Multiplicity of the ten thousand things
which are not reducible to each other, let alone to a unique and
single thing? Surely, if one puts these two points of view si de by side

with each other, one's mind cannot help being thrown into bewilder-
ing confusion. To see the One in the Many and the Many in the One,

or rather to see the Many as One and the One as Many - this
naturally causes what Ibn 'Arabï calls (metaphysical) 'perplexity'
(IJ,ayrah).
Faced with this problem, Chuang-tzu takes a thoroughgoing

anti-essentialist position. The view of things, each being distin-
guished from the rest by a solid 'boundary' of 'essence', he main tains,

does not give a true picture of these things themselves. The 'essen-
tial' distinctions which common sense and Reason recognize be-
tween things are, according to him, devoid of reality. The 'things'

ordinarily look as if they were distinct from each other in terms of
'essences', simply because ordinary men are not 'awake'. If they
were, they would 'chaotify' the things and see them in their original
'undifferentiation'.
The things being 'chaotified', however, is not the same as their
being sheer nothing. The very concept of 'chaotification' would be
meaningless if there were no plurality at all in the world of Being. It
is, as Ibn 'Arabï main tains, a truly fondamental fact that many
'different' things do exist, no matter how 'unreal' they may be in
themselves and from the viewpoint of the higher metaphysical level
of Existence. The differences and distinctions that are observable in
the world may reveal themselves as 'unreal' when observed with the
'spiritual eyesight' of an ecstatic philosopher, but in so far as things
are factually different and distinct from each other, there must be
some ontological ground for that, too. And the ontological ground
cannot be anything other than 'essences'.
The 'essences' are symbolically designated by Chuang-tzu
through the image of the 'hollows' in the trees, which emit all kinds

Essence and Existence 485
of sounds as the Wind blows upon them. Chuang-tzu does not assert
that the 'hollows' do not exist in any sense whatsoever. They are
surely there. The only point is that they do not produce any sound
by themselves. It is the Wind, not the 'hollows', that really produces
the sounds. '(One and the same Wind) blows on the ten thousand
things in different ways, and makes each "hollow" produce its own
peculiar sound, so that each imagines that its own self produces that
particular sound. But who, in reality, is the one who makes (the
"hollows") produce various sounds?'
All this would seem to be tantamount to saying - although
Chuang-tzu himself does not talk in terms of these concepts - that

the 'essences' are not sheer nothing, that they are potentially exist-
ent. The 'essences' do exist, but only in potentia, not in actu; they

are not actual or real in the fullest sense of the word. What is really
'real' is Existence, nothing else. And the 'essences' look as if they
were 'real' only by dint of the actualizing activity of Existence.
The position of the 'hollows' in the ontology of Chuang-tzu
corresponds to that of the 'permanent archetypes' in the ontology of
Ibn' Arabï. The main difference between the two lies in the fact that
in the former the relation between Essence and Existence is merely
symbolically suggested, whereas Ibn 'Arabï consciously takes up
the problem as an ontological theme and elaborates it far more
theoretically.
Details have been given in Chapter XII of the first Part regarding
the conceptual structure of the 'permanent archetypes'. Suffice it
here to note that the 'permanent archetypes' are the 'essences' of
the things, and that they are described as 'neither existent nor
non-existent' - which would exactly apply to the 'hollows' of
Chuang-tzu. It is remarkable, however, that the 'permanent
archetypes' are also described by Ibn' Arabï as 'realities (IJ,aqa'iq)
eternally subsistent in the world of the Unseen'. That is to say, the
'permanent archetypes', although they are 'non-existent' in terms

of'external existence', do existin actu within the Divine Conscious-
ness. The ontology of Ibn 'Arabï is, in this respect, Platonic; it is

more 'essentialist' than that of Chuang-tzu who does not concede
anything more than sheer potentiality to the 'essences'.

V The Self-Evolvement of Existence

The absolu te and ultimate ground of Existence is in both Sufism and
Taoism the Mystery of Mysteries. The latter is, as Ibn 'Arabï says,
the ankar al-nakirat 'the most indeterminate of all indeterminates';
that is to say, it is Something that transcends all qualifications and
relations that are humanly conceivable. And since it is transcendent
to such a degree, it remains for ever unknown and unknowable.

