Showing posts with label **. Show all posts
Showing posts with label **. Show all posts

2022/12/31

Spiritual Direction: What Does a Spiritual Director Actually Do? | Greg Richardson

Spiritual Direction: What Does a Spiritual Director Actually Do? | Greg Richardson

Spiritual Direction: What Does a Spiritual Director Actually Do?
 OCTOBER 6, 2022 BY GREG RICHARDSON
---

What Does a Spiritual Director Do?

It is not unusual, when anyone asks me about what I do, for their next question to be What is spiritual direction? or What does a spiritual director do?

Not many kids say they want to be a spiritual director when they grow up. Most of us have never heard of someone being a spiritual director and we do not understand what it means.


When I explain spiritual direction to people it tends to spark more questions in them. Some people want to know if I am a minister, or why someone would not just talk to a minister. There are people who see me as a resource they can use when they have questions about theology or religion. Other people seem to assume they can tell me about their problems and I will tell them what to do.

A spiritual director is not a substitute for a minister or a church. I do not have the answers to most theological questions, and have quite a few questions myself. It is rare I tell people what they should do.

One of my favorite things about the job title of spiritual director is its irony. I talk with people about a lot of things many of us do not see as spiritual and I work hard not to be particularly directive.

Spiritual direction has a long history. Traditionally, people would seek out a member of the clergy or a monk and tell them their stories. The director would suggest ways they could approach specific problems or issues. Some of these relationships were focused on particular questions, while some continued on an ongoing basis.

There are now many people who are not ministers who have been trained and certified as spiritual directors.


What Makes Someone Good at Spiritual Direction?
Each of us is a unique person, and each spiritual director has their own personal approach to what they do.

I believe the first essential element of spiritual direction is listening well.

For me, practicing spiritual direction is part of my path toward contemplative spirituality. I did not become interested in being a spiritual director until I began to practice listening to sacred stillness.

When I meet with someone for spiritual direction my role is creating and protecting our sacred time and space. It is not my responsibility to solve their problems or make them feel good. We share time and a space where we can be honest with each other. I listen to what they have to say.

Another essential part of my practice of spiritual direction is asking questions which are insightful.

As a recovering attorney, I needed to learn many things in my spiritual direction training. One of the first was how not to cross-examine people.

Now I try to ask questions which get underneath the way someone hears their own story. It helps me to appreciate I am listening to a person’s story for the first time. They may have grown tired of their own story or closed their eyes to significant parts of their lives.

I can hear their stories with fresh ears and recognize things they may have missed.

A third significant part of being a spiritual director is remembering all of life is spiritual.

We too often allow expectations or ideas about what is spiritual and what is not to blind us to spiritual life. Many of us assume certain days or particular kinds of places are more spiritual than others.

A good spiritual director appreciates all of life is spiritual and nothing is excluded.

Finding a Spiritual Director
There are many ways to look for spiritual direction.

Some people look online while others ask their friends. There are associations like Spiritual Directors International which have directories of their members.

No matter how we carry out our search, there are significant things for us to remember as we look.

We are not necessarily trying to find the best educated spiritual director or the one with the most qualifications. The practice of spiritual direction is, at its heart, a relationship. It is important for us to find a spiritual director we can trust and with whom we can be honest.

Spiritual direction is essentially an ongoing conversation. I believe it is important to experience what the conversation will be like for us before choosing whether, and how, to participate.


Many of us seek spiritual direction because we have questions we would like to answer. In addition to finding a conversational connection, we need to be comfortable asking our questions.

It is helpful for us to understand what questions we have before we talk with a spiritual director. Clarifying what someone’s questions are is a helpful step when I talk with someone about spiritual direction.

We are hoping to find someone who will help us recognize new things in parts of our lives.

Why Do People Want Spiritual Direction?
Each of us has our own reasons for seeking spiritual direction. Some of us want an opportunity to discover and explore the deepest truths of our lives. Other people find it helpful to have someone with whom to talk things through. When we hear something or read something we want to be able to work through it with another person.

Some of us want to find someone who will listen to us and ask insightful questions.

We may need to be reminded all of life is spiritual.

Spiritual direction is not about fixing or correcting us, or telling us how to live. A spiritual director is not necessarily like our friend who pokes holes in our arguments and shows us where we are wrong.


Many of us are seeking a spiritual director to be a companion and guide on our journey. Each of us has our own preferences and expectations. We are looking for a relationship which will help us explore spiritual life in our everyday lives.

What would we talk to a spiritual director about today?

How could spiritual direction be helpful to us this week?

[Image by Portland Seminary]

Greg Richardson is a spiritual director in Southern California. He is a recovering assistant district attorney and associate university professor, and is a lay Oblate with New Camaldoli Hermitage near Big Sur, California. Greg’s website is StrategicMonk.com and his email address is StrategicMonk@gmail.com.

2022/12/24

"Buddhist Spirituality Later China Korea Japan And The Modern World Takeuchi Yoshinori"

Full text of "Buddhist Spirituality Later China Korea Japan And The Modern World Takeuchi Yoshinori"



Full text of "Buddhist Spirituality Later China Korea Japan And The Modern World Takeuchi Yoshinori"

Contents 


Preface to the Series xi 

Introduction 

The Staff of the Nanzan Institute xiii 


Part Three: Later China 


15 

Ch’an 



I. A Historical Sketch 



Philip Yampolsky 

II. Ch’an Spirituality 



Thomas P. Kasulis 

24 


III. Four Ch’an Masters 
Dale S. Wright 

IV. The Encounter of Ch’an with Confucianism 
Julia Ching 

44 


Part Four: Korea 

Silla Buddhist Spirituality 
Sung Bae Park 

57 

17 

The Koryo Period 
Robert E. Buswell, Jr. 

79 

18 

Buddhist Spirituality in Premodern and Modern Korea 
Henrik H. Sorensen 


Part Five: Japan 
Foundations 

I. The Birth of Japanese Buddhism 
Hanayama Shinsho aiid Hanayama Shoyii 

II. The Impact of Buddhism in the Nara Period 
Thomas P. Kasulis 

144 


III. The Japanese Transformation of Buddhism 
Royall Tyler 

Heian Period 

I. Saicho 
Umehara Takeshi 

II. Kukai 
Paul B. Watt 

174 


III. Heian Foundation of Kamakura Buddhism 
David Lion Gardiner ' 

186 

21 

Pure Land 



I. Early Pure Land Leaders 
Tamaru Noriyosbi 
II* Honen’s Spiritual Legacy 
Fujimoto Kiyohiko 
III. Shinran’s Way 
Alfred Bloom 

22 The Spirituality of Nichiren 

Laurel Rasplica Rodd 

23 Zen 

I. A Historical Sketch 
Philip Yampolsky 

II. Dogen 

Tsuchida Tomoaki 

III. Three Zen Thinkers 
Minamoto Ryoen 
IV Hakuin 
Michel Mohr 


Tokugawa Period 

I. Buddhist Responses to Confucianism 
Minamoto Ryden 

II. The Buddhist Element in Shingaku 
Paid B. Watt 

III. Jiun Sonja 

337 


Paul B. Watt 

348 

25 

Kiyozawa Manshi’s “Spiritualism” 
Gilbert Johnston and Wakimoto Tsuneya 

359 

26 

Philosophy as Spirituality: The Way of the Kyoto School 
James W. Heisig 

Part Six: Art, Society, and New Directions 

367 

27 

Buddha’s Bodies and the Iconographical Turn 
Mimi Hall Yiengpruksaivan 

391 

28 

Buddhist Spirituality in Modern Taiwan 



Heng-Ching Shih 

. 417 

29 

Soka Gakkai and the Modern Reformation of Buddhism 



Shimazono Sttsumu 

435 

30 

Contemporary Buddhist Spirituality and Social Activism 



Sallie King 

455 

31 

Theravada Spirituality in the West 



Egil Fronsdal 

482 

32 

Zen and the West 



Franz Aubrey Metcalf 

496 

Glossary of Technical Terms 

511 


Contributors 


523 






CONTENTS 


viii 

Photographic Credits 
Name Index 
Subject Index 


526 

527 

539 

=======


Philosophy as Spirituality 
The Way of the Kyoto School 

James W H e i s i g 


I N THE EIRST OE A series of talks delivered on Basel radio in 1949, Karl 
Jaspers described philosophy as the concentrated effort to ecome 
oneself by participating in reality;* 1 For the historian of the Western 
intellectual tradition, the description may seem to exaggerate t e 
importance of only one ingredient in the practice of philosop iy, ut it 
applies well to the group of Japanese thinkers known as the Kyoto sc oo . 
Their pursuit of philosophical questions was never detached from t e cu ti 
vation of human consciousness as participation in the real. Drawing on 
Western philosophy ancient and modern as well as on their ov\ n Bu 11 st 
heritage, and combining the demands of critical thought with the quest or 
religious wisdom, they have enriched world intellectual history wit a res 
Japanese perspective and opened anew the question of the spiritua i men 
sion of philosophy. In this article I would like to focus on this re igious 
significance of their achievement. 

It might be thought that the philosophy of the Kyoto school is inaccessi 
ble to those not versed in the language, religion, and culture of Japan. Rea 
in translation, there is a certain strangeness to the vocabulary, and many o 
the sources these thinkers take for granted will be unfamiliar. They pre 
suppose the education and reading habits of their Japanese audience, so 
that many subtleties of style and allusion, much of what is going on 
between the lines and beneath the surface of their texts, will inevitab y e 
lost on other audiences. Still, it was not their aim to produce a merely Bu 
dhist, much less Japanese, body of thought, but rather to address funda 
mental, universal issues in what they saw as the universally accessible lan¬ 
guage of philosophy. That is why their work has proved intelligible and 


367 






368 


JAPAN 


accessible far beyond Japan, and why it is prized today by many Western 
readers as an enhancement of the spiritual dimension of our common 
•humanity. 