Existence per se is thus absolutely inconceivable and inapproach-
able. Ibn 'Arabï refers to this aspect of Existence by the word

'ghayb, 'concealment' or 'invisibility'. In the Taoist system, it is
hsüan or Mystery that is the most proper word for referring to this
absolutely transcendent stage of Existence.
The Taoist sages have also a set of negative words like wu,
Non-Being, wu-wu, No-thing or 'Nothing', wu-ming, Nameless,
etc. These terms are properly to be considered as functioning still
within the domain of the original transcendence. Conceptually,
however, there is already observable a distinction between these
negative terms and the 'Mystery', because their very 'negative-ness'
indicates their opposition to something 'positive', i.e., the following
stage of yu or Being, at which the 'boundaries' of the things-to-be
are adumbrated. This is the reason why Chuang-tzii proposes to use
the complex expression, No-[No Non-Being] or No-No-Nothing in
order to refer to the ultimate stage of Existence (i.e., the Mystery of
Mysteries) without leaving the level of negativity. However, this

distinction between the Mystery and these negative terms is ex-
clusively conceptual. Otherwise, 'Non-Being', 'Nothing', and

'Nameless' denote exactly the same thing as the 'Mystery'. They all
denote the Absolute in its absoluteness, or Existence at its ultimate
stage, qua Something unknown-unknowable, transcending all
qualifications, determinations, and relations.
It is important to note that Ibn' Arabi calls this ontological level the
'level of Unity (alJ,adiyah )'.The Absolu te at this stage is 'One' in the
sense that it refuses to accept any qualification whatsoever. Thus,
being one here means nothing other than absolute transcendence.

The self-evolvement of Existence 487
The Taoist sages, too, speak of the Way as' One'. As I have tried
to show earlier, the 'One' in the Taoist system is conceptually to be
placed between the stage of Non-Being and that of Being. It is not
exactly the same as the Way qua Mystery, because it is considered as
something which the ten thousand things 'acquire', i.e., partake of.
The One, in other words, is the principle of immanence. The Way is
'immanent' in everything existent as its existential core, or as its
Virtue, as Lao-tzii calls it. But whether regarded as 'immanent' or
'transcendent', the Way is the Way. What is immanent in everything
is exactly the same thing as that which transcends everything. And
this situation corresponds to the conceptual distinction between
tanzih and tashbih and the factual identity of the two in the system of
Ibn 'Arabi.
Thus the Taoist concept of One, in so far as it refers to the
Absolute itself, is an exact counterpart of Ibn 'Arabï's alJ,ad, the
'absolu te One', but in so far as it is 'One' comprising within itself the
possibility of Multiplicity, it is a counterpart of walJ,id, i.e., the 'One
at the level of the Names and Attributes', or the Unity of the Many.
In short, the Taoist One comprises both the alJ,ad and the walJ,id of
Sufism.
These considerations make us realize that the first and ultimate
stage of Existence itself can naturally be considered from two
diff erent angles: ( 1) as the Absolu te perse, and ( 2) as the Absolu te

as the very origin and starting-point of the process of self-
evolvement. In the first of these two aspects, the Absolute is Mys-
tery and Darkness. In the second aspect, on the contrary, a faint

foreboding of light is already perceivable in the very midst of utter
darkness. As Ibn' Arabï says: 'Everything is contained in the bosom
of the Breath, just as the bright light of day in the very darkness of
dawn'.
It is quite significant in this respect that the word used by the
Taoist sages to denote the Mystery, hsüan, originally means 'black'
with a mixture of redness. Lao-tzii, as we have noticed, likes us to
use in this sense also the word p'u meaning originally 'uncarved
wood'. Existence, at this stage of absolu te simplicity, is like
'uncarved wood'. In so far as it still remains 'uncarved', there is
nothing observable but 'wood'. But in so far as it contains the
possibility of producing all kinds of vessels and utensils, it is more
than sheer 'wood'. Actually it is still 'Nothing', but potentially it is
all things. There is at least a vague and indistinct feeling that
something is about to happen. And that is the 'positive' aspect of the
Mystery, the face of the Absolu te turned toward the world of
creation. Ibn 'Arabi conveys the same idea by the expression:
'hidden Treasure', which he has taken from a Tradition. And it is of

488 Sufism and Taoism
the very nature of the 'hidden Treasure' that it 'loves to be known'.
It is, however, at the stage of the Divine Names and Attributes -
in terms of Ibn' Arabi's world-view-that this 'love of being known',
i.e., the inner ontological drive of Existence, becomes actualized.
At the stage of the absolu te Unity, the Absolu te qua Absolu te is
characterized by a perfect 'independence', and does not require by

itself and for itself any creative activity. If' creation' is at all conceiv-
able at this stage, it is simply in the form of a faint foreboding. In the

System of Taoism the concept of Non-Being or Nothing refers
precisely to this delicate situation. 'Deep and Bottomless', Lao-tzii
says, 'it is like the origin and principle of the ten thousand
things .... There is nothing, and yet there seems to be something. 1
know not whose son it is. It would seem to be antecedent even to the
Heavenly Emperor.' 'The Way in its reality is utterly vague, utterly
indistinct. Utterly indistinct, utterly vague, and yet there is in the
midst of it an Image. Utterly vague, utterly indistinct, and yet there
is in the midst of it Something.'

The 'hidden Treasure loves to be known'. The Treasure lies 'hid-
den', and yet it is, so to speak, pressed from inside by the' desire to

be known'. Speaking less symbolically, the infini te things that are
contained in the Absolute in the state of pure potentia forcefully
seek for an outlet. This naturally causes an ontological tension
within the Absolute. And the internai ontological compression,
growing ever stronger finally relieves itself by bursting forth. It is
highly interesting to notice that both Ibn 'Arabi and Chuang-tzii

resort to the same kind of imagery in trying to describe this situa-
tion. Chuang-tzii talks about 'eructation'. He says: 'The Great

Earth eructates; and the eructation is called Wind. As long as the
eructation does not actually occur, nothing is observable. But once
it does occur, all the hollows of the trees raise ringing shouts.' The
issuing forth of the ten thousand things from the Absolute is here
compared to the Great Earth belching forth the Wind.

No less bold and picturesque is the mythopoeic image of 'brea-
thing out' by which Ibn 'Arabi tries to depict the matter. The

ontological state of extreme tension which precedes the 'bursting
out' and which has been caused by an excessive amount of things
accumulated inside is compared to the state in which a man finds
himself when he holds his breath compressed within himself. The
tension reaches the last limit, and the air compressed in the breast
exp Iodes and gushes forth with a violent outburst. In a similar way,
the creative drive of Existence gushes forth out of the depth of
Absolute. This is the phenomenon which Ibn 'Arabi calls the
'breath of the Merciful'. In the theological language peculiar to Ibn
'Arabi, the same phenomenon can also be described as the Divine

The self-evolvement of Existence 489

Names, at the extreme limitof inner compression, suddenly burst-
ing out from the bosom of the Absolute. 'The Names, previous to

their existence in the outer world (in the form of phenomenal
things) exist hidden in the Essence of the Absolu te (i.e., the Mystery
of Mysteries), all of them seeking an outlet toward the world of
external existence. The situation is comparable to the case in which
a man holds his breath within himself. The breath, held within,
seeks an outlet toward the outside, and this causes in the man a
painful sensation of extreme compression. Only when he breathes
out does this compression cease to make itself felt. Just as the man is
tormented by the compression if he does not breathe out, so the
Absolu te would feel the pain of ( ontological) compression if it did
not bring into existence the world in response to the demand of the
Names.' This may also be compared with the image of a great

Cosmic Bellows by which Lao-tzii symbolically-describes the inex-
haustible creative activity of the Way. 'The space between Heaven

and Earth is comparable to a bellows. It is empty (i.e., the Absolute
qua the Mystery of Mysteries is "Nothing"), but its activity is
inexhaustible. The more it works the more it produces.'
Thus Existence, in compliance with its own necessary and natural
internai demand, goes on inexhaustibly determining itself into an
infinity of concrete things. And the 'breath of the Merciful' or the

ontological Mercy pervades all of them, constituting the very exis-
tential core of each one of them. And the existential core thus

acquired by each phenomenal thing is what The Taoist sages call tê
or Virtue.
It is worth remarking that the ral)mah or Mercy as understood by
Ibn 'Arabi is primarily an ontological fact. It refers to the actus of
Existence, namely, the act of making things exist. lt does not

primarily denote the emotive attitude of compassion and benevol-
ence. But Mercy as bestowal of existence of course carries an

emotive and subjective overtone. And this squares well with the
ethical understanding of God in Islam. The creative activity of
Existence is represented in Taoism in a form which is diametrically
opposed to such a conception. For in Taoism the Way is said to be
'non-humane' (pu jen). 'Heaven and Earth', Lao-tzii says, 'lack
"benevolence" (i.e., lack mercy).' They treat the ten thousand
things as if the latter were straw dogs.' The difference between the
two systems, however, is only superficial. For whether described in
terms of Mercy (in Sufism) or non-Mercy (in Taoism), the basic fact
described remains exactly the same. This because the ontological
Mercy, in the conception of Ibn 'Arabi, is absolu tel y gratuitous.
What is meant by both Mercy and non-Mercy is nothing other than
the all-pervading creative activity of Existence. Ibn' Arabi himself