Opinions differ on how to define the membership of the Kyoto school, 
but there is no disagreement that its main pillars are Nishida Kitaro 
( 1870 -1945) and his disciples, Tanabe Hajime (1885-1962) and Nishitani 
Keiji (1900—1990), all of whom held chairs at Kyoto University. Similari¬ 
ties in interest and method, as well as significant differences among the 
three, are best understood by giving each a brief but separate treatment. 


Nishida Kitaro: The Quest of the Locus of Absolute Nothingness 


For Nishida the goal of the philosophical enterprise was self-awakening: to 
t e phenomena of life clearly through recovering the original purity of 
experience to articulate rationally what has been seen, and to reappraise 
i eas t at govern human history and society with reason thus enlight- 

^ r ^ nce realit y ls constantly changing, and since we are part 
t at c ange, unde)standing must be a “direct experiencing from within” 
« lCU a * l °n °f what has been so understood must be an internalized, 
°P nate expression. Accordingly, Nishida’s arguments are often post 
murk k StI *n Ct j ( j? S a P at ^ of thinking he had traversed intuitively, led as 
absorbin ^ ^ ^ SCnSe rea ^ c y as by the Western philosophies he was 

A o • 


a flv npfl r k- t0 aV T e een struc ^ one da y while on a walk by the buzzing of 
confirmed ^ ^ ou £hts, he only “noticed” it later, but this 

and are krp lm * , C ord i nar iness of the experience where things happen 
brines the r n0tlCed accordi ng to biased habits of thought. “I heard a fly” 

between an Xand "X’-X 10 ^ prOCess distorts >nto a relationship 
saw actualiri^ a y * event is pure actuality. Somehow, he 

atel’y distract COnStIt . Ute SUbjeCtS ° b i ects > but then mind is immedi ' 

purity of the n * ° ^ S * S and i ud £ men t, never to find its way back to the 

ter mind from t-k ex P er * ence - To recover that purity would be to unfet- 

nicating the experience?'^ COnst [ aints of bein S reasonable or of commu- 

that mind leans f r 1 °' ° Se wbo d ‘ d not sbare it. This does not mean 

PlyXt W Z r. e S c nSeS t0 SOme privile S ed -errant state, but sim- 

what can onlv h ^ .!™, ltS ,° ltS Unbound, bodily existence, mind reaches 
what can only be called a kind of boundlessness. 

da’s starri experience prior to the subject-object distinction was Nishi- 

a clea r ? COurses throu S h the pages of his collected works like 

stream. In the opening pages of his maiden work, A Study of the Good, 





PHILOSOPHY AS SPIRITUALITY 


369 


Nishida calls it “pure experience,” borrowing a term from the American 
philosopher William James. His attraction to the idea, however, stems less 
from James, or indeed from any Western thinker, than from his own Sino- 
Japanese tradition. We read, for instance, in the eleventh-century Buddhist 
Record of the Transmission of the Lamp that “the mental state having achieved 
true enlightenment is like that before enlightenment began”; or again, the 
great Noh dramatist Zeami (1363-1443) comments on how the Book of 
Changes deliberately omits the element for “mind” in the Chinese glyph for 
“sensation” to indicate a precognitive awareness. 4 Such was the tradition 
out of which Nishida stepped into his study of philosophy and forged what 
he was later to call his “logic of locus.” 5 


The Logic of Locus 

In its forward, rational construction, the process of restoring experience to 
its purity—the aim of the logic of locus—may be described graphically as 
a series of concentric circles. 6 The smallest circle, where the center is most 
in control of the periphery, is that of a judgment where something is pred¬ 
icated of a particular subject. (Japanese does not suffer the ambiguity of the 
term “subject” here as Germanic and Latin languages do, where the gram¬ 
matical subject is easily confused with the subject who makes the judg¬ 
ment.) Thus “The rose is red” is like a small galaxy with the rose at the cen¬ 
ter and redness revolving about it like a planet. Nishida interpreted Aris¬ 
totle’s logic of predication as focused on the subject, which provides a sta¬ 
ble center of gravity for its attributes and the comprehension of which 
grows as more and more attributes are given orbit about it. Nishida sought 
for his own logic the same solid foundation that Aristotle's “subject that 
could not become a predicate,” provided, but without the metaphysical 
nuisance of “substance.” To do so, he reversed the emphasis by following 
the predicates. In other words, he shifted his attention away from expand¬ 
ing description or analysis of the object to releasing predication from the 
subject-object framework in order to see where the process itself takes 
place.” 

As reported by his students, he would then draw a second circle on the 
blackboard surrounding the first, opening the field for other predicating 
judgments. The galaxy of particular judgments is now seen to rest in a larger 
universe where the original, grammatical subject has forfeited its position 
of centrality to the thinking subject who makes the judgment in the first 
place. This is the locus of reflective consciousness. It is not the world; nor is 
it even experience of the world. It is the consciousness where judgments 



370 


JAPAN 


about the world are located—indeed where all attempts to know and con¬ 
trol reality by locating it within the limits of the thinking processes of 
human beings find their homeground. 

The predicate “red” is no longer bound to some particular object, and 
particular objects are no longer limited by their satellite attributes or the 
language that encases them. Everything is seen as relative to the process of 
constructing the world in mind. The move to this wider circle shows judg¬ 
ment to be a finite act within a larger universe of thinking. 

This gives rise to the next question: And just where is this consciousness 
itself located? If mind is a field of circumstances that yield judgments, what 
are the circumstances that define mind? To locate them deeper within the 
mind would be like Baron Munchausen pulling himself out of the swamp 
by his own pigtail. Recourse to the idea of a higher subject for which ordi¬ 
nary consciousness is an object is a surrender to infinite regress. Still, if the 
notions of subject and object only set the boundaries for conscious judg¬ 
ment, this does not preclude the possibility of a still higher level of aware¬ 
ness that will envelop the realm of subjects and objects. 

To show this, Nishida drew another circle about the first two, a broad one 
with broken lines to indicate a location unbounded and infinitely expand¬ 
able (though not, of necessity, infinitely expanded), a place he called “noth¬ 
ingness. This was his absolute, deliberately so named to replace the 
a solute of being in much Western philosophy. Being, for Nishida, cannot 
e a solute because it can never be absolved from the relationships that 
ne it. The true absolution had to be—as the Japanese glyphs zettai indi¬ 
te cut off from any and every “other.” Absoluteness precludes all 

subject and object, all bifurcation of one thing from another, 
all individuation of one mind or another. 

is defined by its unboundedness, this place of absolute nothingness 
f lAlf ° CUS r ° 1 sa * vat i° n > °f deliverance from time and being. It is the 
ment o t e philosophical-religious quest where the action of intuition 
sciousness take place without an acting subject and in the immedi- 
^ c mornent > where the self working on the world yields to a pure 

, 4 ^- ° aS lt lS ' * C iS moment of enlightenment that is right at 

an in t e ere an -now, all-at-once-ness of experience. The final circle is 
t us on e w ose circumference is nowhere and whose center can be any- 

W L CrC ; C lma &^ was ta ken from Cusanus, but the insight behind it was 
there in Nishida from the start. 

In fact, over the years Nishida employed a number of idioms to express 
sel f- awa ren ess at the locus of absolute nothingness, among them: “appro- 
priation, acting intuition, seeing without a seer,” and “knowing a thing 




PHILOSOPHY AS SPIRITUALITY 


371 


by becoming that thing.” In his early writings he is somewhat inhibited by 
Neo-Kantian epistemological conundrums, but he advances steadily to an 
integrated view ol how consciousness takes shape, with a Hegelian empha¬ 
sis on its embeddedness in the historical praxis of a bodily agent. He comes 
to see knowing not as the activity of a self-empowered subject but as “act¬ 
ing intuition” in which the very idea of the subject grasping objects has 
been superseded. This intuition is no longer a spying on reality as the ulti¬ 
mate “other,” but a participation in the self-actualization of reality itself. In 
other words, awareness of the unbounded, absolute character of nothing¬ 
ness which arises out of reflection on immediate experience is not meant to 
detach the subject from the real world but to insinuate its presence still 
deeper there. “True reality,” he writes, “is not the object of dispassionate 
knowing— Without our feelings and will, the actual world ceases to be a 
concrete fact and becomes mere abstract concept.” 7 

This idea of participating in reality by overcoming the subject-object 
dichotomy was given logical form by Nishida in a deliberately ambivalent 
formula that can be read “an absolute self-identity of contradictories or a 
self-identity of absolute contradictories.” The Japanese apposition allows for 
both and he made free use of the double-entendre , depending on whether he 
wished to stress the radical nature of the identity achieved or the radical 
opposition of the elements that go into the identity. A further ambiguity in 
the formula, less transparent in the texts, is the qualification of the identi¬ 
ty as a j^-identity. For one thing, the identity is automatic. It is not induced 
from without, nor is it forced on a stubborn, resistant reality. It takes place 
when the limitations of the narrow circles of subject-predicate and subject- 
object are overcome. Here “identity” refers to the way reality is, minus the 
interference of reflective mind, and the way the mind is when lit up by real¬ 
ity. At the same time, the true identity of reality is not independent of that 
of the true, awakened self. It is not that the self is constructed one way and 
the world another; or that the deepest truth of the self is revealed by 
detaching itself from the world. The apparently absolute opposition 
between the two is only overcome when the individual is aware that “every 
act of consciousness is a center radiating in infinity ” 8 —that is, out into the 
circumferenceless circle of nothingness. 

In all these reflections Nishida is pursuing a religious quest, a summation 
of which he attempted in a rambling final essay, “The Logic of Locus and a 
Religious Worldview.” We see Nishida, on the one hand, at pains to clarify 
the roots of his logic of locus in Buddhist thought; on the other, to clarify 
his understanding of religion as not bound to any particular historical tra¬ 
dition. Religion is not ritual or institution, or even morality. It is “an event 



372 


JAPAN 


of the soul” which the discipline of philosophy can enhance, even as religion 
helps philosophy find its proper place in history. This “place” is none other 
than the immediacy of the moment in which consciousness sees itself as a 
gesture of nothingness within the world of being. For consciousness does 
not see reality from without, but is an act of reality from within and there¬ 
fore part of it. This is the fountainhead of all personal goodness, all just soci¬ 
eties, all true art and philosophy and religion for Nishida. 


Absolute Nothingness 

Nishida s idea of absolute nothingness, which was later to be taken up and 
developed by Tanabe and Nishitani each in his own way, is not a mere gloss 
on his logic of locus. His descriptions of historical praxis as “embodying 
absolute nothingness in time,” 9 and religious intuition as “penetrating into 
the consciousness of absolute nothingness” 10 are intended to preserve the 
experiential side of the logic and at the same time to assert a distinctive 
metaphysical position. But at a more basic level, the idea of nothingness 
itself is the stumbling block for philosophies which consider being as the 
most all-encompassing qualification of the real, and which see nothingness 
aS C ^ c * ass of everything excluded from reality. 

n is search for the ultimate locus of self-awakening—the point at which 
a lty recognizes itself, through the enlightened consciousness of the 
man individual, as relative and finite—Nishida could not accept the idea 
su P re me being of ultimate power and knowledge beside which all else 
unb n ° , m ? re . C ^ an a P a ^ e analogy. He conceived of his absolute as an 
k e - n ° Ur L,/“ circumstance rather than as an enhanced form of ordinary 
had b C ^° CUS . being in reality could not itself be another being; it 
was b° C SOmet ^ n £ that encompassed being and made it relative. Being 
with one S a ^ 0rm c °dependency, a dialectic of identities at odds 

other ^ ^ e ^ nin & one another by each setting itself up as non- 

Only a p S t C t L° ta ^ t ^ suc h things, being could not be an absolute, 

of f u _ ?j t . t e ^-embracing infinity of a nothingness could the totality 
of Che world which beings m0 ve exist at all. 

p-jon ; n ^^ s ^ lc ^ a ^cognized that “God is fundamental to reli- 

rehVin 0rm ‘ ^is left him with two options: either to redefine what 
r i ’ ! particularly Christianity, calls God as absolute nothingness; or 

. I ° W e a ^ so ^ ute being is relative to something more truly 

, 1S 1 a ° Un ^ a c bird way: he took both options. Nishida’s God 
a so ute eing -in- absolute nothingness.” The copulative in here 
meant to signal a relationship of affirmation-in-negation (the so-called 





PHILOSOPHY AS SPIRITUALITY 


373 


logic of soku-hi which Nishida seems to owe more to D. T. Suzuki than to 
the Buddhist sources on which Suzuki drew). The two terms are bound to 
one another by definition. In the same way that there cannot be a creator 
without creatures, or sentient beings without a Buddha, Nishida writes, 
there cannot be an absolute being without an absolute nothingness. On the 
one hand, he insists that the absolute is “truly absolute by being opposed 
to absolutely nothing.” On the other, “the absolute is not merely non- 
relative_It must relate to itself as a form of self-contradiction. 12 

Even his clearest remarks in this regard are something of a logical tangle 
and continue to perplex his commentators. 13 Insofar as I have been able to 
understand the texts, Nishida’s reluctance to absorb God without remain¬ 
der into absolute nothingness seems to stem from his need to preserve the 
element of pure experience in awakened selfhood. Metaphysically, he 
refused to pronounce on God’s nature or existence. But “dropping off body 
and mind to be united with the consciousness of absolute nothingness 14 is 
also a religious act, and one that transforms perception to “see eternity in 
the things of everyday life.” As such, it is an engagement of one’s truest, 
deepest self with a radical, absolute otherness. Nishida recognized this basic 
“spiritual fact” to be the cornerstone of religion, articulated in God-talk or 
Amida-talk as nowhere else in philosophical history. In other words, if the 
absolute in itself is “absolved’’ of all dependence on the relative, there is yet 
a sense in which the absolute for us must be nearer to our true selves than 
anything else can be. The very nature of absolute nothingness was bound to 
this contradiction: “In every religion, in some sense, God is love. 15 It is also 
the point at which logic must finally yield to experience, and hence where 
Nishida’s perplexing prose can best be read as a philosopher’s bow to religion. 

Clearly Nishida’s notion of absolute nothingness is different from the 
“beyond being” ( eji'e/cEiva njs ovoia ?) of classical negative theology. If any¬ 
thing, his idea of locating nothingness absolutely out of this world of being 
may be seen as a metaphysical equivalent of locating the gods in the heav¬ 
ens. His point was not to argue for an uncompromising transcendence of 
ultimate reality, but to establish a ground for human efforts at self-control, 
moral law, and social communion that will not cave in when the earth 
shakes with great change or life is visited by great tragedy. True, the per¬ 
sonal dimension of the divine-human encounter (and its reflection in Chris- 
tological imagery) is largely passed over in favor of an abstract notion of 
divinity not so very different from the God of the philosophers that Pascal 
rejected. In general, Nishida alludes to God as an idiom for life and cre¬ 
ativity minus the connotations of providence and subjectivity. But for one 
so steeped in the Zen Buddhist perspective as Nishida to have given God 



374 


JAPAN 


such a prominent place in his thought proved to be a decisive ingredient in 
opening Kyoto-school philosophy to the world. 

On the whole, Nishida’s “orientalism” is restrained to an ancillary role in 
his philosophy. Zealous disciples, less secure in their philosophical vocation 
and lacking Nishida s religious motivation, have been preoccupied with 
finding in him a logic of the East distinct from that of the West. Nishida 
himself did not go so far. Rarely, if ever, does he set himself or his ideas up 
as alternative or even corrective to “Western philosophy” as a whole. He 
was making a contribution to world philosophy and was happy to find affil¬ 
iates and sympathetic ideas, hidden or overt, in philosophy as he knew it.' 

That said, his attempts to return the true self awakened to absolute noth¬ 
ingness to the world of historical praxis rarely touch down on solid ground. 
Even the most obvious progression from family to tribe to nation to world 
is given little attention. In principle he would hardly have rejected such an 
expansion of the self (though it must be said that during the war years, he 
came dangerously close to describing Japanese culture as a kind of self- 
enc osed world with the emperor as the seal of its internal identity). But this 
was not his primary focus, and in fact he never found a way to apply his 
search for the ultimate locus of the self to the pressing moral demands of 
The bulk of his reflections on the historical world concerns general, 
uctures of human acting and knowing in time rather than the relation of 
p cu ar nations and cultures to universal world order. The attainment of 
true self ultimately lies beyond history; it happens in the “eternal now.” 

■ [ C most ^ mrne diate existential fact of the I-Thou relationship is 

„ . , Ce . virtuall y w khout ethical content into the abstract logic of the 

entity of opposites in which the I discovers the Thou at the bottom 
own interiority. These questions provided the starting point for the 
contributions of Nishitani and Tanabe. 


Tanabe Hajime: Locating Absolute Nothingness in Historical Praxis 

any of the young intelligentsia of his generation, Tanabe was attract- 

C Trr ^ an< ^ ori S inalit y of Nishida’s thinking. But his was a tem- 
perament 1 erent from Nishida's. His writings show a more topical flow 
o ideas and a passion for consistency that contrasts sharply with Nishida’s 
tive eaps o imagination. If Nishida’s prose is a seedbed of suggestive¬ 
ness w lere one needs to read a great deal and occasionally wander off 
etween t e ines to see where things are going, Tanabe’s is more like a 
mathematical calculus where the surface is complex but transparent. Nishi- 
a s wor , it has been said, is like a single essay, interrupted as often by the 




PHILOSOPHY AS SPIRITUALITY 


375 


convention of publishing limits or deadlines as by the end of a thesis. One 
problem flows into the next, not in the interests of a unified system of 
thought but in pursuit of clarity about the matter at hand. Tanabe—and 
for that matter, Nishitani also—were more thematic and produced essays 
that can stand on their own and be understood as such. 

When Meiji Japan opened its doors to the world in the mid-nineteenth 
century after two hundred years of cloister, it immediately-inherited intel¬ 
lectual fashions that had been nurtured during the European enlighten¬ 
ment and the explosion of modern science. Not having been part of the 
process, Japan was ill-prepared to appropriate its results critically. That the 
road should have been a bumpy one, very different both from the West and 
from its Asian neighbors, is understandable. As Japan was going through 
its restoration to the community of nations, the countries of Europe were 
struggling with the idea of national identity. National flags, songs, and 
other more ritual elements aside, we find for the first time a widespread 
concern with distinctive national literatures and philosophies, along with 
national psychologies. The human sciences, all in their infancy, were caught 
up in this fascination even as they tried to monitor it. While the cosmopol¬ 
itan spirit of the enlightenment struggled to survive this test of its roots, 
the natural sciences and technology proudly marched in the van of a 
transnational, transcultural humanity. Throughout it all, Japan swayed 
back and forth between a total infatuation with the superior advances of 
Western culture and a rigid determination to carve out for itself a unique 
position in the world. 

Nishida suffered this ambiguity as a man of his age. 'While he never 
sought translation of his thought into foreign languages, he did recognize 
the need for ties with the contemporary world of philosophical thinkers. To 
this end, Tanabe was sent by Nishida to study in Europe, where word of 
Nishida’s work had already stirred interest. Whereas Nishida could calmly 
pen German phrases here and there in his diaries and skim through English 
and French books without the fear of criticism at home, the young Tanabe 
had to struggle with the daily life of a foreigner clumsily making his way in 
a tongue and culture he had so far only admired from a distance. In the 
course of time, a certain resentment seems to have built up in him over 
Nishida’s insistence that he pursue neo-Kantian thought. His own interests 
turned him in the direction of phenomenology, but on returning to Japan 
he was met with a request of Nishida for a major paper on Kant for a col¬ 
lection celebrating the two hundredth anniversary of the latter s death. Its 
composition was a turning point for Tanabe. 