490 Sufism and Taoism
warns us against understanding the word ralJ,mah with its usual

associations. 'There does not corne into its activity any considera-
tion of attaining an aim, or of a thing's being or not being suitable for

a purpose. Whether suitable or unsuitable the Divine Mercy covers
everything and anything with existence.'
This explanation of Mercy by Ibn 'Arabï is so congenial to the
spirit of Taoism that it will pass verbatim for an explanation by a
Lao-tzu of the Taoist concept of non-Mercy which is as equally
impartial and indiscriminating as Ibn' Arabï's Mercy in bestowing
the gift of 'existence' upon everything and everybody. In the view of
Lao-tzu, the creative activity of the Absolute is extended over the
ten thousand things without a single exception precisely because it
stands on the principle of non-Mercy. If even a trifting amount of
human emotion were involved therein, the Absolute would not be
acting with such an absolu te impartiality. In the view of Ibn' Arabï,
on the contrary, the Absolute bestows 'existence' to all things
without excluding anything precisely because it is the actus of
Mercy. The Divine Mercy being by nature limitlessly wide, it covers
the whole world. As is obvious, the underlying idea is in both cases
one and the same.
The structure itself of this concept of Mercy or non-Mercy is directly
connected with another important idea: that of the Absolute being
'beyond good and evil'. The creative activity of the Absolute, which

consists in the bestowal of 'existence' qua 'existence' upon every-
thing involves no moral judgment. From the point of view of the

Absolu te, it does not matter at all whether a given object be good or
bad. Rather, there is absolutely no such distinction among the
objects. The latter assume these and other evaluational properties
only after having been given 'existence' by the indiscriminating act
of the Absolute; and that from the particular points of view of the
creatures. Otherwise, all existents are on the 'straight way' - as Ibn
'Arabï says - or all existents are 'so-of-themselves' - as the Taoist
sages say. There is no distinction at this stage between good and evil.
This idea is formulated by Lao-tzu and Chuang-tzu in terms of a
'relativist' view of all values. Ordinary men distinguish between
'good' and 'bad', 'beautiful' and 'ugly', 'noble' and 'ignoble', etc.,

and construct their life social as well as persona!, on these distinc-
tions as if they were objective categories that have been fixed in an

unalterable way by the very nature of the things. In truth, however,
these and other seemingly solid objective categories, far from being
'objective', are but products of 'subjective' and 'relative' points of
view. A 'beautiful' lady from the human point of view, Chuang-tzu
argues, is 'ugly' and 'terrifying' enough, from the point of view of
other animais, to make them run away as fast as their legs or wings

The self-evolvement of Existence 491
can carry them. The distinctions are a sheer matter of relative
viewpoints, a matter of likes and dislikes. As Ibn 'Arabï says: 'The
bad is nothing other than what one dislikes, while the good is
nothing other than what one likes.'
Thus in both Sufism and Taoism the basic proposition holds true
that everything is primarily, that is, qua 'existence', neither good
nor evil. However there is a certain respect - again both in Sufism
and Taoism - in which everything is to be considered fundamentally

'good'. This because everything qua 'existence' is a particular self-
manifestation of the Absolute itself. And looked at from such a

viewpoint, all things in the world are 'one'. As Chuang-tzu says:
'(However different they may look from each other) they are, in
reality no other than so man y things that are "affirmable" piled up
one upon the other.' They are at one with each other in being
fundamentally 'affirmable', i.e., good. The Perfect Man 'is "one",
whether he (seemingly) likes something or dislikes something'. And
Lao-tzii: 'Those who are good 1 treat as good. But those who are not
good also 1 treat as good. For the original nature of man is goodness.
Those who are faithful 1 treat as faithful. But even those who are not

faithful 1 treat as faithful. For the original nature of man is faithful-
ness.' Such an attitude would immediately be approved by Ibn

'Arabï, who says: 'What is bad is bad simply because of (the subjec-
tive impression caused by) the taste; but the same thing will be

found to be essentially good, if considered apart from the (subjec-
tive attitude on the part of man) of liking or disliking.'