In his essay Tanabe argued that Kant’s third Critique lacked an important 



376 


JAPAN 


ingredient that Nishida s philosophy could supply. Specifically, he tried to 
wed the idea of self-awakening to Kant’s practical reason in order to shift 
the foundations of morality away from a universal moral will in the direc¬ 
tion of absolute nothingness. On the one hand, he saw that awareness of 
nothingness could provide moral judgment with a telos outside of subjec¬ 
tive will. This “finality of self-awareness,” as he termed it, could provide “a 
common principle for weaving history, religion, and morality into an insol¬ 
uble relationship with one another. On the other hand, it dawned on him 
that Nishida’s true, awakened self effectively cut the individual off from 
history. On completion of his essay, he turned to Hegel to fill the gap. In 
time he realized that Hegel’s absolute knowledge was lacking content, and 
he set out to think through the possibility of praxis in the historical world 
grounded in the self-awareness of absolute nothingness. Nishida, for his 
part, was hard at work on his logic of locus, but Tanabe was not persuaded 
t at it would solve his problem. During this period he developed his dialec- 
c of absolute mediation as a way of establishing the bond between 
absolute nothingness and the historical world . 16 

hilosophical questions aside, two things should be noted with regard to 
I e ^ attem pts to draw the philosophical vocation closer to the histori- 
xj. , .^ r * ^ rst °f a ll, the tendency to be abstract that Tanabe criticized in 
rec a Ver ^ muc ^ ^is own problem. In fact, on his own account he 
ness^^ ^ aw * n m y speculative powers” as responsible for his abstract- 
no y ; Tanabe S & en * us > as apparent as it was to his students, was 

took an C ° r C e overwhelming presence of Nishida, towards whom he 
i t y er more critical position even as he continued to measure his own 
qnnr?l° P ^ pr °£ ress as a Japanese working primarily with Western 
, h S agam ^ Nlshida ’ s contributions. As Nishitani recalls, the dialectic 
j i S a van ^ ln g seems to give us a mirror-image of Tanabe himself 

e y struggling to escape the embrace of Nishida’s philosophy .” 18 


Absolute Nothingness and the Logic of the Specific 

On the occasion of Nishida’s retirement, when the academic world was pil- 
I r eS ° n * ts ^ rst and greatest world philosopher, Tanabe wrote a 

xj- i -i g l plGC j e devious ly entitled “Looking Up to Nishida.” Leaving 
tv’ TT t0 1S . °^ C l ocus > Tanabe (who now held Nishida’s chair at 
yoto niversity) prepared the way for his own “logic of the specific” by 
p esting t at the religious experience that goes by the name of the ‘self- 
a ening o a solute nothingness ... belongs outside the practice and 
anguage o p i osophy, which cannot put up with such a complete lack of 




PHILOSOPHY AS SPIRITUALITY 


377 


conceptual definition.... Religious self-awareness must not be set up as the 
ultimate principle of philosophy .” 19 

The religious bent in Nishida’s philosophy was fed by his many years of 
sitting in zazeii and his ongoing contact with Buddhist and Christian 
thinkers. Tanabe’s religiosity was more bookish. No less than Nishida, he 
shied away from turning the philosopher’s trade against organized religion 
and tried to get to the heart of religious and theological thinkers, but his 
religiosity was a more solitary one. No diaries and few letters remain to let 
us suppose otherwise. The irony is that Tanabe is remembered as the more 
religious figure because of a postwar book on penitential philosophy in 
which he criticizes the profession he had devoted his life to, himself includ¬ 
ed, for its moral timidity. 

Tanabe’s contribution to Kyoto-school philosophy as a religious way, as I 
have said, cannot be separated from his uneasy relationship with Nishida, 
which stimulated him to look closely at some of the questions Nishida had 
skimmed over in his creative flights and which also gave him the founda¬ 
tions for doing so. From Nishida he received the idea of approaching reli¬ 
gious judgments in terms of affirmation-in-negation, as well as the convic¬ 
tion of absolute nothingness as the supreme principle of philosophy. Fur¬ 
ther, like Nishida, he did not consider anything in Japanese language or 
thought a final measure of what was most important in his philosophy. 
These attitudes he passed on, passionately, to the students. Finally, like 
Nishida he never argued for the supremacy of any one religious way over 
any other. What he did not take from Nishida, however, was a conviction 
of the primacy of religious experience as an “event of the soul which phi¬ 
losophy may or may not try to explain but can never generate. For Tanabe, 
there is no unmediated religious experience. Either it is appropriated by the 
individual in an “existentially philosophic” manner or it yields to the 
specificity of theology, ecclesial institution, or folk belief . 20 

Tanabe’s search for his own philosophical position began with a meticu¬ 
lous rethinking of Hegel’s dialectic as applied to a philosophy of absolute 
nothingness. Along the way he became convinced that for nothingness to be 
absolute, it was not enough for it to serve as a principle of identity for the 
finite world from a position somewhere outside of being. It must be a dyna¬ 
mic force that sustains the relationships in which all things live and move 
and have their being. He could not accept the idea that the historical world 
in which opposites struggle with one another to secure their individual 
identities is being driven inexorably towards some quiet, harmonious, beatific 
vision in absolute mind; neither could he feel at home in the private awaken¬ 
ing to a true self within. Precisely because all things without exception are 



34. Nishida Kitaro, age 46 (1916). 






PHILOSOPHY AS SPIRITUALITY 


379 


made to struggle with one another for their individuality, the dialectic is an 
absolute fact of being cannot be accounted for within the world of being 
alone. Only a nothingness outside of being can make things be the essen¬ 
tially interactive things that they are. But the reverse is also true: “Insofar 
as nothingness is nothingness, it is incapable of functioning on its own. 
Being can function only because it is not nothingness .” 21 

If nothingness allows the world to be, awakening to this fact serves as a 
permanent critical principle in all identity, whether in the sense of a lofty 
philosophical principle like Nishida’s self-identity of absolute contradicto¬ 
ries or in the sense of the ordinary psychological self-composure of the indi¬ 
vidual mind. It is the fire in which all identity is purged of the fictions of 
individuality and substantiality that mind attaches to it, leaving only the 
pure awakening to that which has itself no conflict, no otherness: nothing¬ 
ness. This purification of the mind was Tanabe’s test of religious truth. In 
its terms he appreciated the great figures of the Buddhist and Christian 
religious past. 

The logic of the specific is testimony to the fact that Tanabe never made 
peace with his own tendency to distance himself from the historical world 
in the way Nishida did. Many of the latter’s young disciples had turned the 
sharp analysis of Marxism against Nishida’s fixation on self-awareness, but 
to little avail. Tanabe, in contrast, from his critical reading of Kant, had 
come to see that the subject of consciousness is not a mere individual who 
looks at the world through lenses crafted by nature for the mind without 
consultation. It is also a by-product of specific cultural, ethnic, and epochal 
conditions. In its purgative function, the awareness of absolute nothingness 
demands that even our most treasured theories be seen as bundles of rela¬ 
tionships not within our control. We cannot speak without a specific lan¬ 
guage nor think without circumstances with a history. We are not individ¬ 
uals awakening to universal truths, but stand forever on specificity, a great 
shifting bog of bias and unconscious desire beyond the capacity of our mind 
to conquer once and for all. Nothingness sets us in the mire, but it moves 
us to struggle against it—never to be identified with it, never to assume we 
have found an identity of absolute contradictories that is not contaminated 
by specificities of history. This “absolute negation” is the goal of religion . 22 

Philosophical Metanoia 

The problem for Tanabe was to salvage a meaning for self-awakening in this 
logic of the specific and not resign oneself to the cunning of history. It was 
not a lesson he taught himself in the abstract but rather one that was forced 


380 


JAPAN 


on him by his own injudicious—and probably also unnecessary—support of 
state ideology at the height of Japan’s military escapades in Asia. The logic 
that he had shaped to expose the irrational element in social existence was 
now used to set up against the “clear-thinking gaze of existential philoso¬ 
phy” something more engaging: the “praxis of blessed martyrdom” in a 
“war of love.” Proclaiming the nation as the equivalent of Sakyamuni and that 
“participation in its life should be likened to the imitatio Christi ,” 23 Tanabe 
lost touch with the original purpose of his logic of the specific. 

While these sentiments frothed at the surface of Tanabe’s prose, a deep 
resentment towards the impotence of his own religious philosophy seethed 
within him, until in the end it exploded in the pages of his classic work Phil¬ 
osophy as Metanoetics. It was no longer enough to posit absolute nothingness 
as a supreme metaphysical principle grounding the world of being. It must 
be embraced, in an act of unconditional trust, as a force liberating the self 
from its native instinct to self-sufficiency. The notion of faith in Other- 
Power as expressed in the Kyogyoshinsho of Shinran (1 173—1262) gave Tanabe 
the basic framework for his radical metanoia and reconstruction of a phil¬ 
osophy from the ground up. 

It is no coincidence that the heaviest brunt of his penitential attack on 
overreliance on the power of reason fell on the head of Kant’s transcendental 
philosophy, but from there it reaches out to a reassessment of virtually all 
his major philosophical influences, from Hegel and Schelling to Nietzsche, 
Kierkegaard, and Heidegger. Woven into this critique is a positive and 
unabashedly religious insistence on what he calls “nothingness-in-love” or 
compassionate praxis in the historical world. The principal model for this 
ideal is the Dharmakara myth of ascent-in-descent in which the enlight¬ 
ened bodhisattva returns to the world in order to certify his own awakening, 
but frequent mention is also made of the Christian archetype of life-in-death, 
which was to dominate certain of his later works. 24 In any case, his aim was 
not to promote any particular religious tradition over any other but to bridge 
the gap between absolute nothingness and concrete reality in a way that a 
simple leap of self-awareness could not accomplish. He drew on religious 
imagery because it seemed to keep him focused on the moral obligation of 
putting the truth of enlightened mind to work for the sake of all that lives. 