These considerations make it clear that for both Ibn' Arabi and the
Taoist sages there is the closest and most intimate relationship
between the Absolute and the things of the phenomenal world.
Although the latter are apparently far removed from the Absolute,
they are after all so many different forms which the Absolute
assumes in making itself manifest at various stages and in various
places. This intimate ontological relationship between the two
terms of the creative process is in Taoism symbolically expressed by
the image of the Mother-Child relationship. The Way at the stage of
the 'Being' or 'Named' is considered by Lao-tzu the 'Mother of the
ten thousand things'. The symbolic implication of this statement is
that all things in the phenomenal world are the very ftesh and blood
of the Absolute. And the Taoist ideal consists in man's 'knowing the
Children by knowing the Mother, and in his knowing the Children
and yet holding fast to the Mother' .
On the side of Ibn 'Arabi, the same ontological relationship
between the Absolute and phenomenal things is compared to the
inseparable relationship between 'shadow' and its source, i.e., the
man or object that projects it upon the earth. 'Do you not see', Ibn

492 Sufism and Taoism
'Arabï asks, 'how in your ordinary sensible experience shadow is so
closely tied up with the person who projects it that it is absolutely
impossible for it to liberate itself from this tie? This is impossible
because it is impossible for anything to be separated from itself.' The
world is the 'shadow' of the Absolute, and, as such, it is connected
with the latter with the closest relationship which is never to be eut
off. Every single part of the world is a particular aspect of the
Absolute, and is the Absolute in a delimited form.
Ibn 'Arabï describes the same rélationship by referring to the
Divine Name: 'Subtle' (latïf). The 'subtleness' in this context means

the quality of an immaterial thing which, because of its immaterial-
ity, permeates and pervades the substances of all other things,

diffusing itself in the latter and freely mixing with them. 'lt is the
effect of God's "subtleness" that He exists in every particular thing,

designated by a particular name, as the very essence of that particu-
lar thing. He is immanent in every particular thing in such a way that

He is, in each case, referred to by the conventional and customary
meaning of the particular name of that thing. Thus we say: "This is
Heaven", "This is the earth", "This is a tree", etc. But the essence
itself that exists in every one of these things is just one.'
We shall do well to recall that in a passage of his commentary
upon the Qashanï also uses the Mother image. 'The ultimate
ground of everything is called the Mother (umm) because the
mother is the (stem) from which all branches go out.'
lt is worth noticing, further, that both Ibn 'Arabi and the Taoist
sages pictute the process of creation as a perpetual and constant
flow. Their world-view in this respect is of a markedly dynamic
nature. Nothing remains static. The world in its entirety is in fervent
movement. 'As water running in a river, which forever goes on
being renewed continuously' (Ibn 'Arabi), the world transforms

itself kaleidoscopically from moment to moment. The Cosmic Bel-
lows of Lao-tzii is an appropriate symbol for this incessant process

of creation. 'The space between Heaven and Earth is comparable to
a bellows. lt is empty, but its activity is inexhaustible. The more it
works, the more it produces.'
The thesis of the universal Transmutation of things which
Chuang-tzii puts forward also refers to this aspect of Reality. All
things in the phenomenal world are constantly changing from one
form to another. Everything is ontologically involved in the cosmic
process of Transmutation. 'Dying and being alive, being subsistent

and perishing, getting into a predicament and being in the ascend-
ant, being poor and being rich, being clever and being incom-
petent, being disgraced and being honored ... all these are but the

constant changes of things, and the results of the incessant working

The selfevolvement of Existence 493
of Fate. All these thing go on replacing one another before our own
eyes, but no one by his Intellect can trace them back to their real
origin.' These changes 'remind us of all kinds of sounds emerging
from the empty holes (of a flute), or mushrooms coming out of
warm dampness. Day and night, these changes never cease to
replace one another before our eyes.'
Ibn 'Arabi pursues this perpetual flux of things down to a single
moment. The result is his theory of 'new creation', that is, the thesis
that the world goes on being created anew at every single moment.
At every moment, countless things and properties are produced,
and at the very next moment they are annihilated to be replaced by

another infinity of things and properties. And this ontological pro-
cess goes on repeating itself indefinitely and endlessly.

It is remarkable that neither in Sufism nor in Taoism is the
ontological Descent - from the Mystery of Mysteries down to the

stage of phenomenal things - made to represent the final comple-
tion of the activity of Existence. The Descent is followed by its

reversai, that is, Ascent. The ten thousand things flourish exuber-
antly at the last stage of the descending course, and then take an

ascending course toward their ultimate source until they disappear
in the original Darkness and find their resting place in the cosmic
pre-phenomenal Stillness. Thus the whole process of creation forms
a huge ontological circle in which there is in reality neither an initial
point nor a final point. The movement from one stage to another,
considered in itself, is surely a temporal phenomenon. But the
whole circle, having neither an initial point nor a final point, is a
trans-temporal or a-temporal phenomenon. lt is, in other words, a
metaphysical process. Everything is an occurrence in an Eternal
Now.