As it turned out, the purgative, “disruptive” side of his metanoetics over¬ 
shadowed the practical, moral side and left him on shaky ground when it 
came to taking his new “philosophy that is not a philosophy” beyond its ini¬ 
tial statement. Tanabe was aware of this, and devoted his late years to rein¬ 
forcing the foundations of his logic of the specific, fusing elements from 
Zen, Christianity, and Pure Land in the forge of a loving, compassionate 




PHILOSOPHY AS SPIRITUALITY 


381 


self-awakening. But when all was said and done, Tanabe, like Nishida, 
remained aloof from the concrete problems of science, technology, economic 
injustice, and international strife that were shaking the foundations of the 
historical world outside the walls of his study. His was to the end a philos¬ 
ophy committed to uncluttering the mind of its self-deceptions, but forever 
haunted by the knowledge that only in the hopelessly cluttered specificity 
of history can moral praxis exert itself. The vision he left us is a portrait of 
his own struggles with the intellectual life: a seamless robe of ideals tattered 
by experience but not rent, whose weave remains a testimony to the 
weaver’s dedication to the philosophical vocation as a spiritual way. 

Nishitani Keiji: From Nihility to Nothingness 

With Nishitani, the philosophical current that flowed from Nishida 
through Tanabe spread out in fresh, new tributaries. Not only did he carry 
over Tanabe’s concern with historical praxis; he also drew the ties to Bud¬ 
dhism closer than either of his senior colleagues had done and closer, as 
well, to the lived experience of the philosophical quest. In addition, Nishi¬ 
tani took up in his philosophy two major historical problems, each pulling 
him in a different direction. He was preoccupied, on the one hand, with fac¬ 
ing the challenge that modern science brought to religious thinking; on the 
other, with establishing a place for Japan in the world. All of this combines 
to give his writing a wider access to the world forum. 

More than Nishida and Tanabe, Nishitani turned his thought on a world 
axis. He actively welcomed and encouraged contact with philosophers from 
abroad, and in his final years many a foreign scholar beat a path to his small 
home in Kyoto. 25 He, too, studied in Germany as Tanabe before him, and 
later was to travel to Europe and the United States to lecture. The happy 
combination of the publication of his major work, Religion and Nothingness, 
in English and German translation, the rising number of Western scholars 
with the skills to read fluently in the original texts, and the great human 
charm of Nishitani as a person, helped bring the work of the Kyoto philoso¬ 
phers to a wider audience. Still, given the trends in Continental and Amer¬ 
ican philosophy at the time this was happening, it was unsurprising that it 
was the theologians and Buddhologists who were most attracted to Nishi- 
tani’s work. Only after his death did neighboring Asian countries like 
Korea, Taiwan, and Hong Kong begin to show an interest in him and other 
of the Kyoto-school philosophers. But for all his cosmopolitan sentiments, 
Nishitani followed, his predecessors in showing favoritism towards the 
West—as had virtually all Japanese philosophers since the Meiji period. 



382 


JAPAN 


In defending himself against the Inquisition, Galileo presented what has 
become the central assumption of modern science. “I am not interested,” he 
said, "in how to go to heaven, but in how the heavens go.” This dichotomy 
was one that Nishitani never accepted. Not only had the West got it wrong 
in separating philosophy from religion, its separation of religious quest 
from tne pursuit of science also seemed to him fundamentally flawed. Any¬ 
thing that touches human existence, he insisted, had its religious dimen¬ 
sion. Science is always and ever a human enterprise in the service of some¬ 
thing more, but when the existential element is sacrificed to the quest for 
scientific certitude, what we call life, soul, and spirit—including God— 
find their home destroyed. Nishitani’s response was not to retreat into 
preoccupation with the true self, but to argue that only on the self’s true 
homeground do the concrete facts of nature "manifest themselves as they 
are, in their greater ‘truth’.” 26 

In Nishitani the concern with true self reaches its highest point in Kyoto 
p ilosophy. He saw this as the focal point of Nishida’s work and interpreted 
anabe s philosophy as a variation on that theme. In his own writings he 
rew to the surface, through textual allusions and direct confrontation with 
t e original texts, many of the Zen and Buddhist elements in Nishida’s 
^ VOr ‘ ^ Suzuki s efforts to broaden Zen through contact with Pure 

an Buddhism also reverberate in Nishitani’s writings, though not as 
cep y as they do in Tanabe s. In addition, he turned directly to Christian 

t eo ogy both for inspiration and to clarify his own position as distinct from 
the Christian one. 

P er ^ a P s the single greatest stimulus to Nishitani’s broadening of 
ishidas philosophical perspective was Nietzsche, whose writings were 
never far from his mind. The deep impression that Thus Spoke Zarathustra 
a made on him in his university years left him with doubts so profound 
at, in the end, only a combination of Nishida’s method and the study of 
en Buddhism was able to keep them from disabling him. As a scholar of 
[ osophy he had translated and commented on Plotinus, Aristotle, 
oe me Descartes, Schelling, Hegel, Bergson, and Kierkegaard—all of 
w °m e t their mark on his thought. But Nietzsche, like Eckhart, Dogen, 
^ \ an ' ^^-te, ^ en P oets > and the New Testament, he seems to have 
rea t rough the lenses of his own abiding spiritual questions, resulting in 
rca mgs of arresting power and freshness. 

The fundamentals of Nishitani’s own approach to the true self as a philo¬ 
sophical idea are set forth in an early book on "elemental subjectivity.” This 
term (which he introduced into Japanese from Kierkegaard) is not one that 
Nishida favored, but Nishitani’s aim is not substantially different from that 




PHILOSOPHY AS SPIRITUALITY 


383 


of his teacher: to lay the philosophical foundation for full and valid indi¬ 
vidual existence, which in turn would be the basis for social existence, cul¬ 
tural advance, and overcoming the excesses of the modern age. Written at 
the age of forty and under the strong influence of Nishida, the work con¬ 
tains in germ his own mature philosophy. 

As with Nishida, the Achilles’ heel of Nishitani’s highly individual 
approach to historical questions was its application to questions of world 
history. In the attempt to lend support during the war years to elements in 
the Navy and government who wanted to bring some sobriety to the mind¬ 
less antics of the Japanese Army in Asia, his remarks on the role of Japan¬ 
ese culture in Asia blended all too easily with the worst ideologies of the 
period, and the subtle distinctions that made all the difference to him as 
they did to Nishida and Tanabe caught up in the same maelstrom earn 
him little sympathy today in the light of subsequent events. Nishitani suf¬ 
fered a purge after the defeat of Japan and never returned to these ques¬ 
tions in print. While he continued to write on Japan and the culture of the 
East, he did so at a safe distance both from his own earlier opinions and 
from the relentless pummeling of Marxist critics. 


The Standpoint of Emptiness 

To Nishida’s logic of locus and Tanabe’s logic of the specific, Nishitani 
added what he called the standpoint of emptiness. He saw this standpoint 
not as a perspective that one can step into effortlessly, but the achievement 
of a disciplined and uncompromising encounter with doubt. The long 
struggle with nihilism that lay behind him was far from merely academic. 
As a young man, not yet twenty years of age, he had fallen into a deep 
despair in which “the decision to study philosophy was, melodramatic as it 
might sound, a matter of life and death for me.” 27 This was to be the very 
starting point for his description of the religious quest: We become aware 
of religion as a need, as a must for life, only at the level of life at which every¬ 
thing else loses its necessity and its utility.” 28 

For Nishitani, the senseless, perverse, and tragic side of life is an unde¬ 
niable fact. But it is more than mere fact; it is the seed of religious aware¬ 
ness. The meaning of life is thrown into question initially not by sitting 
down to think about it but by being caught up in events outside one s con¬ 
trol. Typically, we face these doubts by retreating to one of the available 
consolations—rational, religious, or otherwise—that all societies provide to 
protect their collective sanity. The first step into radical doubt is to allow 
oneself to be so filled with anxiety that even the simplest frustration can 



384 


JAPAN 


reveal itself as a symptom of the radical meaninglessness at the heart of all 
human existence. Next, one realizes that this sense of ultimate is still 
human-centered and hence incomplete. Now one gives oneself over to the 
cfoubt entirely, and the tragedy of human existence shows itself as a symp¬ 
tom of the whole world of being and becoming. At this point, Nishitani 
says, it is as if a great chasm had opened up underfoot in the midst of ordi¬ 
nary life, an "abyss of nihility.” 


Whole philosophies have been constructed on the basis of this nihility, 
and Nishitani threw himself heart and soul into the study of them, not in 
order to reject them but in order to find the key to what he called the "self¬ 
overcoming of nihilism. The awareness of nihility must be allowed to grow 
in consciousness until all of life is transformed into a great question mark. 
Only in this supreme act of negating the meaning of existence so radically 
that one becomes the negation and is consumed by it, can the possibility of 
a breakthrough appear. Deliverance from doubt that simply transports one 
out of the abyss of meaninglessness and back into a worldview where things 
make sense again, Nishitani protests, is no deliverance at all. The nihility 
itself, in the fullness of its negation, has to be faced squarely in order to be 
seen through as relative to human consciousness and experience. In this 
rmation, reality discloses its secret of absolute emptiness that restores 
II in his philosophical terms, “emptiness might be 

ca ed the field of ‘be-ification (lebtung) in contrast to nihility, which is the 
neld of nullification’ (Nichtung ).” 29 

her words, for Nishitani religion is not so much a search for the 
te as one of the items that make up existence, as an acceptance of the 
P "ss t at embraces this entire world of being and becoming. In that 
acceptance—a "full-bodied appropriation” (tainin )—mind lights up as 
ng t y as mind can. The reality that is lived and died by all things that 
e an P ass awa Y in the world is realized” in the full sense of the 
one s lares in reality and one knows that one is real. This is the stand¬ 
point of emptiness. 

use it is a standpoint, it is not a terminus ad quern so much as a ter- 
quo. t e inauguration of a new way of looking at the things of life, 
new way of valuing the world and reconstructing it. All of life becomes, 
he says a kind of “double-exposure” in which one can see things just as they 
re an at the same time see through them to their relativity and tran¬ 
sience. Far from dulling one’s critical senses, it reinforces them. To return to 
t ie case of science, from the standpoint of emptiness, the modern infatua¬ 
tion with explanation and fact is disclosed for what it is: a sanctification of 
the imperial ego that willingly sacrifices the immediate reality of its own 





PHILOSOPHY AS SPIRITUALITY 


385 


true self for the illusion of perfect knowledge and control. To personify or 
humanize the absolute, to rein it in dogmatically with even the most 
advanced apparatus and reliable theories, is at best a temporary cure to the 
perpetual danger of being overwhelmed by nihility. Only a mysticism of the 
everyday, a living-in-dying, can attune our existence to the empty texture 
of the absolutely real. 

In general, it may be noted, Nishitani favored the term emptiness (S. suny- 
ata) over Nishida’s “absolute nothingness,” in part because its correspon¬ 
ding Chinese glyph, the ordinary character for sky, captures the ambiguity 
of an emptiness-in-fullness that he intends. In this seeing that is at the same 
time a seeing-through, one is delivered from the centripetal egoity of the 
self to the centrifugal ex-stasis of the self that is not a self. This, for him, is 
the essence of religious conversion. 

In principle, Nishitani always insisted that conversion entails engage¬ 
ment in history. While he appreciated, and often repeated, the Zen Bud¬ 
dhist correlation of great doubt with great compassion (the Chinese glyphs 
for both terms are pronounced the same, daihi ), his late writings contain 
numerous censures of Buddhism for its “other-worldly refusal to enter into 
the affairs of human society,” for its “lack of ethics and historical conscious¬ 
ness,” and for its “failure to confront science and technology.’ 30 

In his principal philosophical discussions of history, however, Nishitani 
tends to present Christian views of history, both linear and cyclical, as a 
counterposition to the fuller Buddhist-inspired standpoint of emptiness 
despite the greater sensitivity of the former to moral questions. Emptiness 
or nothingness did not become full by bending time back on itself periodi¬ 
cally, like the seasons that repeat each year, or by providing an evolutionary 
principle that points to an end of time when all the frustrations of nihility will 
be overturned, as is the case in Christian eschatology. He envisaged deliv¬ 
erance from time as a kind of tangent that touches the circle of repetitive 
time at its outer circumference or cuts across the straight line of its forward 
progress. Like Nishida, he preferred the image of an “eternal now that 
breaks through both myths of time to the timelessness of the moment of 
self-awakening. What Christian theism, especially in its personalized image 
of God, gains at one moment in its power to judge history, it often loses at 
the next in its failure to understand the omnipresence of the absolute in all 
things. For Nishitani the standpoint of emptiness perfects the personal 
dimension of human life by the addition of the impersonal, non-differenti¬ 
ating love, which was none other than the very thing that Christianity 
reveres in the God who makes the sun to shine on the just and the unjust 
alike, and who empties himself kenotically in Christ. 31 Yet here again, we 



386 


JAPAN 


see Nishitani in later writings reappraising the I-Thou relationship and the 
interconnectedness of all things, even to the point of claiming that “the per¬ 
sonal is the basic form of existence. 

I*n the foregoing pages much has been sacrificed to brevity and a certain 
forced clarity of exposition. Perhaps only the askese of struggling with the 
original texts can give one a sense of the complexity of the Kyoto school 
thinkers. Philosophically, many problems remain with the “logics” of Nishi¬ 
da, Tanabe, and Nishitani. Some of them have been superseded by more 
recent philosophy; others will benefit from further study and comparison; 
still others are perennial. The task of formulating philosophical questions as 
religious ones belongs, 1 am convinced, among the latter. 


Notes 

1. Karl Jaspers, The Way to Wisdom (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1954), 
14. Translation adjusted. 

2. These two ideas are present from Nishida’s earliest writings. See his two brief 
essays on Bergson in Nishida Kitaro zenshu (hereafter NKZ) 1:317-27; The idea of 

appropnarion (jitoku) appears in An Inquiry into the Good , 5 1 (where it is trans- 
ated realizing with our whole being"). 

3. Nishitani, Nishida Kitaro , 55. 

n• °f the No Drama: The Major Treatises of Zeami , trans. by J. Thomas 

i *T CI ^x Yamazaki Masakazu (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), 
1 35 , 136 . 

5. This term is sometimes translated as "logic of topes," but the connections to 
nstotle which the term suggests seem to conflict with his own position, 
o. bee Kosaka Masaaki chosakushu 8:98-101. 

8 2L KZ see Inquiry into the Good , 49. 
has V* W'itin&y 34. In order to capture the philosophical sense, the translator 
a C , n , S °I? e llbertics w kh particular passages. A more literal translation was 
81-no by YuSa Michiko in The Eastern Buddhist 19:2 (1986) 1-29, 20/1 (1987) 

\j -T eX ' Ual re ^ crcnces to this idea may be found in Jacinto, La filosofia social de 
Nishida Kitaro, 208—12 

10. NKZ 5:182. 

11. Last Writings , 48. 

12. Last Writings, 68—69. 

ichi 3 T d hC Al° ng " Standin8 debates amon £ Takizawa Katsumi, Abe Masao, Yagi Sei- 
l an |zuki Ryomin over the reversibility or irreversibility of the relationship 
... ween °d and the self,-as well as the wider debate over the obscure notion of 
. m y erSe c ° rres pondence (gyakutaio) that appears in Nishida’s final essay, leave lit¬ 
tle hope of a final word on the subject. 

, • 5:177 * The allusion, of course, is to Dogen’s Genjokoan. 

15. NKZ 11:372, 454, 435. 




PHILOSOPHY AS SPIRITUALITY 


387 


16. Tanabe Hajime zenshu (hereafter THZ) 3:7, 78—81. 

17. THZ 3:76-77. 

18. Nishitani, Nish id a Kitard , 167. 

19. THZ 4:306, 318. 

20. THZ 8:257-38. 

21. THZ 7:261. 

22. THZ 6:147-53. 

23. THZ 7:24, 99. 

24. Regarding his relation to Christianity, Tanabe referred to himself in 1948 as 
a permanent Christian-in-the-making, ein werdender Christ who could never 
become ein gewordener Christ (THZ 10:260). The distinction is more commonly 
associated with Nishitani, who adopted it to describe his own sympathies with 
Tanabe’s position. 

25. See the special issue of The Eastern Buddhist devoted to the memory of Nishi¬ 
tani, 25:1 (1992). 

26. “Science and Zen,” The Buddha Eye , 120, 126. 

27. Nishitani Keiji chosakushu (hereafter NKC) 20:175—84. 

28. Religion and Nothingness , 3- 

29- Religion and Nothingness , 124. 

30. See NKC 17:141, 148-50, 154-55, 230-31. 

31. See especially Religion and Nothingness , ch. 2. 

32. NKC 24:109. 


Bibliography 
Primary Sources 

Franck, Frederick, ed. The Buddha Eye: An Anthology of the Kyoto School. New York. 
Crossroad, 1982. 

Jacinto Zavala, Agustin, ed. Textos de la filosofia japonesa rnodema (Zamora: El Cole- 
gio de Michoacan, 1995), vol. 1. 

Nishida Kitard zenshu (Collected works of Nishida Kitaro). 19 vols. Tokyo: Iwa- 
nami, 1978. 

Nishida Kitaro. An Inquiry into the Good. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1990. 

--. Last Writings: Nothingness and the Religious Worldview, trans. by David Dil- 

worth. Honolulu: University of Hawai'i Press, 1987. 

Nishitani Keiji chosakushu (Collected works of Nishitani Keiji). Tokyo: Sobunsha, 
1986-. 26 vols: to date. 

Nishitani Keiji. Religion and Nothingness. Berkeley: University of California Press, 

1982. 

-. The Self-overcoming of Nihilism. Albany: State University of New York 

Press, 1990. 

Ohashi Ryosuke, ed. Die Philosophic der Kyoto-Schule: Texte und Einfiihrung. 
Freiburg: Karl Alber, 1990. 

Tanabe Hajime zenshu (Collected works of Tanabe Hajime). 15 vols. Tokyo: Chiku- 
ma Shobo, 1964. 

Tanabe Hajime. Philosophy as Metanoetics. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986. 




388 


JAPAN 


Secondary Sources 

Heisig James W, and John Maraldo, eds. Rude Awakenings: Zen, the Kyoto School 
, ■ a ” d !l 3e Q“ estlon of Nationalism. Honolulu: University of Hawai'i Press, 1994- 

lacmm 7™<,lo 1 1935-1945- & 


j ~ ^ jonn M ar aJdo, cds. Rude Awaken mgs: 

larinrn 7 Q !/est 'on of Nationalism. Honolulu: University of Hav 
J I ZlV ri r Agustin, ed. U filosofia social cle Nishula Kitaru, 
mo a: El Coleg.o de Michoacan, 1995 vol 1 
Kosaka Masaaki chosaktishii. Tokyo: Risoshaj 1965 vol 8 

Unno 6 ’w neS ' D \ al Ti l ‘ k der absol, “ en Vemnttlung. Freiburg: Herder, 1984. 

Ph,losophy ofLhita,,i Ke,ji - Derke,ey: 

_ Un T;y T XTa S n U Hu n manides Pre^^O^’ ^ Phihs ^ ^ 

Nl thf£w2y Ta r n pA7 Ha | ime> '' “ Nlshltan ' Keiji," and "The Kyoto School" >" 

N ishida Ki^r^^M^or^a/I^sue^ 77 °^^ 0 ' ^ 

Nishitani Kciii • i r UC ' ^ astern Buddhist 28:2 (1995). 

ei, ‘ Mem0r,al Iss ^- The Eastern Buddhist 25:1 (1992). 









2022/12/15

自然体験がスピリチュアリティの醸成に及ぼす影響

_pdf

自然体験がスピリチュアリティの醸成に及ぼす影響
竒二 正彦 NPO法人生態教育センター/立教大学コミュニティ福祉学研究科*
嘉瀬 貴祥 立教大学現代心理学部
濁川 孝志 立教大学コミュニティ福祉学部
Effects of Nature Experience on the Formation of Human Spirituality
KIJI Masahiko
KASE Takayoshi
NIGORIKAWA Takashi
トランスパーソナル心理学/精神医学
原著論文 Vol.17, No.1, Mar, 2018, p.68-p.83
68
Ⅰ. 問題
第1節 現代日本が抱える心にまつわる諸
問題と求められるスピリチュアリ
ティの醸成
 我が国は第二次世界大戦の敗戦から、戦後し
ばらくは極端な食料難、物不足の時代を余儀な
くされた。しかし、高度経済成長期とともに復
興、発展をとげ、1965年の経済白書では「もは
や戦後ではない」と謳うほど豊かとなった。豊
かさを測る指標としてよく使われる、国内総生
産(Gross domestic product; 以下, GDPと略記)
で日本を見ると現在も第3位を維持し(総務省
統計局、2016)、治安に関しても、世界平和度
指数(Global peace index)において日本は162
カ国中第8位と、非常に安全な国であることが
わかる(Institute for Economics and Peace、2015)。
また平均寿命を見ても、男女を合わせると
日 本 は 世 界1位 に あ り、WHO(World Health
Organization, 2016 ; 以下, WHOと略記)は、日
本は総合的に見て世界で最も医療保険制度が
整っている国と報告している(安田, 2001;
WHO, 2016)。このように高度経済成長を果た
し、なおかつ安定成長を続けて来たことで、日
本国民は物的欠乏から解放され、様々な豊かさ
を獲得した。
 しかし一方で日本社会には、自殺、いじめ、
引きこもり、うつ病の増加、高齢者の孤独死な
ど解決の糸口が見いだせない様々な社会問題が
ある。これらの社会現象は、これまで我々が歩
んできた日常的な衣食住・蓄財に関わる欲望の
充足などの物質的な価値観ばかりが注目された
結果として起きているという指摘がある(PIL
研究会, 1993)。生活水準は向上し物質的欲求
は満たされつつある一方で、生きがい感や生き
る意味の喪失という新たな問題が浮上してきた
というのである。Kessler(2000)は、これらの
社会問題は、スピリチュアルな価値観が失われ
たことと無関係ではないと指摘する。特に現代
の若者においては、教育の中からスピリチュア
リティに関わる教材が意図的に排除された状態
にあるため、上記のような破壊的な行動を招く
温床になりやすいという。また大石・安川・濁
川(2008)も、こうした心の問題の多くはスピ
リチュアルな価値観の喪失と関係があると指摘
*〒352-8558 埼玉県新座市北野1-2-26 立教大学
 コミュニティ福祉学部 濁川研究室内 竒二正彦
自然体験がスピリチュアリティの醸成に及ぼす影響(竒二・嘉瀬・濁川)
69
している。
 更に、現代人の生活水準は向上し物質的欲求
は満たされつつある一方で、生きる意味や人生
の目的の喪失という問題が起こってきたという
指摘がある(佐藤, 1993)。ナチス・ドイツに
よる収容所での壮絶な体験を「夜と霧」に綴
り、ロゴセラピーを創始したオーストリアの精
神科医・心理学者のヴィクトール・フランクル
(2002)は、収容所における人権を無視した極
限の状況において、人間の生命力を支えたもの
は、「生きる意味」や「意味への意志」を持つ
か持たないかであったと説いた。林(2011)
は、現代的な文脈で考えた時、「生きる意味」
と「意味への意志」は「スピリチュアルな要
求」に置き換えることができると指摘する。
 生きる意味や目的意識が、人の健康と大きく
関係しているという指摘は、医療における
QOL(Quality of Life:生活(いのち)の質)
の議論にも見られる。藤井(2000)は、ガン患
者のQOLは、従来の要素として挙げられてき
た身体的、心理的、社会的領域だけでなく、ス
ピリチュアルな領域からも捉えた方が良いとい
う。実際、ガン患者の健康に関する調査では、
QOLの要素の一つである身体的領域のケアが
患者に与える影響より、スピリチュアルな領域
に対するケアの方が、患者の全体的QOLに与
える影響がはるかに大きかったという。
 このように、「現代人の心や行動」に関わる
社会問題の解決の一つとして、スピリチュアリ
ティの醸成は重要なテーマであると思われる。
第2節 スピリチュアリティの定義
 では、スピリチュアリティとはなんであろう
か。スピリチュアリティの意味や定義に関して
は、これまで多くの研究者によって議論されて
きた。しかし、これまでに統一された見解が得
られたとは言い難い。それらの諸説は、定義す
る研究者の背景、つまりは国籍、文化的背景、
歴史的背景、学問的背景など様々な要因の影響
を受け、それぞれ異なるものになっている(濁
川、2009)。
 しかし、多くの文献(上田, 2014; 弓山, 2010;
竹内, 2012; 伊田, 2004; 窪寺, 2004, 2008; 西平,
2007; 濁川・遠藤・満石, 2012)が、世界保健
機関(WHO)が1998年に行われた執行理事会
に お い て、 健 康 の 定 義 に ス ピ リ チ ュ ア ル
spiritualという言葉を入れる提案をしたことを
取り上げている。以下に提案された定義を記
す。
Health is a dynamic state of complete physical,
mental, spiritual and social well being and not
merely the absence of disease or infirmity.
(健康とは、完全な身体的、心理的、スピ
リチュアル及び社会的福祉のダイナミック
な状態であり、単に疾病又は病弱の存在し
ないことではない。)
 また、梶原(2014)によれば、スピリチュア
リティの語源は、スピリトゥス(spiritus)とい
うラテン語に由来する。このラテン語は、スピ
ロー(spiro)という「呼吸する」「生きている」
「霊感を得る」「風が吹く」などの意味を持つ動
詞に基づき、「呼吸や息」「いのち」「意識」「霊
感」「風」「香り」そして「霊」や「魂」を意味
する。また、スピリトゥス(spiritus)というラ
テン語は、歴史の中でキリスト教の影響を受け
ており、その影響は旧約聖書の創世記にさかの
ぼることができる。
 さらに、神学者である窪寺(2004)は、「ス
ピリチュアリティとは、人生の危機に直面して
『人間らしく』『自分らしく』生きるための『存
在の枠組み』『自己同一性』が失われたときに、
それらのものを自分の外の超越的なものに求め
たり、あるいは自分の内面の究極的なものに求
める機能である。」と定義する。つまり、スピ
日本トランスパーソナル心理学 / 精神医学会誌「トランスパーソナル心理学 / 精神医学」Vol.17, No.1, 2018 年
70
リチュアリティとは、精神的危機を乗り越える
ために、人間が生得的に持っている「機能」で
あるという。
 近年欧米では、「自分は既成宗教には属さな
いが、スピリチュアルなものは大切にしている
(I'm not religious but spiritual. )」という言葉が
よ く 聞 か れ る と い う( 大 柴, 2014)。 大 柴
(2014)は、こうした動きを、「『既成宗教』が
『組織の維持・管理』に力を注いでいるうちに、
人々はこの世の直中でしっかりと目を凝らして
冷静に現実を見極め、自らを生かし、自らの
『魂』を活性化させる『真のスピリチュアリ
ティ(霊性)』を求めているように私には思わ
れるのである。」と述べている。このように、
スピリチュアリティとは心の健康や安寧に大き
く関わる概念であると思われる。
第3節 スピリチュアリティと自然との関
わり
 スピリチュアリティという概念に関する先行
研究をみると、自然という言葉と関わっている
ことが見て取れる。
 医師である今西(2008)によると、スピリ
チュアリティには一般には大きく二つの側面が
あるという。1つは「自己存在の意識」、もう1
つは「自己を超越したものの存在の意識」であ
る。前者は生きていることの意味、生きる力、
幸福感などと結びつくものであり、後者はいく
ぶん宗教的な要素を含み、自己を取り巻く自然
や絶対的存在としての神などを意識し、自然に
対する畏敬や自然との共生などに関連している
という。
 和・廣野・遠藤・満石・濁川(2014)は、こ
れまでに我が国で開発された代表的なスピリ
チュアリティ測定尺度から、スピリチュアリ
ティの構成概念を整理した。その結果、日本人
が持つスピリチュアリティの概念構造として、
【他者とのつながり】、【自然との一体感】、【畏
敬の念】、【死を超えた希望】、【安心】、【物質主
義からの解放】、【自律】という7項目が抽出さ
れた。この研究の結果から、若者や中高年者に
共通する日本人が持つスピリチュアリティと
は、『人間が、幸福な生(価値ある人生)を全
うするために不可欠なものであり、【他者との
つながり】、【自然との一体感】、【畏敬の念】、
【死を超えた希望】、【安心】、【物質主義からの
解放】、【自律】に重きを置く価値観』という新
たな定義を見出した。
 伊田(2004)は、スピリチュアリティやスピ
リチュアルケアについての様々な論者の見解を
取り上げ、そこで取り上げられているスピリ
チュアリティの概念には様々な類似性があると
報告している。その類似性の一つを「つながり
の中の私」と呼び、「私」は自己(たましい、
内なる自己)、他者、超越者、そして自然との
相互作用を伴ったつながりであると捉えるもの
で、言い換えれば、全体の中の一部としての自
己存在に気づく視点である、と説く。
 中谷・島田・大東(2013)は、スピリチュア
リティの概念構造に関する研究において、キー
ワードを「スピリチュアリティ」「スピリチュ
アル」「覚醒」「危機」「クライシス」「概念」
「グリーフ」「悲嘆」「日本人」と設定して488件
の文献を抽出し、そこから「スピリチュアリ
ティの覚醒」というキーワードでさらに13件の
論文を抽出した。そして、このデータを分析し
た結果、「地球・自然・人とのつながりを感じ
る」という概念が挙げられた。その内容は、
「地球と自分とのつながりを感じる」、「自然と
私が一つになったような何とも表現できない状
態」、「全てが私とひとつになっているようなア
ウェアネスを感じる」、「自己と環境が統一体で
あるという感覚(自然との一体感)」、「死をも
超えた他者との関係(新しい存在と意味の回
復)」、「自分を超越する存在や力との関係にお
いて自己や周囲の人・環境について理解する」
自然体験がスピリチュアリティの醸成に及ぼす影響(竒二・嘉瀬・濁川)
71
であった。
 このように、多くの研究者がスピリチュアリ
ティの概念に「自然」が含まれていることを挙
げている。これらのことを考えると、スピリ
チュアリティと自然とは密接な関連性があるも
のと思われる。
第4節 スピリチュアリティの醸成と自然
体験に関する先行研究
 自然体験とスピリチュアリティに関する先行
研 究 を み る と、McDonald, Wearing, & Ponting
(2009)は、オーストラリアのビクトリア国立
公園において、公園の利用者が荒野においてど
のような至高体験をするのかを調べている。研
究方法は、国立公園に訪れた人に、滞在中にど
のような至高体験があり、その経験の意味や、
至高体験が起こった風景の説明などを自由記述
させたものであった。その結果、核となる以下
7つのテーマがみられた。①審美的な質、②距
離をとる(人間社会の圧力などから逃避する)、
③意味のある経験、④ピーク時の経験数(言及
された最高の経験は、荒野の中で経験された数
多くの肯定的で深遠な瞬間のほんの1つだっ
た)、⑤ワンネスとのつながり、⑥限界の克服
(溢れるエネルギー)、⑦意識の高まり(至高体
験の間または直後に、自分と世界と人生に関し
て深く理解することができた)。
Heintzman(2009)は、自然の中で実施する
レクリエーションと、スピリチュアリティとの
複雑な関係を説明する、経験的研究と理論モデ
ルについて検討しており、自然体験や被験者
の、様々な条件や構成要素が、スピリチュアル
な経験や幸福などにつながる可能性があること
を示唆している。
Piff, Dietze, Feinberg, Stancato, & Keltner
(2015)は、自然体験と畏敬の念との関係につ
いて検討している。その研究は、ユーカリの高
木が林立するキャンパスで実施された。被験者
を、1分間ユーカリの森を注視する群と、高い
建物を眺める群に分け、この瞬間的な経験が宗
教的援助行動のレベルに及ぼす影響を比較して
いる。その結果、森を注視する群と高い建物を
眺める群と比較して、森を注視する群に起こる
自然主義的な畏敬の念が、より宗教的援助行動
を強化し、自己に対する意識の高さを減少させ
たという。
 今西(2008)は、スピリチュアリティを高め
る前段階でリラクゼーション誘導を行うことが
有効であるといい、森林セラピーに注目する。
森林セラピー(森林浴、森林療法)とは、森林
という自然環境を利用した統合医療の一つであ
るが、リラクゼーションのためには、森林内に
ある森林揮発性物質(フィトンチッド)や緑の
癒し効果、自然(小川、風)の音などによる効
果が有効であるという。そして、森林セラピー
によって得られる効果として、今西はスピリ
チュアリティの向上を挙げている。
 また、中右・今西(2009)は、緑の療法的効
果(Ulrich, 1984)や、森林環境での免疫機能
の 向 上( 大 平・ 高 木・ 増 井・ 大 石・ 小 幡,
1999)、 ス ト レ ス の 軽 減(Hansmann, Hug, &
Seeland, 2007)が示された先行研究に注目し、
緑豊かな環境は人にとって生理学的、心理学的
に療法に適した環境であると考えられるとい
う。さらに、中右・今西は日本人のスピリチュ
アリティ観の共通項として、自然との対比にお
ける人の小ささや、自然への畏敬の念が挙げら
れること(田崎・松田・中根, 2001)、日本人
高齢者のスピリチュアリティの構成概念とし
て、「自然との融和」が挙げられること(竹
田・太湯, 2006)から、緑に触れることによ
り、スピリチュアリティの向上が期待できると
している。そして実際に、次世代型統合医療の
実践の場として、大阪府吹田市にある万博記念
公園を選んでいる。中右らによると、万博記念
公園を選んだ理由は、全面的に緑化された260
日本トランスパーソナル心理学 / 精神医学会誌「トランスパーソナル心理学 / 精神医学」Vol.17, No.1, 2018 年
72
ヘクタールの広大な敷地に森林や芝生など、多
様な緑地が整備されていること、また、多目的
ホールを併設した自然観察学習館などの屋内施
設がある点も、各種のプログラムを行うのに適
していたという。その結果、参加者の血液検査
からは、免疫力の向上が確認され、また参加者
の心理質問紙調査からは、QOLの向上が推察
された。さらに参加者からの感想からは、スピ
リチュアリティの向上の可能性が示唆されてい
る。
 濁川ら(2012)は、スピリチュアルな内容を
テーマにした講義を、緑豊かな場所で行なった
場合と、都市環境下にある大学のキャンパスで
行なった場合では、受講者のスピリチュアリ
ティへの影響に関して、どのような違いがある
か検討を試みた。その結果、自然環境下と都市
環境下にある大学のキャンパスで同じ授業を実
施したにもかかわらず、自然環境下で行なった
授業の受講者の方が、スピリチュアリティの涵
養がより促進されることを示した。
 ここまで議論してきたように、現代日本に山
積する、心に関わる社会問題を解決するために
は、スピリチュアリティの醸成が貢献する可能
性がある。そして、スピリチュアリティの概念
の中には自然という言葉が多く見られ、様々な
先行研究からもスピリチュアリティの醸成に関
わる一要因として、自然体験の存在が示唆され
ている。
Ⅱ.目的
 本研究の目的は、自然体験がスピリチュアリ
ティの醸成と関係するかどうかを検討するもの
である。しかし、先行研究では、それぞれの研
究者が自然体験の意味を設定しており、自然体
験の定義が明確ではない。環境教育辞典(日本
環境教育学会, 2013)には、『自然体験活動の
定義としては、1996年、文部省(当時)の研究
会が「青少年の野外教育の充実について(報
告)」の中で示した「自然の中で、自然を活用
して行われる各種活動であり、具体的には、
キャンプ、ハイキング、スキー、カヌーといっ
た野外活動、動植物や星の観察といった自然・
環境学習活動、自然物を使った工作や自然の中
での音楽会といった文化・芸術活動などを含ん
だ総合的な活動」という定義が広く知られてい
る。』とある。そこで、本研究においては、環
境教育辞典の自然体験活動の定義を参考に、4
泊5日の自然体験型合宿の中で、キャンプ、ハ
イキング、カヌーといった野外活動と、動植物
や星空の観察といった自然・環境学習活動等を
実施することとした。また、先行研究におい
て、自然体験の前後でどのような心理的な変化
が起こったのか、定量的な検討をしたものが少
な い。Heintzman(2009) に よ れ ば、 ス ピ リ
チュアリティと自然に基づいたレクリエーショ
ンの関係に関する研究の大部分は定性的である
ため、定性的な知見がより大きな集団に一般化
できるかどうかを判断するには、より定量的な
研究が必要であるという。そこで、本研究の研
究1において、スピリチュアリティの様々な構
成要素の中のどの側面が醸成されるのかを定量
的に検討することとした。Piff et al. (2015)、田
崎・松田・中根(2001)、竹田・太湯(2006)
などの研究を参考に、スピリチュアリティの構
成因子と思われる「自然との融和や一体感」
「畏敬や畏怖の念」「生きがい感」が自然体験に
よって醸成されるのではないかという仮説を立
てた。そして、それらの概念を含む尺度とし
て、日本人の青年層のスピリチュアリティを測
定する尺度Japanese Youth Spirituality Rating Scale
(JYS:濁川・満石・遠藤・廣野・和, 2016)を
使用した。すなわち、JYSで抽出された5つの
因子、①「自然との調和」、②「生きがい」、③
「見えない存在への畏怖」、④「先祖・ルーツと
の繋がり」、⑤「自律」が、短期間の自然体験
自然体験がスピリチュアリティの醸成に及ぼす影響(竒二・嘉瀬・濁川)
73
の前後で、どのように変化するのかを検討する
ことを目的とした。加えて、スピリチュアリ
ティに関連すると思われる「生きがい感」「精
神的健康度」についても同様の検討をすること
を目的とした。
 また、自然体験によってスピリチュアリティ
が醸成されやすい人と、そうでない人に、どの
ような違いがあるのかを検討した先行研究はあ
まり見られない。梅原(1989)によれば、かつ
て我々の祖先は、自然の中で生きとし生けるも
のと共存したことで、太陽に生命の再生を見、
動植物や無機物にまで人間と同じ霊の存在を認
めるというアニミズム思想を持っていた。ま
た、上田(2014)によると、現代日本における
スピリチュアリティの基層には、自然に対する
日本人の霊性観が存在し、自然界の見えない力
の威光は古代アニミズム信仰から現代に至るま
で受け継がれているという。そして、第3節で
取り上げた、和ら(2014)の研究における、日
本人のスピリチュアリティの概念の構成要素
「自然との一体感」の中には、「自然に対する感
受性」という概念が含まれている。これら3つ
の先行研究を踏まえて考えた時、自然体験の蓄
積や、自然に対する感受性、さらにスピリチュ
アリティの醸成の間には、何らかの関係が存在
する可能性がある。藤後・磯・坪井(2014)に
よれば、自然への感受性は、短時間で形成され
るものではなく、幼少期の経験量や経験の質に
由来する能力であるという。つまり、過去の自
然体験が多い者ほど、現在のスピリチュアリ
ティ傾向が高い可能性があることから、研究2
において、その検証を試みることを目的とし
た。